Why Leibniz Should Have Agreed with Berkeley about Abstract Ideas

British Journal for the History of Philosophy 29 (6):1054-1071 (2021)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Leibniz claims that Berkeley “wrongly or at least pointlessly rejects abstract ideas”. What he fails to realize, however, is that some of his own core views commit him to essentially the same stance. His belief that this is the best (and thus most harmonious) possible world, which itself stems from his Principle of Sufficient Reason, leads him to infer that mind and body must perfectly represent or ‘express’ one another. In the case of abstract thoughts he admits that this can happen only in virtue of thinking of some image that, being essentially a mental copy of a brain state, expresses (and is expressed by) that state. But here he faces a problem. In order for a thought to be genuinely abstract, its representational content must differ from that of any mental image, since the latter can represent only particular things. In that case, however, an exact correspondence between the accompanying mental image and the brain state would not suffice to establish a perfect harmony between mind and body. Even on Leibniz’s own principles, then, it appears that Berkeley was right to dismiss abstract ideas.

Similar books and articles

Berkeley's theory of abstract ideas.C. C. W. Taylor - 1978 - Philosophical Quarterly 28 (111):97-115.
Berkeley on Abstract Ideas.Kenneth P. Winkler - 1983 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 65 (1):63-80.
Berkeley's Two Concepts of Impossibility: a Reply to Mckim.Peter S. Wenz - 1982 - Journal of the History of Ideas 43 (4):673.
Wenz on Abstract Ideas and Christian Neo-Platonism in Berkeley.Robert McKim - 1982 - Journal of the History of Ideas 43 (4):665.
Embodied Cognition without Causal Interaction in Leibniz.Julia Jorati - 2020 - In Dominik Perler & Sebastian Bender (eds.), Causation and Cognition in Early Modern Philosophy. London: Routledge. pp. 252–273.
Are Locke’s Abstract Ideas Fictions?Sally Ferguson - 1999 - Review of Metaphysics 53 (1):129 - 140.
Leibniz : mind-body causation and pre-established harmony.Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra - 2009 - In Robin Le Poidevin, Simons Peter, McGonigal Andrew & Ross P. Cameron (eds.), The Routledge Companion to Metaphysics. New York: Routledge. pp. 109-118.
Berkeley's philosophy of mathematics.Douglas M. Jesseph - 2005 - In Kenneth P. Winkler (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Berkeley. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 126-128.
Abstract ideas and the new theory of vision.George S. Pappas - 2002 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 10 (1):55 – 69.
Berkeley's Doctrine of the Notion.John W. Davis - 1959 - Review of Metaphysics 12 (3):378 - 389.

Analytics

Added to PP
2021-03-22

Downloads
704 (#23,165)

6 months
202 (#13,871)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Stephen Puryear
North Carolina State University

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Monadology.Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz - 1991 - Routledge. Edited by N. Rescher.
Sämtliche Schriften und Briefe.Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz - 1967 - Revista Portuguesa de Filosofia 23 (4):500-501.
The Search after Truth.Nicholas Malebranche, Thomas M. Lennon & Paul J. Olscamp - 1982 - Philosophy of Science 49 (1):146-147.
Leibniz on Causation and Agency.Julia Jorati - 2017 - New York: Cambridge University Press.

View all 34 references / Add more references