Hume on Curing Superstition

Hume Studies 12 (2):122-140 (1986)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:122 HUME ON CURING SUPERSTITION In the first volume of his masterful treatment of the Enlightenment Peter Gay says that "David Hume proclaimed philosophy the supreme, indeed the only, cure for superstition." The context suggests that Hume had great "confidence" in this project and that he shared Diderot's view of the philosopher as the apostle of truth who would teach all mankind. Certainly Hume, in common with his philosophical compatriots, thought that superstition was a great evil. He may also have thought that philosophy was the best weapon with which to oppose superstition. But did he think that it was a "cure" and that the philosopher was a pathfinder for a new and glorious dawn of universal enlightenment? He seems rather to have held a somewhat more modest and circumspect view of what philosophy can accomplish by way of liberating humanity from superstition than did some of his more optimistic contemporaries — a view 2 worthy of closer examination. The purpose of this paper is to explain just what he did think by examining those texts where he writes about the curative virtues of philosophy. So that any shifts in Hume's views may be more apparent, the relevant passages will be considered according to their chronological order. In the conclusion to Book I of the Treatise (1738) Hume characterizes the results of his reasoning as a "forelorn solitude" in which he is separated, not only from the crowd, and from "metaphysicians, logicians, mathematicians, and even theologians," but also from philosophers, who, like all others, follow the inconsistent dictates of imagination in alternating between belief in the continual existence of sensible matter and the 123 reliability of causal reasoning, which teaches us that sensible objects are in us, rather than in external nature (T 265-6). His own philosophical reflections have led to the realization that even the causal "connexion, tie, or energy lies merely in themselves," as certainly as do sensed qualities. Thus the philosophical quest itself, which seeks a knowledge of "the ultimate and operating principle... which resides in the external object," is revealed as a contradictory or meaningless enterprise. We are left with a "very dangerous dilemma, whichever way we answer it," whose horns are precisely superstition and philosophy. That is, we may either "assent to every trivial suggestion of the fancy... often contrary to each other... [which will] lead us into such errors, absurdities, and obscurities, that we must at last become asham'd of our credulity;" or we may "take a resolution to reject all the trivial suggestions of the fancy, and adhere to the understanding" which will lead us to the conclusion that there is "not the lowest degree of evidence in any proposition, either in philosophy or common life" (T 266-8). He believes that philosophy has come to an impasse which he does not know how to escape, and which we commonly deal with by simply ceasing to think about the problem, finding ourselves "absolutely and necessarily determin'd to live, and talk, and act like other people in the common affairs of life" (T 269). Observation of the actual effects of philosophy upon conduct warrants the conclusion that "refin'd reflections have little or no influence upon us," excepting, of course, for that brief time in which those reflections leave us quite agitated and confounded by our inability to provide answers to the questions which most trouble us. 124 Philosophy is here characterized, not as a cure for superstition, but as an equal and opposite mental disposition, whose reflections ultimately undermine its own rational credentials, so that they seem no more valid than those of superstition. He does indeed resort to the therapeutic metaphor, but only to make nature the physician which "cures me of this philosophical melancholy and delirium" by applying that "carelessness and inattention" which he earlier identified as that which "alone can afford us any remedy" for philosophical despair (T 218). So philosophy is itself in need of the cure afforded by amusement and the various "common affairs of life" with which gentlemen occupy themselves. When engaged in those pursuits, philosophy seems individually and socially useless, in effect "an abuse of time" (T 270). If one returns to...

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,475

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Religion and Hume's legacy.D. Z. Phillips & Timothy Tessin (eds.) - 1999 - New York: St. Martin's Press, Scholarly and Reference Division.
Plutarch on superstition.Howard Armin Moellering - 1963 - Boston,: Christopher Pub. House.
The Phenomenology of Superstition or a Phenomenological Superstition?Elena Ibáñez-Guerra - 2008 - Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 15 (3):251-254.
Liability in the Care of the Elderly.P. Iyer - 2004 - Hume Studies 33 (1):124-131.
`In every civilized community': Hume on belief and the demise of religion.Timothy M. Costelloe - 2004 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 55 (3):171-185.
Hume’s Empiricism and the Rationality of Induction.João Paulo Monteiro - 2000 - The Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 7:139-149.
Hume on morality.James Baillie - 2000 - New York: Routledge.
Hume = small Hume.Jeffrey Ketland - 2002 - Analysis 62 (1):92–93.
Writings on religion.David Hume - 1992 - La Salle, Ill.: Open Court. Edited by Antony Flew.

Analytics

Added to PP
2011-01-09

Downloads
18 (#824,856)

6 months
2 (#1,202,576)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Citations of this work

In What Sense are Errors in Philosophy ‘Only Ridiculous’?Lisa Ievers - 2014 - Journal of Scottish Philosophy 12 (2):213-229.

Add more citations

References found in this work

No references found.

Add more references