Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Lowness for genericity.Liang Yu - 2006 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 45 (2):233-238.
    We study lowness for genericity. We show that there exists no Turing degree which is low for 1-genericity and all of computably traceable degrees are low for weak 1-genericity.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Cohesive sets and rainbows.Wei Wang - 2014 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 165 (2):389-408.
    We study the strength of RRT32, Rainbow Ramsey Theorem for colorings of triples, and prove that RCA0 + RRT32 implies neither WKL0 nor RRT42 source. To this end, we establish some recursion theoretic properties of cohesive sets and rainbows for colorings of pairs. We show that every sequence admits a cohesive set of non-PA Turing degree; and that every ∅′-recursive sequence admits a low3 cohesive set.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The axiomatization of randomness.Michiel van Lambalgen - 1990 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 55 (3):1143-1167.
    We present a faithful axiomatization of von Mises' notion of a random sequence, using an abstract independence relation. A byproduct is a quantifier elimination theorem for Friedman's "almost all" quantifier in terms of this independence relation.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Ramsey-type graph coloring and diagonal non-computability.Ludovic Patey - 2015 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 54 (7-8):899-914.
    A function is diagonally non-computable if it diagonalizes against the universal partial computable function. D.n.c. functions play a central role in algorithmic randomness and reverse mathematics. Flood and Towsner asked for which functions h, the principle stating the existence of an h-bounded d.n.c. function implies Ramsey-type weak König’s lemma. In this paper, we prove that for every computable order h, there exists an ω\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${\omega}$$\end{document} -model of h-DNR which is not a not (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Degrees bounding principles and universal instances in reverse mathematics.Ludovic Patey - 2015 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 166 (11):1165-1185.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Open questions in reverse mathematics.Antonio Montalbán - 2011 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 17 (3):431-454.
    We present a list of open questions in reverse mathematics, including some relevant background information for each question. We also mention some of the areas of reverse mathematics that are starting to be developed and where interesting open question may be found.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Partition theorems and computability theory.Joseph R. Mileti - 2005 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 11 (3):411-427.
    The connections between mathematical logic and combinatorics have a rich history. This paper focuses on one aspect of this relationship: understanding the strength, measured using the tools of computability theory and reverse mathematics, of various partition theorems. To set the stage, recall two of the most fundamental combinatorial principles, König's Lemma and Ramsey's Theorem. We denote the set of natural numbers by ω and the set of finite sequences of natural numbers by ω<ω. We also identify each n ∈ ω (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • RT2 2 does not imply WKL0.Jiayi Liu - 2012 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 77 (2):609-620.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • RT₂² does not imply WKL₀.Jiayi Liu - 2012 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 77 (2):609-620.
    We prove that RCA₀ + RT $RT\begin{array}{*{20}{c}} 2 \\ 2 \\ \end{array} $ ̸͢ WKL₀ by showing that for any set C not of PA-degree and any set A, there exists an infinite subset G of A or ̅Α, such that G ⊕ C is also not of PA-degree.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Separating principles below Ramsey's theorem for pairs.Manuel Lerman, Reed Solomon & Henry Towsner - 2013 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 13 (2):1350007.
    In recent years, there has been a substantial amount of work in reverse mathematics concerning natural mathematical principles that are provable from RT, Ramsey's Theorem for Pairs. These principles tend to fall outside of the "big five" systems of reverse mathematics and a complicated picture of subsystems below RT has emerged. In this paper, we answer two open questions concerning these subsystems, specifically that ADS is not equivalent to CAC and that EM is not equivalent to RT.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Primitive Recursion and the Chain Antichain Principle.Alexander P. Kreuzer - 2012 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 53 (2):245-265.
    Let the chain antichain principle (CAC) be the statement that each partial order on $\mathbb{N}$ possesses an infinite chain or an infinite antichain. Chong, Slaman, and Yang recently proved using forcing over nonstandard models of arithmetic that CAC is $\Pi^1_1$-conservative over $\text{RCA}_0+\Pi^0_1\text{-CP}$ and so in particular that CAC does not imply $\Sigma^0_2$-induction. We provide here a different purely syntactical and constructive proof of the statement that CAC (even together with WKL) does not imply $\Sigma^0_2$-induction. In detail we show using a (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Recursively enumerable sets modulo iterated jumps and extensions of Arslanov's completeness criterion.C. G. Jockusch, M. Lerman, R. I. Soare & R. M. Solovay - 1989 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (4):1288-1323.
  • A cohesive set which is not high.Carl Jockusch & Frank Stephan - 1993 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 39 (1):515-530.
    We study the degrees of unsolvability of sets which are cohesive . We answer a question raised by the first author in 1972 by showing that there is a cohesive set A whose degree a satisfies a' = 0″ and hence is not high. We characterize the jumps of the degrees of r-cohesive sets, and we show that the degrees of r-cohesive sets coincide with those of the cohesive sets. We obtain analogous results for strongly hyperimmune and strongly hyperhyperimmune sets (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Lowness for Kurtz randomness.Noam Greenberg & Joseph S. Miller - 2009 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 74 (2):665-678.
    We prove that degrees that are low for Kurtz randomness cannot be diagonally non-recursive. Together with the work of Stephan and Yu [16], this proves that they coincide with the hyperimmune-free non-DNR degrees, which are also exactly the degrees that are low for weak 1-genericity. We also consider Low(M, Kurtz), the class of degrees a such that every element of M is a-Kurtz random. These are characterised when M is the class of Martin-Löf random, computably random, or Schnorr random reals. (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Reverse mathematics and a Ramsey-type König's Lemma.Stephen Flood - 2012 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 77 (4):1272-1280.
    In this paper, we propose a weak regularity principle which is similar to both weak König's lemma and Ramsey's theorem. We begin by studying the computational strength of this principle in the context of reverse mathematics. We then analyze different ways of generalizing this principle.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Ramsey's Theorem and Cone Avoidance.Damir D. Dzhafarov & Carl G. Jockusch - 2009 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 74 (2):557-578.
    It was shown by Cholak, Jockusch, and Slaman that every computable 2-coloring of pairs admits an infinite low₂ homogeneous set H. We answer a question of the same authors by showing that H may be chosen to satisfy in addition $C\,\not \leqslant _T \,H$, where C is a given noncomputable set. This is shown by analyzing a new and simplified proof of Seetapun's cone avoidance theorem for Ramsey's theorem. We then extend the result to show that every computable 2-coloring of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • The polarized Ramsey’s theorem.Damir D. Dzhafarov & Jeffry L. Hirst - 2009 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 48 (2):141-157.
    We study the effective and proof-theoretic content of the polarized Ramsey’s theorem, a variant of Ramsey’s theorem obtained by relaxing the definition of homogeneous set. Our investigation yields a new characterization of Ramsey’s theorem in all exponents, and produces several combinatorial principles which, modulo bounding for ${\Sigma^0_2}$ formulas, lie (possibly not strictly) between Ramsey’s theorem for pairs and the stable Ramsey’s theorem for pairs.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • A Δ20 set with no infinite low subset in either it or its complement.Rod Downey, Denis R. Hirschfeldt, Steffen Lempp & Reed Solomon - 2001 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 66 (3):1371-1381.
    We construct the set of the title, answering a question of Cholak, Jockusch, and Slaman [1], and discuss its connections with the study of the proof-theoretic strength and effective content of versions of Ramsey's Theorem. In particular, our result implies that every ω-model of RCA 0 + SRT 2 2 must contain a nonlow set.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Combinatorial principles weaker than Ramsey's Theorem for pairs.Denis R. Hirschfeldt & Richard A. Shore - 2007 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 72 (1):171-206.
    We investigate the complexity of various combinatorial theorems about linear and partial orders, from the points of view of computability theory and reverse mathematics. We focus in particular on the principles ADS (Ascending or Descending Sequence), which states that every infinite linear order has either an infinite descending sequence or an infinite ascending sequence, and CAC (Chain-AntiChain), which states that every infinite partial order has either an infinite chain or an infinite antichain. It is well-known that Ramsey's Theorem for pairs (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • On the Strength of Ramsey's Theorem.David Seetapun & Theodore A. Slaman - 1995 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 36 (4):570-582.
    We show that, for every partition F of the pairs of natural numbers and for every set C, if C is not recursive in F then there is an infinite set H, such that H is homogeneous for F and C is not recursive in H. We conclude that the formal statement of Ramsey's Theorem for Pairs is not strong enough to prove , the comprehension scheme for arithmetical formulas, within the base theory , the comprehension scheme for recursive formulas. (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • The Strength of the Rainbow Ramsey Theorem.Barbara F. Csima & Joseph R. Mileti - 2009 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 74 (4):1310 - 1324.
    The Rainbow Ramsey Theorem is essentially an "anti-Ramsey" theorem which states that certain types of colorings must be injective on a large subset (rather than constant on a large subset). Surprisingly, this version follows easily from Ramsey's Theorem, even in the weak system RCA₀ of reverse mathematics. We answer the question of the converse implication for pairs, showing that the Rainbow Ramsey Theorem for pairs is in fact strictly weaker than Ramsey's Theorem for pairs over RCA₀. The separation involves techniques (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • On the strength of Ramsey's theorem for pairs.Peter A. Cholak, Carl G. Jockusch & Theodore A. Slaman - 2001 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 66 (1):1-55.
    We study the proof-theoretic strength and effective content of the infinite form of Ramsey's theorem for pairs. Let RT n k denote Ramsey's theorem for k-colorings of n-element sets, and let RT $^n_{ denote (∀ k)RT n k . Our main result on computability is: For any n ≥ 2 and any computable (recursive) k-coloring of the n-element sets of natural numbers, there is an infinite homogeneous set X with X'' ≤ T 0 (n) . Let IΣ n and BΣ (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • Generics for computable Mathias forcing.Peter A. Cholak, Damir D. Dzhafarov, Jeffry L. Hirst & Theodore A. Slaman - 2014 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 165 (9):1418-1428.
    We study the complexity of generic reals for computable Mathias forcing in the context of computability theory. The n -generics and weak n -generics form a strict hierarchy under Turing reducibility, as in the case of Cohen forcing. We analyze the complexity of the Mathias forcing relation, and show that if G is any n -generic with n≥2n≥2 then it satisfies the jump property G≡TG′⊕∅G≡TG′⊕∅. We prove that every such G has generalized high Turing degree, and so cannot have even (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Ramsey's theorem and recursion theory.Carl G. Jockusch - 1972 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 37 (2):268-280.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations