Acquisition

Critical Inquiry 6 (2):291-303 (1979)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Material acquisition—buying, inheriting, being given—and nonmaterial—learning a word, assimilating a form—have been likened, and in both, meaningful acquisition cannot take place without a taxonomy, a scheme of categories into which the acquired element can be fitted. Then with these elements—both material and nonmaterial—we create a world or build and project a self, the painter and the interior decorator equally manipulating the elements in a vocabulary. The coarseness of such an outlook seems to bludgeon away long-established fine distinctions. We need not deny, however, that there may be a kind of "indifference" in regard to "the real existence of the thing" which allows us "to play the part of judge in matters of taste," as Kant would have it,1 we need not deny the existence of an "aesthetic attitude: it is just that such indifference and such an attitude probably don't have much to do with our day-to-day experience of artifacts and perhaps needn't. The "aesthetic attitude" was not long ago defined by Jerome Stolnitz as "disinterested and sympathetic attention to and contemplation of any object of awareness whatever, for its own sake alone."2 Stolnitz is at pains to distinguish the aesthetic attitude from "interests" with which it may be preferable to confuse it. "One of them," he writes, "is the interest in owning a work of art for the sake of pride or prestige". And again, "Another nonaesthetic interest is the 'cognitive,' i.e., the interest in gaining knowledge about an object". Both these interests sound rather acquisitive, and let us consider the "aesthetic attitude" as somehow tied in everyday practice to the bundle of "acquiring" activities. · 1. Immanuel Kant, The Critique of Judgment, trans. James Creed Meredith, p. 43.· 2. Jerome Stolnitz, Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art Criticism, excerpted in Introductory Readings in Aesthetics, ed. John Hospers, p. 19; all further citations in text. Hiram W. Woodward, Jr. is a lecturer in the department of the history of art at the University of Michigan. He is editor of Eighty Works in the University of Michigan Museum of Art: A Handbook and coeditor of Barabudur: History and Significance of a Buddhist Monument.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,752

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

The aesthetic attitude.David E. W. Fenner - 1996 - Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press.
Aesthetic Experience and Value.Richard R. Mccarty - 1984 - Dissertation, University of Missouri - Columbia
The Aesthetic Attitude.Alexandra King - 2012 - Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
"The aesthetic attitude" in the rise of modern aesthetics.Jerome Stolnitz - 1978 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 36 (4):409-422.
"The aesthetic attitude" in the rise of modern aesthetics: Again.Jerome Stolnitz - 1984 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 43 (2):205-208.
Remarks on aesthetic intentionality: Husserl or Kant.Danielle Lories - 2006 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 14 (1):31-49.
Kant on the normativity of taste: The role of aesthetic ideas.Andrew Chignell - 2007 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 85 (3):415 – 433.
Aesthetic Disinterestedness in Kant and Schopenhauer.Bart Vandenabeele - 2012 - Estetika: The European Journal of Aesthetics 49 (1):45-70.
Aesthetic experience and aesthetic object.Roman Ingarden - 1960 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 21 (3):289-313.
The artistic values in aesthetic experience.Jerome Stolnitz - 1973 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 32 (1):5-15.

Analytics

Added to PP
2014-01-17

Downloads
23 (#679,329)

6 months
9 (#302,300)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

No references found.

Add more references