Switch to: References

Citations of:

Why favour simplicity?

Analysis 65 (3):205-210 (2005)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Oversimplification: A reply to white.Nathan Robert Smith - 2008 - Analysis 68 (2):161–168.
  • Oversimplification: a reply to White.Nathanrobert Smith - 2008 - Analysis 68 (2):161-168.
  • Moderate monism and modality.Harold W. Noonan - 2008 - Analysis 68 (1):88-94.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Normativity in the Philosophy of Science.Marie I. Kaiser - 2019 - Metaphilosophy 50 (1-2):36-62.
    This paper analyzes what it means for philosophy of science to be normative. It argues that normativity is a multifaceted phenomenon rather than a general feature that a philosophical theory either has or lacks. It analyzes the normativity of philosophy of science by articulating three ways in which a philosophical theory can be normative. Methodological normativity arises from normative assumptions that philosophers make when they select, interpret, evaluate, and mutually adjust relevant empirical information, on which they base their philosophical theories. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Structure and Dynamics of Scientific Theories: A Hierarchical Bayesian Perspective.Leah Henderson, Noah D. Goodman, Joshua B. Tenenbaum & James F. Woodward - 2010 - Philosophy of Science 77 (2):172-200.
    Hierarchical Bayesian models (HBMs) provide an account of Bayesian inference in a hierarchically structured hypothesis space. Scientific theories are plausibly regarded as organized into hierarchies in many cases, with higher levels sometimes called ‘paradigms’ and lower levels encoding more specific or concrete hypotheses. Therefore, HBMs provide a useful model for scientific theory change, showing how higher‐level theory change may be driven by the impact of evidence on lower levels. HBMs capture features described in the Kuhnian tradition, particularly the idea that (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • Ramsey + Moore ≠ God.David Barnett - 2008 - Analysis 68 (2):168 - 174.
    Frank Ramsey writes: If two people are arguing ‘if p will q?’ and both are in doubt as to p, they are adding p hypothetically to their stock of knowledge and arguing on that basis about q. We can say that they are fixing their degrees of belief in q given p. (1931) Chalmers and Hájek write: Let us take the first sentence [of Ramsey] the way it is often taken, as proposing the following test for the acceptability of an (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Our Reliability is in Principle Explainable.Dan Baras - 2017 - Episteme 14 (2):197-211.
    Non-skeptical robust realists about normativity, mathematics, or any other domain of non- causal truths are committed to a correlation between their beliefs and non- causal, mind-independent facts. Hartry Field and others have argued that if realists cannot explain this striking correlation, that is a strong reason to reject their theory. Some consider this argument, known as the Benacerraf–Field argument, as the strongest challenge to robust realism about mathematics, normativity, and even logic. In this article I offer two closely related accounts (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Complexity unfavoured.Alan Baker - 2008 - Analysis 68 (1):85–88.