Results for 'Bernard J. Baars'

(not author) ( search as author name )
1000+ found
Order:
  1. A Cognitive Theory of Consciousness.Bernard J. Baars - 1988 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Conscious experience is one of the most difficult and thorny problems in psychological science. Its study has been neglected for many years, either because it was thought to be too difficult, or because the relevant evidence was thought to be poor. Bernard Baars suggests a way to specify empirical constraints on a theory of consciousness by contrasting well-established conscious phenomena - such as stimulus representations known to be attended, perceptual, and informative - with closely comparable unconscious ones - (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   542 citations  
  2. Attention, self, and conscious self-monitoring.Bernard J. Baars - 1998 - In A Cognitive Theory of Consciousness. Cambridge University Press.
    ?In everday language, the word ?attention? implies control of access to consciousness, and we adopt this usage here. Attention itself can be either voluntary or automatic. This can be readily modeled in the theory. Further, a contrastive analysis of spontaneously self?attributed vs. self?alien experiences suggests that ?self? can be interpreted as the more enduring, higher levels of the dominant context hierarchy, which create continuity over the changing flow of events. Since context is by definition unconscious in GW theory, self in (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  3. How conscious experience and working memory interact.Bernard J. Baars & Stan Franklin - 2003 - Trends in Cognitive Sciences 7 (4):166-172.
  4. In the Theater of Consciousness: The Workspace of the Mind.Bernard J. Baars - 1997 - New York: Oxford University Press USA.
    The study of conscious experience has seen remarkable strides in the last ten years, reflecting important technological breakthroughs and the enormous efforts of researchers in disciplines as varied as neuroscience, cognitive science, and philosophy. Although still embroiled in debate, scientists are now beginning to find common ground in their understanding of consciousness, which may pave the way for a unified explanation of how and why we experience and understand the world around us. Written by eminent psychologist Bernard J. (...), In the Theater of Consciousness: The Workspace of the Mind brings us to the frontlines of this exciting discipline, offering the general reader a fascinating overview of how top scientists currently understand the processes underlying conscious experience. Combining psychology with brain science, Baars brilliantly brings his subject to life with a metaphor that has been used to understand consciousness since the time of Aristotle--the mind as theater. Here consciousness is seen as a "stage" on which our sensations, perceptions, thoughts, and feelings play to a vast, silent audience. Behind the scenes, silent context operators shape conscious experience; they include implicit expectations, self systems, and scene setters. Using this framework, Baars presents compelling evidence that human consciousness rides on top of biologically ancient mechanisms. In humans it manifests itself in inner speech, imagery, perception, and voluntary control of thought and action. Topics like hypnosis, absorbed states of mind, adaptation to trauma, and the human propensity to project expectations on uncertainty, all fit into the expanded theater metaphor. As Baars explores our present understanding of the mind, he takes us to the top laboratories around the world, where we witness some of the field's most exciting breakthroughs and discoveries. And throughout the book, Baars has sprinkled numerous and often highly amusing on-the-spot demonstrations that illuminate the ideas under discussion. Understanding consciousness is perhaps the most difficult puzzle facing the sciences today. In the Theater of Consciousness offers an invaluable introduction to the field, brilliantly weaving together the various theories that have emerged as scientists continue their quest to uncover the profound mysteries of the mind--and of human nature itself. (shrink)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  5.  47
    Global Workspace Dynamics: Cortical “Binding and Propagation” Enables Conscious Contents.Bernard J. Baars, Stan Franklin & Thomas Zoega Ramsoy - 2013 - Frontiers in Psychology 4.
  6. The functions of consciousness.Bernard J. Baars - 1988 - In A Cognitive Theory of Consciousness. New York: Cambridge University Press.
  7. The conscious access hypothesis: Origins and recent evidence.Bernard J. Baars - 2002 - Trends in Cognitive Sciences 6 (1):47-52.
  8.  64
    Does Philosophy Help or Hinder Scientific Work on Consciousness?Bernard J. Baars & Katharine McGovern - 1993 - Consciousness and Cognition 2 (1):18-27.
  9. Some essential differences between consciousness and attention, perception, and working memory.Bernard J. Baars - 1997 - Consciousness and Cognition 6 (2-3):363-371.
    When “divided attention” methods were discovered in the 1950s their implications for conscious experience were not widely appreciated. Yet when people process competing streams of sensory input they show both selective processesandclear contrasts between conscious and unconscious events. This paper suggests that the term “attention” may be best applied to theselection and maintenanceof conscious contents and distinguished from consciousness itself. This is consistent with common usage. The operational criteria for selective attention, defined in this way, are entirely different from those (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  10. In the theatre of consciousness: Global workspace theory, a rigorous scientific theory of consciousness.Bernard J. Baars - 1997 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 4 (4):292-309.
    Can we make progress exploring consciousness? Or is it forever beyond human reach? In science we never know the ultimate outcome of the journey. We can only take whatever steps our current knowledge affords. This paper explores today's evidence from the viewpoint of Global Workspace theory. First, we ask what kind of evidence has the most direct bearing on the question. The answer given here is ‘contrastive analysis’ -- a set of paired comparisons between similar conscious and unconscious processes. This (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   133 citations  
  11. Subjective experience is probably not limited to humans: The evidence from neurobiology and behavior.Bernard J. Baars - 2005 - Consciousness and Cognition 14 (1):7-21.
    In humans, conscious perception and cognition depends upon the thalamocortical complex, which supports perception, explicit cognition, memory, language, planning, and strategic control. When parts of the T-C system are damaged or stimulated, corresponding effects are found on conscious contents and state, as assessed by reliable reports. In contrast, large regions like cerebellum and basal ganglia can be damaged without affecting conscious cognition directly. Functional brain recordings also show robust activity differences in cortex between experimentally matched conscious and unconscious events. This (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  12.  6
    In the Theater of Consciousness: The Workspace of the Mind.Bernard J. Baars - 1997 - New York: Oxford University Press USA.
    Written by eminent psychologist Bernard J. Baars, this book brings us to the frontlines of the consciousness debate, offering the general reader a fascinating overview of how top scientists currently understand the processes underlying conscious experience. The study of conscious experience has seen remarkable strides in the last ten years, reflecting important technological breakthroughs and the enormous efforts of researchers in disciplines as varied as neuroscience, cognitive science, and philosophy. Scientists are just now beginning to find common ground (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  13. Global workspace theory of consciousness: Toward a cognitive neuroscience of human experience?Bernard J. Baars - 2006 - In Steven Laureys (ed.), Boundaries of Consciousness. Elsevier.
  14.  30
    Conscious contents provide the nervous system with coherent, global information.Bernard J. Baars - 1983 - In Richard J. Davidson, Gary E. Schwartz & D. H. Shapiro (eds.), Consciousness and Self-Regulation. Plenum. pp. 41--79.
  15. Brain, conscious experience, and the observing self.Bernard J. Baars, Thomas Zoega Ramsoy & Steven Laureys - 2003 - Trends in Neurosciences 26 (12):671-5.
    Conscious perception, like the sight of a coffee cup, seems to involve the brain identifying a stimulus. But conscious input activates more brain regions than are needed to identify coffee cups and faces. It spreads beyond sensory cortex to frontoparietal association areas, which do not serve stimulus identification as such. What is the role of those regions? Parietal cortex support the ‘first person perspective’ on the visual world, unconsciously framing the visual object stream. Some prefrontal areas select and interpret conscious (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  16. Consciousness is computational: The Lida model of global workspace theory.Bernard J. Baars & Stan Franklin - 2009 - International Journal of Machine Consciousness 1 (1):23-32.
    The currently leading cognitive theory of consciousness, Global Workspace Theory,1,2 postulates that the primary functions of consciousness include a global broadcast serving to recruit internal resources with which to deal with the current situation and to modulate several types of learning. In addition, conscious experiences present current conditions and problems to a "self" system, an executive interpreter that is identifiable with brain structures like the frontal lobes and precuneus.1Be it human, animal or artificial, an autonomous agent3 is said to be (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  17.  24
    Putting the focus on the fringe: Three empirical cases.Bernard J. Baars - 1993 - Consciousness and Cognition 2 (2):126-36.
    After suggesting an operational definition for fringe experiences—as opposed to clearly conscious and clearly unconscious phenomena—we examine three empirical cases: The tip-of-the-tongue experience, the fringe experience of "wrongness," and the case of conscious focus on abstract, hard-to-image conscious contents. In each case, Mangan′s four major claims are explored in some detail. Most tasks seem to involve a combination of conscious experiences, complex unconscious representations, and multiple fringe experiences. The chief disagreement from this analysis involves vague experiences that are generally believed (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  18.  27
    Biological implications of a Global Workspace theory of consciousness: Evidence, theory, and some phylogenetic speculations.Bernard J. Baars - 1987 - In G. Greenberg & E. Tobach (eds.), Cognition, Language, and Consciousness: Integrative Levels. Lawrence Erlbaum. pp. 209--236.
  19.  37
    Why volition is a foundation issue for psychology.Bernard J. Baars - 1993 - Consciousness and Cognition 2 (4):281-309.
    Since the advent of behaviorism the question of volition or "will" has been largely neglected. We consider evidence indicating that two identical behaviors may be quite distinct with respect to volition: For instance, with practice the details of predictable actions become less and less voluntary, even if the behavior itself does not visibly change. Likewise, people can voluntarily imitate involuntary slips they have just made. Such examples suggest that the concept of volition applies not to visible behavior per se, but (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  20.  36
    A neurobiological interpretation of global workspace theory.Bernard J. Baars & James Newman - 1994 - In Antti Revonsuo & Matti Kamppinen (eds.), Consciousness in Philosophy and Cognitive Neuroscience. Lawrence Erlbaum. pp. 211--226.
  21.  32
    The Global Workspace Theory of Consciousness.Bernard J. Baars - 2017 - In Susan Schneider & Max Velmans (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness. Chichester, UK: Wiley. pp. 227–242.
    Global Workspace Theory (GWT) can be compared to a theater of mind, in which conscious contents resemble a bright spot on the stage of immediate memory, selected by a spotlight of attention under executive guidance. Only the bright spot is conscious; the rest of the theater is dark and unconscious. GWT has been implemented in a number of explicit and testable global workspace models (GWM's). These specific GW models suggest that conscious experiences recruit widely distributed brain functions that are mostly (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  22. How brain reveals mind: Neural studies support the fundamental role of conscious experience.Bernard J. Baars - 2003 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 10 (9-10):100-114.
    In the last decade, careful studies of the living brain have opened the way for human consciousness to return to the heights it held before the behavioristic coup of 1913. This is illustrated by seven cases: the discovery of widespread brain activation during conscious perception; high levels of regional brain metabolism in the resting state of consciousness, dropping drastically in unconscious states; the brain correlates of inner speech; visual imagery; fringe consciousness; executive functions of the self; and volition. Other papers (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  23.  93
    A thoroughly empirical approach to consciousness.Bernard J. Baars - 1994 - PSYCHE: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Research On Consciousness 1.
    When are psychologists entitled to call a certain theoretical construct "consciousness?" Over the past few decades cognitive psychologists have reintroduced almost the entire conceptual vocabulary of common sense psychology, but now in a way that is tied explicitly to reliable empirical observations, and to compelling and increasingly adequate theoretical models. Nevertheless, until the past few years most cognitive psychologists and neuroscientists avoided dealing with consciousness. Today there is an increasing willingness to do so. But is "consciousness" different from other theoretical (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  24.  10
    Putting the Focus on the Fringe: Three Empirical Cases.Bernard J. Baars - 1993 - Consciousness and Cognition 2 (2):126-136.
    After suggesting an operational definition for fringe experiences—as opposed to clearly conscious and clearly unconscious phenomena—we examine three empirical cases: The tip-of-the-tongue experience, the fringe experience of "wrongness," and the case of conscious focus on abstract, hard-to-image conscious contents. In each case, Mangan′s four major claims are explored in some detail. Most tasks seem to involve a combination of conscious experiences, complex unconscious representations, and multiple fringe experiences. The chief disagreement from this analysis involves vague experiences that are generally believed (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  25.  22
    Essential Sources in the Scientific Study of Consciousness.Bernard J. Baars & J. B. Newman (eds.) - 2001 - MIT Press.
    Current thinking and research on consciousness and the brain.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  26.  68
    Surprisingly small subcortical structures are needed for the state of waking consciousness, while cortical projection areas seem to provide perceptual contents of consciousness.Bernard J. Baars - 1995 - Consciousness and Cognition 4 (2):159-62.
  27. The global workspace theory of consciousness.Bernard J. Baars - 2007 - In Max Velmans & Susan Schneider (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness. Blackwell. pp. 236--246.
  28.  33
    A curious coincidence? Consciousness as an object of scientific scrutiny fits our personal experience remarkably well.Bernard J. Baars - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):669-670.
  29.  94
    Metaphors of consciousness and attention in the brain.Bernard J. Baars - 1998 - Trends in Neurosciences 21:58-62.
  30.  44
    How does a serial, integrated and very limited stream of consciousness emerge from a nervous system that is mostly unconscious, distributed, parallel and of enormous capacity?Bernard J. Baars - 1993 - In G. R. Bock & James L. Marsh (eds.), Experimental and Theoretical Studies of Consciousness. Ciba Foundation Symposium 174. pp. 174--282.
  31. One, not two, neural correlates of consciousness.Bernard J. Baars & Steven Laureys - 2005 - Trends in Cognitive Sciences 9 (6):269.
  32. The Neural Basis of Conscious Experience.Bernard J. Baars - 1988 - In A Cognitive Theory of Consciousness. New York: Cambridge University Press.
  33. Understanding subjectivity: Global workspace theory and the resurrection of the observing self.Bernard J. Baars - 1996 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 3 (3):211-17.
    The world of our experience consists at all times of two parts, an objective and a subjective part . . . The objective part is the sum total of whatsoever at any given time we may be thinking of, the subjective part is the inner 'state' in which the thinking comes to pass.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  34. Neuronal mechanisms of consciousness: A relational global workspace approach.Bernard J. Baars, J. B. Newman & John G. Taylor - 1998 - In Stuart R. Hameroff, Alfred W. Kaszniak & Alwyn Scott (eds.), Toward a Science of Consciousness II: The Second Tucson Discussions and Debates. MIT Press. pp. 269-278.
    This paper explores a remarkable convergence of ideas and evidence, previously presented in separate places by its authors. That convergence has now become so persuasive that we believe we are working within substantially the same broad framework. Taylor's mathematical papers on neuronal systems involved in consciousness dovetail well with work by Newman and Baars on the thalamocortical system, suggesting a brain mechanism much like the global workspace architecture developed by Baars (see references below). This architecture is relational, in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  35. The global brainweb: An update on global workspace theory.Bernard J. Baars - 2003 - Science and Consciousness Review 2.
  36. Is feeling pain just mindreading? Our mind-brain constructs realistic knowledge of ourselves.Bernard J. Baars - 2009 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 32 (2):139-140.
    Carruthers claims that (target article,). This may be true in many cases. But like other constructivist claims, it fails to explain occasions when constructed knowledge is accurate, like a well-supported scientific theory. People can know their surrounding world and to some extent themselves. Accurate self-knowledge is firmly established for both somatosensory and social pain.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  20
    Spatial Brain Coherence during the Establishment of a Conscious Event.Bernard J. Baars - 1997 - Consciousness and Cognition 6 (1):1-2.
  38.  33
    When Are Images Conscious? The Curious Disconnection between Imagery and Consciousness in the Scientific Literature.Bernard J. Baars - 1995 - Consciousness and Cognition 5 (3):261-264.
  39. A neurobiological interpretation of the global workspace theory of consciousness.Bernard J. Baars & J. B. Newman - 1994 - In Antti Revonsuo & Matti Kamppinen (eds.), Consciousness in Philosophy and Cognitive Neuroscience. Lawrence Erlbaum.
  40.  46
    Experimental Slips and Human Error: Exploring the Architecture of Volition.Bernard J. Baars - 1992 - Plenum Press.
    This work makes three valuable contributions to the study of human slips and errors.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  41.  69
    Evidence that phenomenal consciousness is the same as access consciousness.Bernard J. Baars - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2):249-249.
    Block seems to propose untested answers to empirical questions. Whether consciousness is a “mongrel problem,” rather than a single core fact with many facets, is an empirical issue. Likewise, the intimate relationship between personal consciousness and global access functions cannot be decided pretheoretically. This point is demonstrated by the reader's private experience of foveal versus parafoveal vision, and for conscious versus unconscious representation of the many meanings of common words.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  42. Recovering consciousness: A timeline.Bernard J. Baars - forthcoming - Science and Consciousness Review.
  43. Attention vs consciousness in the visual brain: Differences in conception, phenomenology, behavior, neuroanatomy, and physiology.Bernard J. Baars - 1999 - Journal of General Psychology 126:224-33.
  44.  46
    The brain basis of a "consciousness monitor": Scientific and medical significance.Bernard J. Baars - 2001 - Consciousness and Cognition 10 (2):159-164.
    Surgical patients under anesthesia can wake up unpredictably and be exposed to intense, traumatic pain. Current medical techniques cannot maintain depth of anesthesia at a perfectly stable and safe level; the depth of unconsciousness may change from moment to moment. Without an effective consciousness monitor anesthesiologists may not be able to adjust dosages in time to protect patients from pain. An estimated 40,000 to 200,000 midoperative awakenings may occur in the United States annually. E. R. John and coauthors present the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  45. How deliberate, spontaneous, and unwanted memories emerge in a computational model of consciousness.Bernard J. Baars, Uma Ramamurthy & Stan Franklin - 2007 - In John H. Mace (ed.), Involuntary Memory. New Perspectives in Cognitive Psychology. Blackwell. pp. 177-207.
  46. Conscious contents provide coherent, global information.Bernard J. Baars - 2008 - In Hans Liljenström & Peter Århem (eds.), Consciousness transitions: phylogenetic, ontogenetic, and physiological aspects. Boston: Elsevier.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. What is a theory of consciousness a theory of? The search for criterial constraints on theory.Bernard J. Baars - 1986 - Imagination, Cognition, and Personality 1:3-24.
  48. What is conscious in the control of action? A modern ideomotor theory of voluntary action.Bernard J. Baars - 1987 - In D. Gorfein & Robert R. Hoffman (eds.), Learning and Memory: The Ebbinghaus Centennial Symposium. Lawrence Erlbaum.
  49.  57
    Working memory requires conscious processes, not vice versa: A global workspace account.Bernard J. Baars - 2003 - In Naoyuki Osaka (ed.), Neural Basis of Consciousness. John Benjamins. pp. 49--11.
  50.  37
    A biocognitive approach to the conscious core of immediate memory.Bernard J. Baars - 2001 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 24 (1):115-116.
    The limited capacity of immediate memory “rides” on the even more limited capacity of consciousness, which reflects the dynamic activity of the thalamocortical core of the brain. Recent views of the conscious narrow-capacity component of the brain are explored with reference to global workspace theory (Baars 1988; 1993; 1998). The radical limits of immediate memory must be explained in terms of biocognitive brain architecture.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 1000