Music, Geometry, and the Listener: Space in The History of Western Philosophy and Western Classical Music

Abstract

This thesis is directed towards a philosophy of music by attention to conceptions and perceptions of space. I focus on melody and harmony, and do not emphasise rhythm, which, as far as I can tell, concerns time rather than space. I seek a metaphysical account of Western Classical music in the diatonic tradition. More specifically, my interest is in wordless, untitled music, often called 'absolute' music. My aim is to elucidate a spatial approach to the world combined with a curiosity about the nature of the Pythagorean intervals. Thus one question I seek to answer is: What do the Pythagorean intervals import to music? In their original formulation by Pythagoras, and further, by Plato, their import seemed mystical and analogous to a 'harmony of the spheres.' In this spatial approach, the Pythagorean intervals are indicative of infinite depth. The faculty of hearing alone does not ordinarily spatially locate sources. Hearing is ordinarily combined with sight in order to spatially locate a sound. Yet we talk about music as if it were spatially located, that is, as if it were a visible object with a surface and themes or 'objects'. I explore the faculty of vision and consider in what ways the processes of vision might be similar to and distinct from audition. My source for this approach is David Marr's book 'Vision' and his theory of the 2 1/2-dimensional sketch. In a medium in which there is no spatial location, it is important to situate the listener. Newton solved the problem of location by demonstrating the effects of gravity. P. F. Strawson claims that an analogy of distance is required in hearing to situate the listener, that is, a sense of nearer to and further from a source or object that permits a perception of distance. I claim that in music, the key signature and the scalar relations of musical themes provide this analogy of distance. The works of Plato, Aristotle, Descartes, Leibniz, and Newton are studied for their accounts of motion, bodies, and space. From these metaphysicians can be gleaned elements of music that include form, motion, timbre, dynamics, and attraction. By incorporating motion, I aim to show that although we may not know the true nature of space, we can learn from hearing music that space is perceptible in other than three dimensions

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,503

External links

  • This entry has no external links. Add one.
Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

  • Only published works are available at libraries.

Similar books and articles

Music.Nicholas Cook - 2010 - New York, NY: Sterling.
Moribund music: can classical music be saved?Carolyn Beckingham - 2009 - Portland: Sussex Academic Press.
Musical Understandings: And Other Essays on the Philosophy of Music.Stephen Davies - 2011 - Oxford, GB: New York;Oxford University Press.
Philosophy and music.Jerrold Levinson - 2009 - Topoi 28 (2):119-123.
The language of music.Deryck Cooke - 1959 - New York: Oxford University Press.
The second sense: language, music, & hearing.Robin Maconie - 2002 - Lanham, Md.: Scarecrow Press.
Music and the aural arts.Andy Hamilton - 2007 - British Journal of Aesthetics 47 (1):46-63.
The science of music.Robin Maconie - 1997 - New York: Oxford University Press.
Music & meaning.Jenefer Robinson (ed.) - 1997 - Ithaca [N.Y.]: Cornell University Press.

Analytics

Added to PP
2015-12-03

Downloads
10 (#1,184,994)

6 months
1 (#1,472,167)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

No references found.

Add more references