Results for 'hyperarithmetic'

85 found
Order:
  1.  13
    Intrinsically Hyperarithmetical Sets.Ivan N. Soskov - 1996 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 42 (1):469-480.
    The main result proved in the paper is that on every recursive structure the intrinsically hyperarithmetical sets coincide with the relatively intrinsically hyperarithmetical sets. As a side effect of the proof an effective version of the Kueker's theorem on definability by means of infinitary formulas is obtained.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  2.  25
    Computable structures and the hyperarithmetical hierarchy.C. J. Ash - 2000 - New York: Elsevier. Edited by J. Knight.
    This book describes a program of research in computable structure theory. The goal is to find definability conditions corresponding to bounds on complexity which persist under isomorphism. The results apply to familiar kinds of structures (groups, fields, vector spaces, linear orderings Boolean algebras, Abelian p-groups, models of arithmetic). There are many interesting results already, but there are also many natural questions still to be answered. The book is self-contained in that it includes necessary background material from recursion theory (ordinal notations, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  3.  15
    Hyperarithmetical relations in expansions of recursive structures.Alan D. Vlach - 1994 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 66 (2):163-196.
    Let be a model of a theory T. Depending on wether is decidable or recursive, and on whether T is strongly minimal or -minimal, we find conditions on which guarantee that every infinite independent subset of is not recursively enumerable. For each of the same four cases we also find conditions on which guarantee that every infinite independent subset of has Turing degree 0'. More generally, let be a recursive -structure, R a relation symbol not in , ψ a recursive (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  55
    Mass problems and hyperarithmeticity.Joshua A. Cole & Stephen G. Simpson - 2007 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 7 (2):125-143.
    A mass problem is a set of Turing oracles. If P and Q are mass problems, we say that P is weakly reducible to Q if for all Y ∈ Q there exists X ∈ P such that X is Turing reducible to Y. A weak degree is an equivalence class of mass problems under mutual weak reducibility. Let [Formula: see text] be the lattice of weak degrees of mass problems associated with nonempty [Formula: see text] subsets of the Cantor (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  5.  34
    Realizing Levels of the Hyperarithmetic Hierarchy as Degree Spectra of Relations on Computable Structures.Walker M. White & Denis R. Hirschfeldt - 2002 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 43 (1):51-64.
    We construct a class of relations on computable structures whose degree spectra form natural classes of degrees. Given any computable ordinal and reducibility r stronger than or equal to m-reducibility, we show how to construct a structure with an intrinsically invariant relation whose degree spectrum consists of all nontrivial r-degrees. We extend this construction to show that can be replaced by either or.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  6.  8
    Theorems of hyperarithmetic analysis and almost theorems of hyperarithmetic analysis.James S. Barnes, Jun le Goh & Richard A. Shore - 2022 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 28 (1):133-149.
    Theorems of hyperarithmetic analysis occupy an unusual neighborhood in the realms of reverse mathematics and recursion-theoretic complexity. They lie above all the fixed iterations of the Turing jump but below ATR $_{0}$. There is a long history of proof-theoretic principles which are THAs. Until the papers reported on in this communication, there was only one mathematical example. Barnes, Goh, and Shore [1] analyze an array of ubiquity theorems in graph theory descended from Halin’s [9] work on rays in graphs. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  48
    Up to Equimorphism, Hyperarithmetic Is Recursive.Antonio Montalbán - 2005 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 70 (2):360 - 378.
    Two linear orderings are equimorphic if each can be embedded into the other. We prove that every hyperarithmetic linear ordering is equimorphic to a recursive one. On the way to our main result we prove that a linear ordering has Hausdorff rank less than $\omega _{1}^{\mathit{CK}}$ if and only if it is equimorphic to a recursive one. As a corollary of our proof we prove that, given a recursive ordinal α, the partial ordering of equimorphism types of linear orderings (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  8.  22
    Relative to any non-hyperarithmetic set.Noam Greenberg, Antonio Montalbán & Theodore A. Slaman - 2013 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 13 (1):1250007.
    We prove that there is a structure, indeed a linear ordering, whose degree spectrum is the set of all non-hyperarithmetic degrees. We also show that degree spectra can distinguish measure from category.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  9.  14
    Almost Theorems of Hyperarithmetic Analysis.Richard A. Shore - forthcoming - Journal of Symbolic Logic:1-33.
    Theorems of hyperarithmetic analysis (THAs) occupy an unusual neighborhood in the realms of reverse mathematics and recursion theoretic complexity. They lie above all the fixed (recursive) iterations of the Turing Jump but below ATR $_{0}$ (and so $\Pi _{1}^{1}$ -CA $_{0}$ or the hyperjump). There is a long history of proof theoretic principles which are THAs. Until Barnes, Goh, and Shore [ta] revealed an array of theorems in graph theory living in this neighborhood, there was only one mathematical denizen. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  45
    Indecomposable linear orderings and hyperarithmetic analysis.Antonio Montalbán - 2006 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 6 (1):89-120.
    A statement of hyperarithmetic analysis is a sentence of second order arithmetic S such that for every Y⊆ω, the minimum ω-model containing Y of RCA0 + S is HYP, the ω-model consisting of the sets hyperarithmetic in Y. We provide an example of a mathematical theorem which is a statement of hyperarithmetic analysis. This statement, that we call INDEC, is due to Jullien [13]. To the author's knowledge, no other already published, purely mathematical statement has been found (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  11.  25
    Categoricity in hyperarithmetical degrees.C. J. Ash - 1987 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 34 (1):1-14.
  12.  45
    A note on the hyperarithmetical hierarchy.H. B. Enderton & Hilary Putnam - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (3):429-430.
  13.  34
    An introduction to hyperarithmetical functions.Julia Robinson - 1967 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 32 (3):325-342.
  14. Degrees of Categoricity and the Hyperarithmetic Hierarchy.Barbara F. Csima, Johanna N. Y. Franklin & Richard A. Shore - 2013 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 54 (2):215-231.
    We study arithmetic and hyperarithmetic degrees of categoricity. We extend a result of E. Fokina, I. Kalimullin, and R. Miller to show that for every computable ordinal $\alpha$, $\mathbf{0}^{}$ is the degree of categoricity of some computable structure $\mathcal{A}$. We show additionally that for $\alpha$ a computable successor ordinal, every degree $2$-c.e. in and above $\mathbf{0}^{}$ is a degree of categoricity. We further prove that every degree of categoricity is hyperarithmetic and show that the index set of structures (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  15.  4
    Martin’s conjecture for regressive functions on the hyperarithmetic degrees.Patrick Lutz - forthcoming - Journal of Mathematical Logic.
    We answer a question of Slaman and Steel by showing that a version of Martin’s conjecture holds for all regressive functions on the hyperarithmetic degrees. A key step in our proof, which may have applications to other cases of Martin’s conjecture, consists of showing that we can always reduce to the case of a continuous function.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  44
    Galvin’s “Racing Pawns” Game, Internal Hyperarithmetic Comprehension, and the Law of Excluded Middle.Chris Conidis, Noam Greenberg & Daniel Turetsky - 2013 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 54 (2):233-252.
    We show that the fact that the first player wins every instance of Galvin’s “racing pawns” game is equivalent to arithmetic transfinite recursion. Along the way we analyze the satisfaction relation for infinitary formulas, of “internal” hyperarithmetic comprehension, and of the law of excluded middle for such formulas.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  10
    Elementary Formal Systems for Hyperarithmetical Relations.Melvin Fitting - 1978 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 24 (1‐6):25-30.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  28
    Elementary Formal Systems for Hyperarithmetical Relations.Melvin Fitting - 1978 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 24 (1-6):25-30.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. ASH, CJ, Categoricity in hyperarithmetical degrees BALDWIN, JT and HARRINGTON, L., Trivial pursuit: Re-marks on the main gap COOPER, SB and EPSTEIN, RL, Complementing below re-cursively enumerable degrees.J. Steprans & S. Shelah - 1987 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 34:311.
  20.  17
    Recursive linear orderings and hyperarithmetical functions.Shih-Chao Liu - 1962 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 3 (3):129-132.
  21.  13
    A decidable Ehrenfeucht theory with exactly two hyperarithmetic models.Robert C. Reed - 1991 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 53 (2):135-168.
    Millar showed that for each n<ω, there is a complete decidable theory having precisely eighteen nonisomorphic countable models where some of these are decidable exactly in the hyperarithmetic set H. By combining ideas from Millar's proof with a technique of Peretyat'kin, the author reduces the number of countable models to five. By a theorem of Millar, this is the smallest number of countable models a decidable theory can have if some of the models are not 0″-decidable.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  22.  10
    ASH, CJ, Categoricity in hyperarithmetical degrees (1) BALDWIN, JT and HARRINGTON, L., Trivial pursuit: Re-marks on the main gap (3) COOPER, SB and EPSTEIN, RL, Complementing below re-cursively enumerable degrees (1). [REVIEW]Rl Epstein - 1987 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 34 (1):311.
  23. Structures and the Hyperarithmetical Hierarchy. Knight has directed or co-directed seven doctoral dissertations in mathematics and one in electrical engineering. She served on selection panels for the NSF Postdoctoral Fellowships, on program committees of numerous meetings, and as an editor of The Journal of Symbolic Logic (1989-1995). [REVIEW]D. Haskell, G. Hjorth, C. Jockusch, A. Kanamori, H. J. Keisler, V. McGee & T. Pitassi - 2000 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 6 (1).
  24.  23
    On the decidability of the theories of the arithmetic and hyperarithmetic degrees as uppersemilattices.James S. Barnes - 2017 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 82 (4):1496-1518.
    We establish the decidability of the${{\rm{\Sigma }}_2}$theory of both the arithmetic and hyperarithmetic degrees in the language of uppersemilattices, i.e., the language with ≤, 0, and$\sqcup$. This is achieved by using Kumabe-Slaman forcing, along with other known results, to show given finite uppersemilattices${\cal M}$and${\cal N}$, where${\cal M}$is a subuppersemilattice of${\cal N}$, that every embedding of${\cal M}$into either degree structure extends to one of${\cal N}$iff${\cal N}$is an end-extension of${\cal M}$.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  9
    The Axiom of Choice and the Class of Hyperarithmetic Functions.G. Kreisel - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (2):333-334.
  26.  29
    C. Spector. Hyperarithmetical quantifiers. Fundamenta mathematicae, vol. 48 no. 3 , pp. 313–320. - Shih-Chao Liu. Recursive linear orderings and hyper arithmetical junctions. Notre Dame journal of formal logic, vol. 3 , pp. 129–132. [REVIEW]Gustav Hensel - 1966 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 31 (1):137-137.
  27. Review: C. Spector, Hyperarithmetical Quantifiers; Shih-Chao Liu, Recursive Linear Orderings and Hyperarithmetical Functions. [REVIEW]Gustav Hensel - 1966 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 31 (1):137-137.
  28.  12
    The generic degrees of density-1 sets, and a characterization of the hyperarithmetic reals.Gregory Igusa - 2015 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 80 (4):1290-1314.
    A generic computation of a subsetAof ℕ is a computation which correctly computes most of the bits ofA, but which potentially does not halt on all inputs. The motivation for this concept is derived from complexity theory, where it has been noticed that frequently, it is more important to know how difficult a type of problem is in the general case than how difficult it is in the worst case. When we study this concept from a recursion theoretic point of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  29. Ash, CJ, Stability of recursive structures in arithmetical degrees Ash, CJ, Categoric@ in hyperarithmetical degrees.D. Cenzer, P. Clote, R. L. Smith, S. S. Wainer, K. J. Compton, C. W. Henson & S. Shelah - 1988 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 40:307-310.
  30.  25
    The weakness of the pigeonhole principle under hyperarithmetical reductions.Benoit Monin & Ludovic Patey - 2020 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 21 (3):2150013.
    The infinite pigeonhole principle for 2-partitions asserts the existence, for every set A, of an infinite subset of A or of its complement. In this paper, we study the infinite pigeonhole pr...
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31.  25
    Hisao Tanaka. On limits of sequences of hyperarithmetical functionals and predicates. Commentarii mathematici Universitatis Sancti Pauli, vol. 14 no. 2 , pp. 105–121. - Tosiyuki Tugué and Hisao Tanaka. A note on the effective descriptive set theory. Commentarii mathematici Universitatis Sancti Pauli, vol. 15 no. 1 , pp. 19–28. [REVIEW]Stephen J. Garland - 1974 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 39 (2):344-345.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  15
    Review: Hisao Tanaka, On Limits of Sequences of Hyperarithmetical Functionals and Predicates; Tosiyuki Tugue, Hisao Tanaka, A Note on the Effective Descriptive Set Theory. [REVIEW]Stephen J. Garland - 1974 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 39 (2):344-345.
  33.  20
    Antonio Montalbán, Indecomposable linear orderings and hyperarithmetic analysis_. Journal of Mathematical Logic, vol. 6 (2006), no. 1, pp. 89–120. - Itay Neeman, _The strength of Jullien’s indecomposability theorem_. Journal of Mathematical Logic, vol. 8 (2008), no. 1, pp. 93–119. - Itay Neeman, _Necessary use of_ _induction in a reversal. Journal of Symbolic Logic, vol. 76 (2011), no. 2, pp. 561–574. [REVIEW]Henry Towsner - 2014 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 20 (3):366-368.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  15
    Ash C. J. and Knight J.. Computable structures and the hyperarithmetical hierarchy. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics, vol. 144. Elsevier, Amsterdam etc. 2000, xv + 346 pp. [REVIEW]Valentina Harizanov - 2001 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 7 (3):383-385.
  35.  18
    Review: C. J. Ash, J. Knight, Computable Structures and the Hyperarithmetical Hierarchy. [REVIEW]Valentina Harizanov - 2001 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 7 (3):383-385.
  36.  16
    Kreisel G.. The axiom of choice and the class of hyperarithmetic functions. Koninklijke Nederlandse Akademie van Wetenschappen, Proceedings, series A, vol. 65 , pp. 307–319; also Indagationes mathematicae, vol. 24 , pp. 307–319. [REVIEW]Yiannis N. Moschovakis - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (2):333-334.
  37.  10
    Review: G. Kreisel, The Axiom of Choice and the Class of Hyperarithmetic Functions. [REVIEW]Yiannis N. Moschovakis - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (2):333-334.
  38. Comparing Peano arithmetic, Basic Law V, and Hume’s Principle.Sean Walsh - 2012 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 163 (11):1679-1709.
    This paper presents new constructions of models of Hume's Principle and Basic Law V with restricted amounts of comprehension. The techniques used in these constructions are drawn from hyperarithmetic theory and the model theory of fields, and formalizing these techniques within various subsystems of second-order Peano arithmetic allows one to put upper and lower bounds on the interpretability strength of these theories and hence to compare these theories to the canonical subsystems of second-order arithmetic. The main results of this (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  39.  35
    An example related to Gregory’s Theorem.J. Johnson, J. F. Knight, V. Ocasio & S. VanDenDriessche - 2013 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 52 (3-4):419-434.
    In this paper, we give an example of a complete computable infinitary theory T with countable models ${\mathcal{M}}$ and ${\mathcal{N}}$ , where ${\mathcal{N}}$ is a proper computable infinitary extension of ${\mathcal{M}}$ and T has no uncountable model. In fact, ${\mathcal{M}}$ and ${\mathcal{N}}$ are (up to isomorphism) the only models of T. Moreover, for all computable ordinals α, the computable ${\Sigma_\alpha}$ part of T is hyperarithmetical. It follows from a theorem of Gregory (JSL 38:460–470, 1972; Not Am Math Soc 17:967–968, 1970) (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  15
    Halin’s infinite ray theorems: Complexity and reverse mathematics.James S. Barnes, Jun Le Goh & Richard A. Shore - forthcoming - Journal of Mathematical Logic.
    Halin in 1965 proved that if a graph has [Formula: see text] many pairwise disjoint rays for each [Formula: see text] then it has infinitely many pairwise disjoint rays. We analyze the complexity of this and other similar results in terms of computable and proof theoretic complexity. The statement of Halin’s theorem and the construction proving it seem very much like standard versions of compactness arguments such as König’s Lemma. Those results, while not computable, are relatively simple. They only use (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  14
    On the complexity of categoricity in computable structures.Walker M. White - 2003 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 49 (6):603.
    We investigate the computational complexity the class of Γ-categorical computable structures. We show that hyperarithmetic categoricity is Π11-complete, while computable categoricity is Π04-hard.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  42.  43
    On Σ1 1 equivalence relations over the natural numbers.Ekaterina B. Fokina & Sy-David Friedman - 2012 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 58 (1-2):113-124.
    We study the structure of Σ11 equivalence relations on hyperarithmetical subsets of ω under reducibilities given by hyperarithmetical or computable functions, called h-reducibility and FF-reducibility, respectively. We show that the structure is rich even when one fixes the number of properly equation imagei.e., Σ11 but not equation image equivalence classes. We also show the existence of incomparable Σ11 equivalence relations that are complete as subsets of ω × ω with respect to the corresponding reducibility on sets. We study complete Σ11 (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  43.  36
    Computing maximal chains.Alberto Marcone, Antonio Montalbán & Richard A. Shore - 2012 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 51 (5-6):651-660.
    In (Fund Math 60:175–186 1967), Wolk proved that every well partial order (wpo) has a maximal chain; that is a chain of maximal order type. (Note that all chains in a wpo are well-ordered.) We prove that such maximal chain cannot be found computably, not even hyperarithmetically: No hyperarithmetic set can compute maximal chains in all computable wpos. However, we prove that almost every set, in the sense of category, can compute maximal chains in all computable wpos. Wolk’s original (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  10
    Borel combinatorics fail in HYP.Henry Towsner, Rose Weisshaar & Linda Westrick - 2022 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 23 (2).
    We characterize the completely determined Borel subsets of HYP as exactly the [Formula: see text] subsets of HYP. As a result, HYP believes there is a Borel well-ordering of the reals, that the Borel Dual Ramsey Theorem fails, and that every Borel d-regular bipartite graph has a Borel perfect matching, among other examples. Therefore, the Borel Dual Ramsey Theorem and several theorems of descriptive combinatorics are not theories of hyperarithmetic analysis. In the case of the Borel Dual Ramsey Theorem, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  4
    Investigating the Computable Friedman–Stanley Jump.Uri Andrews & Luca San Mauro - forthcoming - Journal of Symbolic Logic:1-27.
    The Friedman–Stanley jump, extensively studied by descriptive set theorists, is a fundamental tool for gauging the complexity of Borel isomorphism relations. This paper focuses on a natural computable analog of this jump operator for equivalence relations on $\omega $, written ${\dotplus }$, recently introduced by Clemens, Coskey, and Krakoff. We offer a thorough analysis of the computable Friedman–Stanley jump and its connections with the hierarchy of countable equivalence relations under the computable reducibility $\leq _c$. In particular, we show that this (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  24
    A transfinite hierarchy of reals.George Barmpalias - 2003 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 49 (2):163-172.
    We extend the hierarchy defined in [5] to cover all hyperarithmetical reals. An intuitive idea is used or the definition, but a characterization of the related classes is obtained. A hierarchy theorem and two fixed point theorems are presented.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47.  40
    A generalization of the limit lemma and clopen games.Peter Clote - 1986 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 51 (2):273-291.
    We give a new characterization of the hyperarithmetic sets: a set X of integers is recursive in e α if and only if there is a Turing machine which computes X and "halts" in less than or equal to the ordinal number ω α of steps. This result represents a generalization of the well-known "limit lemma" due to J. R. Shoenfield [Sho-1] and later independently by H. Putnam [Pu] and independently by E. M. Gold [Go]. As an application of (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48.  18
    Necessary use of [image] induction in a reversal.Itay Neeman - 2011 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 76 (2):561 - 574.
    Jullien's indecomposability theorem (INDEC) states that if a scattered countable linear order is indecomposable, then it is either indecomposable to the left, or indecomposable to the right. The theorem was shown by Montalbán to be a theorem of hyperarithmetic analysis, and then, in the base system RCA₀ plus ${\mathrm{\Sigma }}_{1}^{1}\text{\hspace{0.17em}}$ induction, it was shown by Neeman to have strength strictly between weak ${\mathrm{\Sigma }}_{1}^{1}$ choice and ${\mathrm{\Delta }}_{1}^{1}$ comprehension. We prove in this paper that ${\mathrm{\Sigma }}_{1}^{1}$ induction is needed (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  49.  40
    On the ranked points of a Π1 0 set.Douglas Cenzer & Rick L. Smith - 1989 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (3):975-991.
    This paper continues joint work of the authors with P. Clote, R. Soare and S. Wainer (Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, vol. 31 (1986), pp. 145--163). An element x of the Cantor space 2 ω is said have rank α in the closed set P if x is in $D^\alpha(P)\backslash D^{\alpha + 1}(P)$ , where D α is the iterated Cantor-Bendixson derivative. The rank of x is defined to be the least α such that x has rank α in (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  50.  17
    On the Π1 1 -separation principle.Antonio Montalbán - 2008 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 54 (6):563-578.
    We study the proof-theoretic strength of the Π11-separation axiom scheme, and we show that Π11-separation lies strictly in between the Δ11-comprehension and Σ11-choice axiom schemes over RCA0.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
1 — 50 / 85