Results for 'Fixpoint'

54 found
Order:
  1. Fixpoint Semantics for Logic Programming A Survey.Melvin Fitting - unknown
    The variety of semantical approaches that have been invented for logic programs is quite broad, drawing on classical and many-valued logic, lattice theory, game theory, and topology. One source of this richness is the inherent non-monotonicity of its negation, something that does not have close parallels with the machinery of other programming paradigms. Nonetheless, much of the work on logic programming semantics seems to exist side by side with similar work done for imperative and functional programming, with relatively minimal contact (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  2. Fixpoints of models constructions.Sergei Tupailo - 2007 - Logique Et Analyse 50:63-78.
  3.  9
    Grounded fixpoints and their applications in knowledge representation.Bart Bogaerts, Joost Vennekens & Marc Denecker - 2015 - Artificial Intelligence 224 (C):51-71.
  4.  72
    Completeness for flat modal fixpoint logics.Luigi Santocanale & Yde Venema - 2010 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 162 (1):55-82.
    This paper exhibits a general and uniform method to prove axiomatic completeness for certain modal fixpoint logics. Given a set Γ of modal formulas of the form γ, where x occurs only positively in γ, we obtain the flat modal fixpoint language by adding to the language of polymodal logic a connective γ for each γΓ. The term γ is meant to be interpreted as the least fixed point of the functional interpretation of the term γ. We consider (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  5.  10
    Fixpoint semantics for active integrity constraints.Bart Bogaerts & Luís Cruz-Filipe - 2018 - Artificial Intelligence 255 (C):43-70.
  6.  5
    Revisiting the conservativity of fixpoints over intuitionistic arithmetic.Mattias Granberg Olsson & Graham E. Leigh - 2023 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 63 (1):61-87.
    This paper presents a novel proof of the conservativity of the intuitionistic theory of strictly positive fixpoints, $$\widehat{{\textrm{ID}}}{}_{1}^{{\textrm{i}}}{}$$ ID ^ 1 i, over Heyting arithmetic ($${\textrm{HA}}$$ HA ), originally proved in full generality by Arai (Ann Pure Appl Log 162:807–815, 2011. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.apal.2011.03.002). The proof embeds $$\widehat{{\textrm{ID}}}{}_{1}^{{\textrm{i}}}{}$$ ID ^ 1 i into the corresponding theory over Beeson’s logic of partial terms and then uses two consecutive interpretations, a realizability interpretation of this theory into the subtheory generated by almost negative fixpoints, and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  31
    Fixpoints Without the Natural Numbers.B. Banaschewski - 1991 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 37 (8):125-128.
  8.  24
    Fixpoints Without the Natural Numbers.B. Banaschewski - 1991 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 37 (8):125-128.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  16
    Non-deterministic approximation fixpoint theory and its application in disjunctive logic programming.Jesse Heyninck, Ofer Arieli & Bart Bogaerts - 2024 - Artificial Intelligence 331 (C):104110.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  8
    On independence-friendly fixpoint logics.J. C. Bradfield - 2004 - Philosophia Scientiae 8:125-144.
    Nous introduisons une extension aux points fixes de la logique IF (faite pour l’indépendance) de Hintikka et Sandu. Nous donnons des résultats sur sa complexité et son pouvoir expressif. Nous la relions aux jeux de parité à information imparfaite, et nous montrons une application à la définition d’un mu-calcul modal fait pour l’indépendance.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  11.  44
    On independence-friendly fixpoint logics.J. C. Bradfield - 2004 - Philosophia Scientiae 8 (2):125-144.
    Nous introduisons une extension aux points fixes de la logique IF (faite pour l’indépendance) de Hintikka et Sandu. Nous donnons des résultats sur sa complexité et son pouvoir expressif. Nous la relions aux jeux de parité à information imparfaite, et nous montrons une application à la définition d’un mu-calcul modal fait pour l’indépendance.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  12.  12
    Analyzing the computational complexity of abstract dialectical frameworks via approximation fixpoint theory.Hannes Strass & Johannes Peter Wallner - 2015 - Artificial Intelligence 226 (C):34-74.
  13.  6
    Embedding justification theory in approximation fixpoint theory.Simon Marynissen, Bart Bogaerts & Marc Denecker - 2024 - Artificial Intelligence 331 (C):104112.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  13
    Derived models of mice below the least fixpoint of the Solovay sequence.Dominik Adolf & Grigor Sargsyan - 2019 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 84 (1):27-53.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. A Program to Compute G¨odel-L¨ob Fixpoints.Melvin Fitting - unknown
    odel-L¨ ob computability logic. In order to make things relatively self-contained, I sketch the essential ideas of GL, and discuss the significance of its fixpoint theorem. Then I give the algorithm embodied in the program in a little more detail. It should be emphasized that nothing new is presented here — all the theory and methodology are due to others. The main interest is, in a sense, psychological. The approach taken here has been declared in the literature, more than (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16. A first order axiomatisation of least fixpoint on finite models.Jan van Eijck - unknown
    Let R be a relational variable of arity m, and let ¯ x be an m-tuple of variables. Let φ be a first order formula that is positive in R, i.e., all occurrences of R in φ are in the scope of an even number of negations. Then λRλ¯.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  5
    Review: Alfred Tarski, A Lattice-Theoretical Fixpoint Theorem and its Applications. [REVIEW]H. Gericke - 1957 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 22 (4):370-370.
  18.  16
    Tarski Alfred. A lattice-theoretical fixpoint theorem and its applications. Pacific journal of mathematics, Bd. 5 , S. 285–309. [REVIEW]H. Gericke - 1957 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 22 (4):370-370.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. Semantics, conceptual spaces, and the meeting of minds.Massimo Warglien & Peter Gärdenfors - 2013 - Synthese 190 (12):2165-2193.
    We present an account of semantics that is not construed as a mapping of language to the world but rather as a mapping between individual meaning spaces. The meanings of linguistic entities are established via a “meeting of minds.” The concepts in the minds of communicating individuals are modeled as convex regions in conceptual spaces. We outline a mathematical framework, based on fixpoints in continuous mappings between conceptual spaces, that can be used to model such a semantics. If concepts are (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  20. On modal μ -calculus and gödel-löb logic.Luca Alberucci & Alessandro Facchini - 2009 - Studia Logica 91 (2):145 - 169.
    We show that the modal µ-calculus over GL collapses to the modal fragment by showing that the fixpoint formula is reached after two iterations and answer to a question posed by van Benthem in [4]. Further, we introduce the modal µ~-calculus by allowing fixpoint constructors for any formula where the fixpoint variable appears guarded but not necessarily positive and show that this calculus over GL collapses to the modal fragment, too. The latter result allows us a new (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  21.  52
    Well-founded semantics for defeasible logic.Frederick Maier & Donald Nute - 2010 - Synthese 176 (2):243 - 274.
    Fixpoint semantics are provided for ambiguity blocking and propagating variants of Nute's defeasible logic. The semantics are based upon the well-founded semantics for logic programs. It is shown that the logics are sound with respect to their counterpart semantics and complete for locally finite theories. Unlike some other nonmonotonic reasoning formalisms such as Reiter's default logic, the two defeasible logics are directly skeptical and so reject floating conclusions. For defeasible theories with transitive priorities on defeasible rules, the logics are (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  5
    Introduction to Lattices and Order.B. A. Davey & H. A. Priestley - 2002 - Cambridge University Press.
    This new edition of Introduction to Lattices and Order presents a radical reorganization and updating, though its primary aim is unchanged. The explosive development of theoretical computer science in recent years has, in particular, influenced the book's evolution: a fresh treatment of fixpoints testifies to this and Galois connections now feature prominently. An early presentation of concept analysis gives both a concrete foundation for the subsequent theory of complete lattices and a glimpse of a methodology for data analysis that is (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   102 citations  
  23.  81
    Argument-based extended logic programming with defeasible priorities.Henry Prakken & Giovanni Sartor - 1997 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 7 (1-2):25-75.
    ABSTRACT Inspired by legal reasoning, this paper presents a semantics and proof theory of a system for defeasible argumentation. Arguments are expressed in a logic-programming language with both weak and strong negation, conflicts between arguments are decided with the help of priorities on the rules. An important feature of the system is that these priorities are not fixed, but are themselves defeasibly derived as conclusions within the system. Thus debates on the choice between conflicting arguments can also be modelled. The (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   87 citations  
  24.  38
    Generalized quantifiers and pebble games on finite structures.Phokion G. Kolaitis & Jouko A. Väänänen - 1995 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 74 (1):23-75.
    First-order logic is known to have a severely limited expressive power on finite structures. As a result, several different extensions have been investigated, including fragments of second-order logic, fixpoint logic, and the infinitary logic L∞ωω in which every formula has only a finite number of variables. In this paper, we study generalized quantifiers in the realm of finite structures and combine them with the infinitary logic L∞ωω to obtain the logics L∞ωω, where Q = {Qi: iε I} is a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  25. Kleene's logic, generalized.Melvin Fitting - unknown
    Kleene’s well-known strong three-valued logic is shown to be one of a family of logics with similar mathematical properties. These logics are produced by an intuitively natural construction. The resulting logics have direct relationships with bilattices. In addition they possess mathematical features that lend themselves well to semantical constructions based on fixpoint procedures, as in logic programming.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  26.  26
    On Modal μ-Calculus and Gödel-Löb Logic.Luca Alberucci & Alessandro Facchini - 2009 - Studia Logica 91 (2):145-169.
    We show that the modal µ-calculus over GL collapses to the modal fragment by showing that the fixpoint formula is reached after two iterations and answer to a question posed by van Benthem in [4]. Further, we introduce the modal µ~-calculus by allowing fixpoint constructors for any formula where the fixpoint variable appears guarded but not necessarily positive and show that this calculus over GL collapses to the modal fragment, too. The latter result allows us a new (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  27.  21
    Consistency of the intensional level of the Minimalist Foundation with Church’s thesis and axiom of choice.Hajime Ishihara, Maria Emilia Maietti, Samuele Maschio & Thomas Streicher - 2018 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 57 (7-8):873-888.
    Consistency with the formal Church’s thesis, for short CT, and the axiom of choice, for short AC, was one of the requirements asked to be satisfied by the intensional level of a two-level foundation for constructive mathematics as proposed by Maietti and Sambin From sets and types to topology and analysis: practicable foundations for constructive mathematics, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2005). Here we show that this is the case for the intensional level of the two-level Minimalist Foundation, for short MF, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28.  22
    Generalized Bosbach and Riečan states on nucleus-based-Glivenko residuated lattices.Bin Zhao & Hongjun Zhou - 2013 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 52 (7-8):689-706.
    Bosbach and Riečan states on residuated lattices both are generalizations of probability measures on Boolean algebras. Just from the observation that both of them can be defined by using the canonical structure of the standard MV-algebra on the unit interval [0, 1], generalized Riečan states and two types of generalized Bosbach states on residuated lattices were recently introduced by Georgescu and Mureşan through replacing the standard MV-algebra with arbitrary residuated lattices as codomains. In the present paper, the Glivenko theorem is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  29.  29
    Effective Cut-elimination for a Fragment of Modal mu-calculus.Grigori Mints - 2012 - Studia Logica 100 (1-2):279-287.
    A non-effective cut-elimination proof for modal mu-calculus has been given by G. Jäger, M. Kretz and T. Studer. Later an effective proof has been given for a subsystem M 1 with non-iterated fixpoints and positive endsequents. Using a new device we give an effective cut-elimination proof for M 1 without restriction to positive sequents.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30. On the Dynamic Logic of Agency and Action.Chrysafis Hartonas - 2014 - Studia Logica 102 (3):441-478.
    We present a Hilbert style axiomatization and an equational theory for reasoning about actions and capabilities. We introduce two novel features in the language of propositional dynamic logic, converse as backwards modality and abstract processes specified by preconditions and effects, written as \({\varphi \Rightarrow \psi}\) and first explored in our recent paper (Hartonas, Log J IGPL Oxf Univ Press, 2012), where a Gentzen-style sequent calculus was introduced. The system has two very natural interpretations, one based on the familiar relational semantics (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  52
    On Certain Quasivarieties of Quasi-MV Algebras.A. Ledda, T. Kowalski & F. Paoli - 2011 - Studia Logica 98 (1-2):149-174.
    Quasi-MV algebras are generalisations of MV algebras arising in quantum computational logic. Although a reasonably complete description of the lattice of subvarieties of quasi-MV algebras has already been provided, the problem of extending this description to the setting of quasivarieties has so far remained open. Given its apparent logical repercussions, we tackle the issue in the present paper. We especially focus on quasivarieties whose generators either are subalgebras of the standard square quasi-MV algebra S , or can be obtained therefrom (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  7
    A predicative variant of hyland’s effective topos.Maria Emilia Maietti & Samuele Maschio - 2021 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 86 (2):433-447.
    Here, we present a category ${\mathbf {pEff}}$ which can be considered a predicative variant of Hyland's Effective Topos ${{\mathbf {Eff} }}$ for the following reasons. First, its construction is carried in Feferman’s predicative theory of non-iterative fixpoints ${{\widehat {ID_1}}}$. Second, ${\mathbf {pEff}}$ is a list-arithmetic locally cartesian closed pretopos with a full subcategory ${{\mathbf {pEff}_{set}}}$ of small objects having the same categorical structure which is preserved by the embedding in ${\mathbf {pEff}}$ ; furthermore subobjects in ${{\mathbf {pEff}_{set}}}$ are classified by (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  64
    BDD-based decision procedures for the modal logic K ★.Guoqiang Pan, Ulrike Sattler & Moshe Y. Vardi - 2006 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 16 (1-2):169-207.
    We describe BDD-based decision procedures for the modal logic K. Our approach is inspired by the automata-theoretic approach, but we avoid explicit automata construction. Instead, we compute certain fixpoints of a set of types — which can be viewed as an on-the-fly emptiness of the automaton. We use BDDs to represent and manipulate such type sets, and investigate different kinds of representations as well as a “level-based” representation scheme. The latter turns out to speed up construction and reduce memory consumption (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  28
    Normalizable linear orders and generic computations in finite models.Alexei P. Stolboushkin & Michael A. Taitslin - 1999 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 38 (4-5):257-271.
    Numerous results about capturing complexity classes of queries by means of logical languages work for ordered structures only, and deal with non-generic, or order-dependent, queries. Recent attempts to improve the situation by characterizing wide classes of finite models where linear order is definable by certain simple means have not been very promising, as certain commonly believed conjectures were recently refuted (Dawar's Conjecture). We take on another approach that has to do with normalization of a given order (rather than with defining (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  72
    Algebraic and topological semantics for inquisitive logic via choice-free duality.Nick Bezhanishvili, Gianluca Grilletti & Wesley H. Holliday - 2019 - In Rosalie Iemhoff, Michael Moortgat & Ruy de Queiroz (eds.), Logic, Language, Information, and Computation. WoLLIC 2019. Lecture Notes in Computer Science, Vol. 11541. Springer. pp. 35-52.
    We introduce new algebraic and topological semantics for inquisitive logic. The algebraic semantics is based on special Heyting algebras, which we call inquisitive algebras, with propositional valuations ranging over only the ¬¬-fixpoints of the algebra. We show how inquisitive algebras arise from Boolean algebras: for a given Boolean algebra B, we define its inquisitive extension H(B) and prove that H(B) is the unique inquisitive algebra having B as its algebra of ¬¬-fixpoints. We also show that inquisitive algebras determine Medvedev’s logic (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  36.  29
    How to define a linear order on finite models.Lauri Hella, Phokion G. Kolaitis & Kerkko Luosto - 1997 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 87 (3):241-267.
    We carry out a systematic investigation of the definability of linear order on classes of finite rigid structures. We obtain upper and lower bounds for the expressibility of linear order in various logics that have been studied extensively in finite model theory, such as least fixpoint logic LFP, partial fixpoint logic PFP, infinitary logic Lω∞ω with a finite number of variables, as well as the closures of these logics under implicit definitions. Moreover, we show that the upper and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  37.  15
    準無矛盾論理に基づく議論フレームワーク.高橋 武久 梅田 勇一 - 2004 - Transactions of the Japanese Society for Artificial Intelligence 19:83-94.
    Argumentation is the most representative of intelligent activities of humans. Therefore, it is natural to think that it could have many implications for artificial intelligence and computer science as well. Specifically, argumentation may be considered a most primitive capability for interaction among computational agents. In this paper we present an argumentation framework based on the four-valued paraconsistent logic. Tolerance and acceptance of inconsistency that this logic has as its logical feature allow for arguments on inconsistent knowledge bases with which we (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  14
    A notation system for ordinal using ψ‐functions on inaccessible mahlo numbers.Helmut Pfeiffer & H. Pfeiffer - 1992 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 38 (1):431-456.
    G. Jäger gave in Arch. Math. Logik Grundlagenforsch. 24 , 49-62, a recursive notation system on a basis of a hierarchy Iαß of α-inaccessible regular ordinals using collapsing functions following W. Buchholz in Ann. Pure Appl. Logic 32 , 195-207. Jäger's system stops, when ordinals α with Iα0 = α enter. This border is now overcome by introducing additional a hierarchy Jαß of weakly inaccessible Mahlo numbers, which is defined similarly to the Jäger hierarchy. An ordinal μ is called Mahlo, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  28
    An infinite-game semantics for well-founded negation in logic programming.Chrysida Galanaki, Panos Rondogiannis & William W. Wadge - 2008 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 151 (2-3):70-88.
    We present an infinite-game characterization of the well-founded semantics for function-free logic programs with negation. Our game is a simple generalization of the standard game for negation-less logic programs introduced by van Emden [M.H. van Emden, Quantitative deduction and its fixpoint theory, Journal of Logic Programming 3 37–53] in which two players, the Believer and the Doubter, compete by trying to prove a query. The standard game is equivalent to the minimum Herbrand model semantics of logic programming in the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  40.  29
    Locales, Nuclei, and Dragalin Frames.Guram Bezhanishvili & Wesley Holliday - 2016 - In Lev Beklemishev, Stéphane Demri & András Máté (eds.), Advances in Modal Logic, Volume 11. London: College Publications. pp. 177-196.
    It is a classic result in lattice theory that a poset is a complete lattice iff it can be realized as fixpoints of a closure operator on a powerset. Dragalin [9,10] observed that a poset is a locale (complete Heyting algebra) iff it can be realized as fixpoints of a nucleus on the locale of upsets of a poset. He also showed how to generate a nucleus on upsets by adding a structure of “paths” to a poset, forming what we (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  21
    Towards incorporating background theories into quantifier elimination.Andrzej Szalas - 2008 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 18 (2-3):325-340.
    In the paper we present a technique for eliminating quantifiers of arbitrary order, in particular of first-order. Such a uniform treatment of the elimination problem has been problematic up to now, since techniques for eliminating first-order quantifiers do not scale up to higher-order contexts and those for eliminating higher-order quantifiers are usually based on a form of monotonicity w.r.t implication (set inclusion) and are not applicable to the first-order case. We make a shift to arbitrary relations “ordering” the underlying universe. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Determined game logic is complete.Jan van Eijck - unknown
    Non-determined game logic is the logic of two player board games where the game may end in a draw: unlike the case with determined games, a loss of one player does not necessarily constitute of a win of the other player. A calculus for non-determined game logic is given in [4] and shown to be complete. The calculus adds a new rule for the treatment of greatest fixpoints, and a new unfolding axiom for iterations of the universal player. The technique (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. A note on the completeness of Kozen's axiomatisation of the propositional μ-calculus.Igor Walukiewicz - 1996 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 2 (3):349-366.
    The propositional μ -calculus is an extension of the modal system K with a least fixpoint operator. Kozen posed a question about completeness of the axiomatisation of the logic which is a small extension of the axiomatisation of the modal system K. It is shown that this axiomatisation is complete.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. On polynomial time computation over unordered structures.Andreas Blass, Yuri Gurevich & Saharon Shelah - 2002 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 67 (3):1093-1125.
    This paper is motivated by the question whether there exists a logic capturing polynomial time computation over unordered structures. We consider several algorithmic problems near the border of the known, logically defined complexity classes contained in polynomial time. We show that fixpoint logic plus counting is stronger than might be expected, in that it can express the existence of a complete matching in a bipartite graph. We revisit the known examples that separate polynomial time from fixpoint plus counting. (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  45.  13
    Semantic Games for Algorithmic Players.Emmanuel Genot & Justine Jacot - unknown
    We describe a class of semantic extensive entailment game with algorithmic players, related to game-theoretic semantics, and generalized to classical first-order semantic entailment. Players have preferences for parsimonious spending of computational resources, and compute partial strategies, under qualitative uncertainty about future histories. We prove the existence of local preferences for moves, and strategic fixpoints, that allow to map eeg game-tree to the building rules and closure rules of Smullyan's semantic tableaux. We also exhibit a strategy profile that solves the (...) selection problem, and can be mapped to systematic constructions of semantic trees, yielding a completeness result by translation. We conclude on possible generalizations of our games. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46.  22
    Deciding the unguarded modal -calculus.Oliver Friedmann & Martin Lange - 2013 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 23 (4):353-371.
    The modal -calculus extends basic modal logic with second-order quantification in terms of arbitrarily nested fixpoint operators. Its satisfiability problem is EXPTIME-complete. Decision procedures for the modal -calculus are not easy to obtain though since the arbitrary nesting of fixpoint constructs requires some combinatorial arguments for showing the well-foundedness of least fixpoint unfoldings. The tableau-based decision procedures so far also make assumptions on the unfoldings of fixpoint formulas, e.g., explicitly require formulas to be in guarded normal (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  7
    Semantic games for first-order entailment with algorithmic players.Emmanuel Genot & Justine Jacot - unknown
    If semantic consequence is analyzed with extensive games, logical reasoning can be accounted for by looking at how players solve entailment games. However, earlier approaches to game semantics cannot achieve this reduction, by want of explicitly dened preferences for players. Moreover, although entailment games can naturally translate the idea of argumentation about a common ground, a cognitive interpretation is undermined by the complexity of strategic reasoning. We thus describe a class of semantic extensive entailment game with algorithmic players, who have (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  59
    Model checking for hybrid logic.Martin Lange - 2009 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 18 (4):465-491.
    We consider the model checking problem for Hybrid Logic. Known algorithms so far are global in the sense that they compute, inductively, in every step the set of all worlds of a Kripke structure that satisfy a subformula of the input. Hence, they always exploit the entire structure. Local model checking tries to avoid this by only traversing necessary parts of the input in order to establish or refute the satisfaction relation between a given world and a formula. We present (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49.  32
    Classical Fω, orthogonality and symmetric candidates.Stéphane Lengrand & Alexandre Miquel - 2008 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 153 (1-3):3-20.
    We present a version of system Fω, called image, in which the layer of type constructors is essentially the traditional one of Fω, whereas provability of types is classical. The proof-term calculus accounting for the classical reasoning is a variant of Barbanera and Berardi’s symmetric λ-calculus.We prove that the whole calculus is strongly normalising. For the layer of type constructors, we use Tait and Girard’s reducibility method combined with orthogonality techniques. For the layer of terms, we use Barbanera and Berardi’s (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  36
    Consistency Defaults.Paolo Liberatore - 2007 - Studia Logica 86 (1):89-110.
    A consistency default is a propositional inference rule that asserts the consistency of a formula in its consequence. Consistency defaults allow for a straightforward encoding of domains in which it is explicitely known when something is possible. The logic of consistency defaults can be seen as a variant of cumulative default logic or as a generalization of justified default logic; it is also able to simulate Reiter default logic in the seminormal case. A semantical characterization of consistency defaults in terms (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 54