Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Berkeley.Margaret Atherton - 2018 - Hoboken: Wiley.
    Presents a concise and comprehensive analysis of George Berkeley’s thought and the impact of his intellectual contributions to philosophy In this latest addition to the Blackwell Great Minds series, noted scholar of early modern philosophy Margaret Atherton examines Berkeley’s most influential work and demonstrates the significant conceptual impact of his ideas in metaphysics and the philosophy of religion. A concise and rigorous primer on Berkeley’s essential writings and contributions to modern philosophy Written by a leading scholar of early modern philosophy (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Embodied Cognition without Causal Interaction in Leibniz.Julia Jorati - 2020 - In Dominik Perler & Sebastian Bender (eds.), Causation and Cognition in Early Modern Philosophy. London: Routledge. pp. 252–273.
    My aim in this chapter is to explain how and why all human cognition depends on the body for Leibniz. I will show that there are three types of dependence: (a) the body is needed in order to supply materials, or content, for thinking; (b) the body is needed in order to give us the opportunity for the discovery of innate ideas; and (c) the body is needed in order to provide sensory notions as vehicles of thought. The third type (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Leibniz on Concepts and Their Relation to the Senses (Leibniz über Begriffe und ihr Verhältnis zu den Sinnen).Stephen Puryear - 2008 - In Dominik Perler & Markus Wild (eds.), Sehen und Begreifen. Wahrnehmungstheorien in der Frühen Neuzeit. Berlin, Deutschland: de Gruyter. pp. 235-264.
    Despite holding that all concepts are strictly speaking innate, Leibniz attempts to accommodate the common belief that at least some concepts are adventitious by appealing to his theory of ideal action. The essential idea is that an innate concept can be considered adventitious, in a sense, just in case its ideal cause is to be found outside the mind of the one who possesses the concept. I explore this attempt at accommodation and argue that it fails. [See external link for (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Against Barbaric Physics (Antibarbarus Physicus).Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz - 1989 - In Roger Ariew & Daniel Garber (eds.), G. W. Leibniz Philosophical Essays. Hackett. pp. 312-320.
  • Berkeley's Thought.George Sotiros Pappas - 2000 - Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.
    In this highly original account of Bishop George Berkeley's epistemological and metaphysical theories, George S. Pappas seeks to determine precisely what doctrines the philosopher held and what arguments he put forward to support them. Specifically, Pappas overturns accepted opinions about Berkeley's famous attack on the Lockean doctrine of abstract ideas. Berkeley's criticism of these ideas had been thought relevant only to his views on language and to his nominalism; Pappas persuasively argues that Berkeley's ideas about abstraction are crucial to nearly (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Leibnizian expression.Chris Swoyer - 1995 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 33 (1):65-99.
  • Changing the cartesian mind: Leibniz on sensation, representation and consciousness.Alison Simmons - 2001 - Philosophical Review 110 (1):31-75.
    What did Leibniz have to contribute to the philosophy of mind? To judge from textbooks in the philosophy of mind, and even Leibniz commentaries, the answer is: not much. That may be because Leibniz’s philosophy of mind looks roughly like a Cartesian philosophy of mind. Like Descartes and his followers, Leibniz claims that the mind is immaterial and immortal; that it is a thinking thing ; that it is a different kind of thing from body and obeys its own laws; (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Spinoza, Leibniz, and the Rationalist Reconceptions of Imagination.Dennis L. Sepper - 2005 - In Alan Nelson (ed.), A Companion to Rationalism. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 322–342.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Spinoza and the Passionate Imagination Leibniz and the Logic of Imagination Wolff and the Scholasticism of Imagination Conclusion.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Leibniz on the Metaphysics of Color.Stephen Puryear - 2011 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 86 (2):319-346.
    Drawing on remarks scattered through his writings, I argue that Leibniz has a highly distinctive and interesting theory of color. The central feature of the theory is the way in which it combines a nuanced subjectivism about color with a reductive approach of a sort usually associated with objectivist theories of color. After reconstructing Leibniz's theory and calling attention to some of its most notable attractions, I turn to the apparent incompatibility of its subjective and reductive components. I argue that (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Monadic Interaction.Stephen Puryear - 2010 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 18 (5):763-796.
    Leibniz has almost universally been represented as denying that created substances, including human minds and the souls of animals, can causally interact either with one another or with bodies. Yet he frequently claims that such substances are capable of interacting in the special sense of what he calls 'ideal' interaction. In order to reconcile these claims with their favored interpretation, proponents of the traditional reading often suppose that ideal action is not in fact a genuine form of causation but instead (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Berkeley by George Pitcher. [REVIEW]Margaret Atherton - 1979 - Journal of Philosophy 76 (1):42-52.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • The Epistemological Functions of Symbolization in Leibniz’s Universal Characteristic.Christian Leduc - 2014 - Foundations of Science 19 (1):53-68.
    Leibniz’s universal characteristic is a fundamental aspect of his theory of cognition. Without symbols or characters it would be difficult for the human mind to define several concepts and to achieve many demonstrations. In most disciplines, and particularly in mathematics, the mind must then focus on symbols and their combinatorial rules rather than on mental contents. For Leibniz, mental perception is most of the time too confused for attaining distinct notions and valid deductions. In this paper, I argue that the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Locke's relations and God's good pleasure.Rae Langton - 2000 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 100 (1):75–91.
    Did God give things 'accidental powers not rooted in their natures', powers not rooted in intrinsic properties? For Leibniz, no. For Locke, the answer is disputed. On a voluntarist reading, yes, secondary and tertiary qualities are superadded (Margaret Wilson). On a mechanist reading, no, as for Leibniz (Michael Ayers). Since Locke viewed these qualities as relational, his view of relations ought to bear on the dispute. Locke said relation is 'not contained in the real existence of things'. Bennett says Locke (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Berkeley on abstraction.Daniel E. Flage - 1986 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 24 (4):483-501.
  • The Role of Visual Language in Berkeley’s Account of Generality.Katherine Dunlop - 2011 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 83 (3):525-559.
  • Leibniz and the Veridicality of Body Perceptions.Kenneth L. Pearce - 2016 - Philosophers' Imprint 16.
    According to Leibniz's late metaphysics, sensory perception represents to us as extended, colored, textured, etc., a world which fundamentally consists only of non-spatial, colorless entities, the monads. It is a short step from here to the conclusion that sensory perception radically misleads us about the true nature of reality. In this paper, I argue that this oft-repeated claim is false. Leibniz holds that in typical cases of body perception the bodies perceived really exist and have the qualities, both primary and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Monadology.Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz - 1991 - Routledge. Edited by N. Rescher.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   82 citations  
  • Discourse on metaphysics.Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz - 2007 - In Aloysius Martinich, Fritz Allhoff & Anand Vaidya (eds.), Philosophy. Blackwell. pp. 81-84.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  • Principle of Sufficient Reason.Yitzhak Melamed & Martin Lin - unknown - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    The Principle of Sufficient Reason is a powerful and controversial philosophical principle stipulating that everything must have a reason or cause. This simple demand for thoroughgoing intelligibility yields some of the boldest and most challenging theses in the history of metaphysics and epistemology. In this entry we begin with explaining the Principle, and then turn to the history of the debates around it. A section on recent discussions of the Principle will be added in the near future.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Sämtliche Schriften und Briefe.Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz - 1967 - Revista Portuguesa de Filosofia 23 (4):500-501.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   130 citations  
  • Leibniz on Sensation and the Limits of Reason.Walter Ott - 2016 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 33 (2):135-153.
    I argue that Leibniz’s doctrine of sensory representation is intended in part to close an explanatory gap in his philosophical system. Unlike the twentieth century explanatory gap, which stretches between neural states on one side and phenomenal character on the other, Leibniz’s gap lies between experiences of secondary qualities like color and taste and the objects that cause them. The problem is that the precise arrangement and distribution of such experiences can never be given a full explanation. In response, Leibniz (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Berkeley's Anti-Abstractionism.Margaret Atherton - 1987 - In Ernest Sosa (ed.), Essays on the Philosophy of George Berkeley. D. Reidel.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge.George Berkeley - 1901 - The Monist 11:637.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   318 citations  
  • Berkeley : The Central Arguments.A. C. GRAYLING - 1986 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 50 (1):181-181.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The Search after Truth.Nicholas Malebranche, Thomas M. Lennon & Paul J. Olscamp - 1982 - Philosophy of Science 49 (1):146-147.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   112 citations  
  • Leibniz's Conception of Expression.Mark A. Kulstad - 1977 - Studia Leibnitiana 9 (1):55 - 76.
    Dieser Aufsatz analysiert Leibniz' Begriff der Expression. Er ist eine Vorstudie zu einer umfassenden Untersuchung der Lehre, daß jede einfache Substanz das ganze Weltall ausdrückt. Leibnizens Beispiele und Definitionen von Expression werden besprochen, und dann wird die Analyse des Begriffs in zwei Stufen entwickelt.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Leibniz: An Introduction.C. D. Broad & C. Lewy - 1975 - Studia Leibnitiana 7 (2):297-299.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Are mind body relations natural and intelligible? Some early modern perspectives.Pauline Phemister - 2011 - In Keith Allen & Tom Stoneham (eds.), Causation and Modern Philosophy. Routledge. pp. 87-103.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Monadology (1714).Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz - unknown
    Copyright © 2010–2015 All rights reserved. Jonathan Bennett [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small ·dots· enclose material that has been added, but can be read as though it were part of the original text. Occasional •bullets, and also indenting of passages that are not quotations, are meant as aids to grasping the structure of a sentence or a thought. Every four-point ellipsis . . . . indicates the omission of a brief passage that seems to present more difficulty than it is (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations