Kant and Leibniz on Relations and Their Place in the Monadology

In Stefano Bacin, Alfredo Ferrarin, Claudio La Rocca & Margit Ruffing (eds.), Kant und die Philosophie in weltbürgerlicher Absicht. Akten des XI. Internationalen Kant-Kongresses. Boston: de Gruyter. pp. Vol 5: 391-403 (2013)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Throughout the development of his views of relations, Kant takes Leibniz’s theory as a constant – though not fixed – term of comparison. In fact, Kant’s picture and evaluation of Leibniz develop as well. Kant is a stalwart advocate of the Physical Influx model of causality, which he equates with the reality of interaction relations. Leibniz’s view of the ideality of such relations, by contrast, entails Monadology and Pre-established Harmony. Kant’s premiss is the “Basic Insight” that we cannot conceptually grasp how two independent substances may relate to each other – a negative principle he maintains all along, from the 1755 “New Elucidation” to the Critical age. The Rationalist Kant still thinks that we can derive positive results about the intelligible world from this Insight – thanks to the “real use of the understanding” of the 1770 “Dissertation,” which he later repudiates. I show, however, that the “Dissertation” fails to disprove Pre-established Harmony and I argue that a “reformed” Leibnizian thinker may combine Monadology with Kant’s separation of the intelligible and sensible worlds. Crucially, this reformed theory reappears in Kant’s 1786 and 1790 texts. While the 1781 “Amphiboly” famously accuses Leibniz of the invalid real use of the understanding and of exchanging phenomena for noumena, Kant’s picture of Leibniz in 1786 is more favourable. The reformed Monadology, in which spatial phenomena do not mirror the Harmonic order of monads, is ascribed to Leibniz. Since this model is now seen as the only “correct intellectual picture of the noumena” (based on the Insight), and since it has only a negative function, Kant commends Leibniz as a forerunner of Criticism.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,897

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Kant's critique of the Leibnizian philosophy : Contra the Leibnizians, but pro Leibniz.Anja Jauernig - 2008 - In Daniel Garber & Béatrice Longuenesse (eds.), Kant and the Early Moderns. Princeton University Press. pp. 41-63 (and 214-223 notes).
Is Kant's Realm of Ends a Unum per Se? Aquinas, Suárez, Leibniz and Kant on Composition.Lucas Thorpe - 2010 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 18 (3):461-485.
Leibniz: a collection of critical essays.Harry G. Frankfurt - 1976 - Notre Dame [Ind.]: University of Notre Dame Press.
One Community or Many? From Logic to Juridical Law, via Metaphysics [in Kant].Lucas Thorpe - 2011 - In Howard Williams, Sorin Baiasu & Sami Pihlstrom (eds.), Politics and Metaphysics in Kant. Political Philosophy Now: University of Wales Press.
Leibniz.Harry G. Frankfurt - 1972 - Garden City, N.Y.,: Anchor Books.
Bodies, Matter, Monads and Things in Themselves.Nicholas Stang - 2022 - In Brandon Look (ed.), Leibniz and Kant. Oxford University Press.. pp. 142–176.
Leibniz and Kant on Possibility and Existence.Ohad Nachtomy - 2012 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 20 (5):953-972.
Kant’s third law of mechanics: The long shadow of Leibniz.Marius Stan - 2013 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 44 (3):493-504.

Analytics

Added to PP
2014-08-19

Downloads
14 (#990,629)

6 months
2 (#1,198,857)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Marco Santi
Humboldt-University, Berlin

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

No references found.

Add more references