Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. How to Refer to a Thing by a Word: Another Difference Between Dignāga’s and Kumārila’s Theories of Denotation.Kiyotaka Yoshimizu - 2011 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 39 (4-5):571-587.
    In studies of Indian theories of meaning it has been standard procedure to examine their relevance to the ontological issues between Brahmin realism about universals and Buddhist nominalism. It is true that Kumārila makes efforts to secure the real existence of a generic property denoted by a word by criticizing Dignāga, who declares that the real world consists of absolutely unique individuals. The present paper, however, concentrates on the linguistic approaches Dignāga and Kumārila adopt to deny or to prove the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • History in the Abstract: ‘Brahman-ness’ and the Discipline of Nyāya in Seventeenth-Century Vārāṇasī.Samuel Wright - 2016 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 44 (5):1041-1069.
    Over the last fifteen years, studies on Sanskrit intellectual history between the fifteenth and eighteenth centuries have produced a body of scholarship that has fundamentally reshaped our understanding of the period. Yet, despite significant advances in the understanding of the social-historical circumstances of authors and disciplines as well as success in elucidating major features of intellectual thought, a main point of difficultly has been in combining both the intellectuality and sociality of Sanskrit scholars. By examining a debate within the discipline (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Controversial Provision for the Nominative Ending: Nominal Sentences and Aṣṭādhyāyī 2.3.46.Davide Mocci & Tiziana Pontillo - 2022 - Journal of the American Oriental Society 140 (1):47.
    The present joint contribution offers a tentative comprehensive re-interpretation of Pāṇini’s rule A 2.3.46, and shows how that rule teaches the application of the nominative ending without making use of the notion of “subject,” a notion that belongs to other grammatical systems, but not to Pāṇini’s. We discuss the controversial domain of some segments of its wording by attempting to adhere to Pāṇini’s framework and his usus scribendi. In particular, we read the first constituent of the compound prātipadikārtha­ liṅgaparimāṇavacana­ as (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Unraveling the Kāvyaprakāśa: Jayadeva Pīyūṣavarṣa’s idiosyncratic sequence of topics in the Candrāloka.David Mellins - 2007 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 35 (3):227-251.
    In his twelfth century alaṃkāraśāstra, the Candrāloka, Jayadeva Pīyūṣavarṣa reverses the sequence of topics found in Mammaṭa’s Kāvyapr-akāśa, an earlier and immensely popular work. With such a structural revisionism, Jayadeva asserts the autonomy of his own work and puts forth an ambitious critique of earlier approaches to literary analysis. Jayadeva investigates the technical and aesthetic components of poetry in the first part of the Candrāloka, prior to his formal semantic investigations in the latter half of the text, thus suggesting that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Traditionalism and Innovation: Philosophy, Exegesis, and Intellectual History in Jñānaśrīmitra’s Apohaprakaraṇa. [REVIEW]Lawrence J. Mccrea & Parimal G. Patil - 2005 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 34 (4):303-366.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • (Close) the Door, the King (Is Going): The Development of Elliptical Resolution in Bhāṭṭa Mīmāṃsā.Malcolm Keating - 2017 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 45 (5):911-938.
    This paper examines three commentaries on the Śabdapariccheda in Kumārila Bhaṭṭa’s Ślokavārttika, along with the the seventeenth century Bhāṭṭa Mīmāṃsā work, the Mānameyodaya. The focus is the Mīmāṃsā principle that only sentences communicate qualified meanings and Kumārila’s discussion of a potential counter-example to this claim–single words which appear to communicate such content. I argue that there is some conflict among commentators over precisely what Kumārila describes with the phrase sāmarthyād anumeyetvād, although he is most likely describing ellipsis completion through arthāpatti. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Precision in Philosophy.Sven Ove Hansson - 2012 - Theoria 78 (4):273-275.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Language and testimony in classical indian philosophy.Madhav Deshpande - forthcoming - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Kumārila.Daniel Arnold - 2010 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Cow is to be Tied Up: Sort-Shifting in Classical Indian Philosophy.Keating Malcolm - 2013 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 30 (4):311-332.
    This paper undertakes textual exegesis and rational reconstruction of Mukula Bhaṭṭa’s Abhidhā-vṛttta-mātṛkā, or “The Fundamentals of the Communicative Function.” The treatise was written to refute Ānandavardhana’s claim, made in the Dhvanyāloka, that there is a third “power” of words, vyañjanā (suggestion), beyond the two already accepted by traditional Indian philosophy: abhidhā (denotation) and lakṣaṇā(indication).1 I argue that the explanation of lakṣaṇā as presented in his text contains internal tensions, although it may still be a compelling response to Ānandavardhana.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations