19 found
Order:
Disambiguations
Silvio Seno Chibeni [20]Silvio Chibeni [6]Silvio S. Chibeni [1]
  1.  31
    Afirmando o conseqüente: uma defesa do realismo científico (?!).Silvio Seno Chibeni - 2006 - Scientiae Studia 4 (2):221-249.
    No categories
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  2.  16
    Berkeley e o papel das hipóteses na filosofia natural.Silvio Seno Chibeni - 2010 - Scientiae Studia 8 (3):389-419.
  3. Hume e o "dogma do reducionismo".Silvio Seno Chibeni - 2011 - Kriterion: Journal of Philosophy 52 (124):343-353.
  4.  15
    Holism in microphysics.Silvio Seno Chibeni - 2004 - Epistemologia 27 (2):227-244.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  5.  39
    As posições de Newton, Locke e Berkeley sobre a natureza da gravitação.Silvio Seno Chibeni - 2013 - Scientiae Studia 11 (4):811-839.
    Ao defender, nos Princípios matemáticos de filosofia natural, a existência de uma força de gravitação universal, Newton desencadeou uma onda de dúvidas e objeções filosóficas. Suas próprias declarações sobre a natureza da gravitação não são facilmente interpretáveis como formando um conjunto consistente de opiniões. Por um lado, logo após fornecer as três definições de "quantidades de forças centrípetas" (Defs. 6-8), Newton observa que está tratando tais forças "matematicamente", sem se pronunciar sobre sua realidade física. Mas, por outro lado, no Escólio (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6. Explanations in Microphysics: A response to van Fraassen's argument.Silvio Seno Chibeni - 2008 - Principia 12 (1):49-72.
    http://dx.doi.org/10.5007/1808-1711.2008v12n1p49 The aim of this article is to offer a rejoinder to an argument against scientific realism put forward by van Fraassen, based on theoretical considerations regarding microphysics. At a certain stage of his general attack to scientific realism, van Fraassen argues, in contrast to what realists typically hold, that empirical regularities should sometimes be regarded as “brute facts”, which do not ask for explanation in terms of deeper, unobservable mechanisms. The argument from microphysics formulated by van Fraassen is based (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  44
    Afirming the consequent: a defense of scientific realism (?!).Silvio Seno Chibeni - 2006 - Scientiae Studia 4 (2):221-249.
  8.  8
    Berkeley and the role of hypothesis in natural philosophy.Silvio Seno Chibeni - 2010 - Scientiae Studia 8 (3):389-419.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9. Discussions Quinton’s Neglected Argument for Scientific Realism.Silvio Seno Chibeni - 2005 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 36 (2):393-400.
    This paper discusses an argument for scientific realism put forward by Anthony Quinton in The Nature of Things. The argument – here called the controlled continuity argument – seems to have received no attention in the literature, apparently because it may easily be mistaken for a better-known argument, Grover Maxwell’s “argument from the continuum”. It is argued here that, in point of fact, the two are quite distinct and that Quinton’s argument has several advantages over Maxwell’s. The controlled continuity argument (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  19
    Explanations in Microphysics: A response to van Fraassen's argument.Silvio Seno Chibeni - 2008 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 12 (1):49-72.
    The aim of this article is to offer a rejoinder to an argument against scientific realism put forward by van Fraassen, based on theoretical considerations regarding microphysics. At a certain stage of his general attack to scientific realism, van Fraassen argues, in contrast to what realists typically hold, that empirical regularities should sometimes be regarded as “brute facts”, which do not ask for explanation in terms of deeper, unobservable mechanisms. The argument from microphysics formulated by van Fraassen is based on (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  69
    Hume e as bases científicas da tese de que não há acaso no mundo.Silvio Seno Chibeni - 2012 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 16 (2):229-254.
    http://dx.doi.org/10.5007/1808-1711.2012v16n2p229 Tanto no Tratado da Natureza Humana como na Investigação sobre o Entendimento Humano , Hume mostra-se convencido de que “não há acaso no mundo”, e que “aquilo que o vulgo chama de acaso não passa de uma causa secreta e escondida”. Essa tese desempenha papel crucial em sua análise do livre-arbítrio e, conseguintemente, da responsabilidade moral; é também um elemento importante em sua discussão sobre os milagres. No entanto, o próprio Hume ofereceu, no Tratado , um argumento convincente para (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  12
    Hume e as bases científicas da tese de que não há acaso no mundo.Silvio Seno Chibeni - 2012 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 16 (2):229-254.
    Both in the Treatise of Human Nature and in the Enquiry concerning Human Understanding, Hume defends that “there is no chance in the world”, and that “what the vulgar call chance is nothing but a secret and conceal’d cause”. This view plays a crucial role in Hume’s influential analysis of free will and moral responsibility. It functions also as a central presupposition in his discussion of miracles. However, Hume himself argued convincingly that the “maxim of causality”, according to which “whatever (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  12
    Hume e o "dogma do reducionismo".Silvio Seno Chibeni - 2011 - Kriterion: Journal of Philosophy 52 (124):343-353.
  14.  8
    Hume on the principles of natural philosophy.Silvio Chibeni - 2003 - Manuscrito 26 (1):183-205.
    Both in the Introduction to the Treatise of Human Nature and in the, Hume expressly declared that his goal was to contribute to the development of a “science of man” methodologically akin to the natural sciences, and capable of emulating their “accuracy” and explanatory success. He regarded these sciences as starting from careful observation of phenomena, and proceeding to the establish-ment of “principles” of increasing generality. Although rejecting as vain any hope of discovering “the ultimate principles” of any science, he (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  9
    Hume on unobservable entities.Silvio Seno Chibeni - 2018 - Doispontos 15 (1).
  16. The spiritist paradigm.Silvio S. Chibeni - 1990 - Human Nature 1 (2):82-87.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17. Locke on the Epistemological Status of Scientific Laws.Silvio Seno Chibeni - 2005 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 9 (1-2):19-41.
    This article aims to defend Locke against Quine’s charge, made in his famous “two dogmas” paper, that Locke’s theory of knowledge is badly flawed, not only for assuming the dogmas, but also for adopting an “in-tolerably restrictive” version of the dogma of reductionism. It is shown here that, in his analysis of the epistemological status of scientific laws, Locke has effectively transcended the narrow idea-empiricism which un-derlies this version of reductionism. First, in order to escape idealism, he introduced the notion (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  18.  75
    Realismo cient’ifico empirista.Sílvio Seno Chibeni - 1997 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 1 (2):255--270.
    In his influential criticism of scientific realism, Bas van Fraassen assumes that this doctrine is incompatible with empiricism, according to which the sole ultimate basis of knowledge is experience. This claim has been generally accepted in the contemporary literature in philosophy of science. Thus, the very distinction between scientific realism and empiricism is often forgotten, the term 'empiricism' being now widely used to designate a range of anti-realist positions, such as van Fraassen's "construct ive empiricism". In this paper it is (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  17
    Russell e a Noção de Causa.Sílvio Seno Chibeni - 2001 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 5 (1-2):125–148.
    The central aim of this article is to discuss Russell's analysis of the notion of cause. In his presidential address to the Aristotelian Society in 1912, Russell put forward several theses on causality in general, and specially on its role in science. He claimed that although vague references to causal laws are often found in the beginnings of science, "in the advanced sciences” the word 'cause' never occurs". Furthermore, Russell maintained that even in philosophy the word 'cause' is "so inextricably (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark