Irony, Disruption and Moral Imperfection

Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 23 (3):545-559 (2020)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Irony has a suspicious moral reputation, especially in popular media and internet culture. Jonathan Lear (2011) introduces a proposal which challenges this suspicion and identifies irony as a means to achieve human excellence. For Lear, irony is a disruptive uncanniness which arises from a gap between aspiration and actualisation in our practical identity. According to Lear, such a disruptive experience of ironic uncanniness reorients us toward excellence, because it passionately propels us to really live up to that practical identity. However, Lear’s understanding of irony is idiosyncratic and his proposal overlooks that disruption often results from value incompatibility between different practical identities. The disruption which follows from value incompatibility does not inherently reorient us toward excellence. The point is exactly that achieving excellence in one practical identity is sometimes incompatible with excellence in the other. Pace Lear, I do not identify this disruptive experience as a central example of irony. Instead, I consider irony a virtuous coping strategy for such disruption, because it introduces the necessary distance from our moral imperfection to sustain practical deliberation and maintain good mental health. Such virtuous irony negotiates a golden mean between too little disruption (complete insensitivity toward one’s imperfection) and too much disruption (a complete breakdown of practical deliberation and mental health). I argue that ironic media in popular culture provide a rich source of such virtuous irony, which I demonstrate through analysis of satirical examples.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,423

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Making Peace with Moral Imperfection.Camil Golub - 2019 - Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 16 (2).
Kierkegaard on Mastered Irony.Brad Frazier - 2004 - International Philosophical Quarterly 44 (4):465-479.
What God Does Not Possess: Moses Mendelssohn’s Philosophy of Imperfection.Dustin Noah Atlas - 2019 - Journal of Jewish Thought and Philosophy 27 (1):26-59.
Morals and Their Ironies.Ruth L. Smith - 1998 - Journal of Religious Ethics 26 (2):367 - 388.
Irony and Shame in Socratic Ethics.Julie Piering - 2010 - International Philosophical Quarterly 50 (4):473-488.
Moral Imperfection and Moral Phenomenology in Kant.Benjamin Lipscomb - 2010 - In Benjamin J. Bruxvoort Lipscomb & James Krueger (eds.), Kant's Moral Metaphysics: God, Freedom, and Immortality. de Gruyter. pp. 49.
Kierkegaard on the Problems of Pure Irony.Brad Frazier - 2004 - Journal of Religious Ethics 32 (3):417 - 447.

Analytics

Added to PP
2020-07-20

Downloads
23 (#668,995)

6 months
8 (#346,782)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Citations of this work

Existential Aesthetics.Hans Maes - 2022 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 80.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity.Richard Rorty - 1989 - The Personalist Forum 5 (2):149-152.
The mess inside: narrative, emotion, and the mind.Peter Goldie - 2012 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Ruling Passions.Simon Blackburn - 1998 - Philosophy 75 (293):454-458.
Meaning and relevance.Deirdre Wilson & Dan Sperber - 2012 - New York: Cambridge University Press. Edited by Dan Sperber.

View all 26 references / Add more references