Homeschooling, freedom of conscience, and the school as republican sanctuary: An analysis of arguments representing polar conceptions of the secular state and religious neutrality

Dissertation, University of Jyväskylä (2016)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

This paper examines how stances and understandings pertaining to whether home education is civically legitimate within liberal democratic contexts can depend on how one conceives normative roles of the secular state and the religious neutrality that is commonly associated with it. For the purposes of this paper, home education is understood as a manifestation of an educational philosophy ideologically based on a given conception of the good. Two polar conceptions of secularism, republican and liberal-pluralist, are explored. Republican secularists declare that religious expressions do not belong in the public sphere and justify this exclusion by promoting religious neutrality as an end in itself. But liberal-pluralists claim that religious neutrality is only the means to ensure protection of freedom of conscience and religion, which are moral principles. Each conception is associated with its own stance on whether exemptions or accommodations on account of religious beliefs have special legal standing and thereby warranted. The indeterminate nature of religion and the allegedly biased exclusion of secular beliefs, cited by some when denying religious exemptions, can be overcome by understanding all religious and conscientious beliefs as having equal standing as conceptions of the good. Analysis of court documents from the Uwe Romeike et al asylum case are guided by these understandings, and relationships among themes are explored. In summary, any stance regarding home education may depend on one’s view of secularism, particularly in relation to whether one views religious neutrality as a means to ensure protection of freedom of conscience or an end in itself.

Similar books and articles

The Right to Religious Education in Lithuania.Birutė Pranevičienė & Agnė Margevičiūtė - 2012 - Jurisprudencija: Mokslo darbu žurnalas 19 (2):443-458.
Why Tolerate Conscience?François Boucher & Cécile Laborde - forthcoming - Criminal Law and Philosophy:1-21.
The secular and secularisms.José Casanova - 2009 - Social Research: An International Quarterly 76 (4):1049-1066.
Religious Freedom in Theory and Practice.Jonathan Fox - 2015 - Human Rights Review 16 (1):1-22.
Alternative Burdens on Freedom of Conscience.Adam J. Kolber - 2010 - San Diego Law Review 47:919-934.
Is There a Human Right to Freedom of Religion?Paul Tiedemann - 2015 - Human Rights Review 16 (2):83-98.
Academic Freedom and Religiously Affiliated Universities.Liviu Andreescu - 2008 - Journal for the Study of Religions and Ideologies 7 (19):162-183.
Why Tolerate Conscience?François Boucher & Cécile Laborde - 2016 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 10 (3):493-514.
Rethinking the Comparative Study of Religious Ethics.David Little - 2015 - Journal of Religious Ethics 43 (3):525-542.
Freedom of Religion.Avihay Dorfman - 2008 - Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 21 (2):279-319.
Justice in education and religious freedom.Jon Mahoney - 2014 - Social Philosophy and Policy 31 (1):276-294.
Reclaiming the secular and the religious: The primacy of religious autonomy.Michael W. McConnell - 2009 - Social Research: An International Quarterly 76 (4):1333-1344.

Analytics

Added to PP
2016-10-29

Downloads
899 (#16,048)

6 months
295 (#7,410)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Paul Oh
University of Jyväskylä

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

A Theory of Justice: Revised Edition.John Rawls - 1999 - Harvard University Press.
Political Liberalism.J. Rawls - 1995 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 57 (3):596-598.
Liberalism and the Limits of Justice.Michael J. Sandel - 1982 - New York: Cambridge University Press.

View all 33 references / Add more references