Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. On Hamblin's 15 Tense Theorem.Manfred Kudlek - 2010 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 20 (1):63-80.
    It is demonstrated that Hamblin's 15 tense theorem does not only hold for temporal logic with linear time but also for branching time. Furthermore three other theorems with finitely many tenses are shown.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Early Formation of Modal Logic and its Significance: A Historical Note on Quine, Carnap, and a Bit of Church.Adam Tamas Tuboly - 2018 - History and Philosophy of Logic 39 (3):289-304.
    The aim of the paper is to show that W. V. O. Quine's animadversions against modal logic did not get the same attention that is considered to be the case nowadays. The community of logicians focused solely on the technical aspects of C. I. Lewis’ systems and did not take Quine's arguments and remarks seriously—or at least seriously enough to respond. In order to assess Quine's place in the history, however, his relation to Carnap is considered since their notorious break (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Decidability of four modal logics.Krister Segerberg - 1968 - Theoria 34 (1):21-25.
  • Decidability of S4.1.Krister Segerberg - 1968 - Theoria 34 (1):7-20.
  • Decidability of S4.1.Kit Fine - 1974 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 39 (3):611-612.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Decidability of S4.1.Krister Segerberg - 1968 - Theoria 34 (1):7-20.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • BI‐Modal Logic, Double‐Closure Algebras, and Hilbert Space.Jean E. Rubin - 1962 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 8 (3‐4):305-322.
  • Peirce’s Contributions to Possible-Worlds Semantics.Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen - 2006 - Studia Logica 82 (3):345 - 369.
    A century ago, Charles S. Peirce proposed a logical approach to modalities that came close to possible-worlds semantics. This paper investigates his views on modalities through his diagrammatic logic of Existential Graphs (EGs). The contribution of the gamma part of EGs to the study of modalities is examined. Some ramifications of Peirce’s remarks are presented and placed into a contemporary perspective. An appendix is included that provides a transcription with commentary of Peirce’s unpublished manuscript on modality from 1901.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Peirce’s Contributions to Possible-Worlds Semantics.Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen - 2006 - Studia Logica 82 (3):345-369.
    A century ago, Charles S. Peirce proposed a logical approach to modalities that came close to possible-worlds semantics. This paper investigates his views on modalities through his diagrammatic logic of Existential Graphs. The contribution of the GAMMA part of EGs to the study of modalities is examined. Some ramifications of Peirce's remarks are presented and placed into a contemporary perspective. An appendix is included that provides a transcription with commentary of Peirce's unpublished manuscript on modality from 1901.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Modality, analogy, and ideal experiments according to C. S. Peirce.Charles G. Morgan - 1979 - Synthese 41 (1):65 - 83.
  • Which Modal Logic Is the Right One?John P. Burgess - 1999 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 40 (1):81-93.
    The question, "Which modal logic is the right one for logical necessity?," divides into two questions, one about model-theoretic validity, the other about proof-theoretic demonstrability. The arguments of Halldén and others that the right validity argument is S5, and the right demonstrability logic includes S4, are reviewed, and certain common objections are argued to be fallacious. A new argument, based on work of Supecki and Bryll, is presented for the claim that the right demonstrability logic must be contained in S5, (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Supervenience, Dependence, Disjunction.Lloyd Humberstone - forthcoming - Logic and Logical Philosophy:1.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Idempotent Variations on the Theme of Exclusive Disjunction.L. Humberstone - 2021 - Studia Logica 110 (1):121-163.
    An exclusive disjunction is true when exactly one of the disjuncts is true. In the case of the familiar binary exclusive disjunction, we have a formula occurring as the first disjunct and a formula occurring as the second disjunct, so, if what we have is two formula-tokens of the same formula-type—one formula occurring twice over, that is—the question arises as to whether, when that formula is true, to count the case as one in which exactly one of the disjuncts is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Modal translation of substructural logics.Chrysafis Hartonas - 2020 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 30 (1):16-49.
    In an article dating back in 1992, Kosta Došen initiated a project of modal translations in substructural logics, aiming at generalising the well-known Gödel–McKinsey–Tarski translation of intuitionistic logic into S4. Došen's translation worked well for (variants of) BCI and stronger systems (BCW, BCK), but not for systems below BCI. Dropping structural rules results in logic systems without distribution. In this article, we show, via translation, that every substructural (indeed, every non-distributive) logic is a fragment of a corresponding sorted, residuated (multi) (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Lattice logic as a fragment of (2-sorted) residuated modal logic.Chrysafis Hartonas - 2019 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 29 (2):152-170.
    ABSTRACTCorrespondence and Shalqvist theories for Modal Logics rely on the simple observation that a relational structure is at the same time the basis for a model of modal logic and for a model of first-order logic with a binary predicate for the accessibility relation. If the underlying set of the frame is split into two components,, and, then frames are at the same time the basis for models of non-distributive lattice logic and of two-sorted, residuated modal logic. This suggests that (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The McKinsey–Lemmon logic is barely canonical.Robert Goldblatt & Ian Hodkinson - 2007 - Australasian Journal of Logic 5:1-19.
    We study a canonical modal logic introduced by Lemmon, and axiomatised by an infinite sequence of axioms generalising McKinsey’s formula. We prove that the class of all frames for this logic is not closed under elementary equivalence, and so is non-elementary. We also show that any axiomatisation of the logic involves infinitely many non-canonical formulas.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Mathematical modal logic: A view of its evolution.Robert Goldblatt - 2003 - Journal of Applied Logic 1 (5-6):309-392.
  • Intuitionistic logic and modality via topology.Leo Esakia - 2004 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 127 (1-3):155-170.
    In the pioneering article and two papers, written jointly with McKinsey, Tarski developed the so-called algebraic and topological frameworks for the Intuitionistic Logic and the Lewis modal system. In this paper, we present an outline of modern systems with a topological tinge. We consider topological interpretation of basic systems GL and G of the provability logic in terms of the Cantor derivative and the Hausdorff residue.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • On McKinsey's syntatical characterizations of systems of modal logic.F. R. Drake - 1962 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 27 (4):400-406.
  • How meaningful are modal operators?David Makinson - 1966 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 44 (3):331 – 337.
    A philosophical discussion of the intuitive meaning of the formalism of modal propositional logics.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The Interpretation of Formalized Implication.Haskell B. Curry - 1959 - Theoria 25 (1):1-26.
  • The interpretation of some Lewis systems of modal logic.M. J. Cresswell - 1967 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 45 (2):198 – 206.
  • The genesis of possible worlds semantics.B. Jack Copeland - 2002 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 31 (2):99-137.
    This article traces the development of possible worlds semantics through the work of: Wittgenstein, 1913-1921; Feys, 1924; McKinsey, 1945; Carnap, 1945-1947; McKinsey, Tarski and Jónsson, 1947-1952; von Wright, 1951; Becker, 1952; Prior, 1953-1954; Montague, 1955; Meredith and Prior, 1956; Geach, 1960; Smiley, 1955-1957; Kanger, 1957; Hintikka, 1957; Guillaume, 1958; Binkley, 1958; Bayart, 1958-1959; Drake, 1959-1961; Kripke, 1958-1965.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • Which Modal Models are the Right Ones (for Logical Necessity)?John P. Burgess - 2010 - Theoria 18 (2):145-158.
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Russell and his sources for non-classical logics.Irving H. Anellis - 2009 - Logica Universalis 3 (2):153-218.
    My purpose here is purely historical. It is not an attempt to resolve the question as to whether Russell did or did not countenance nonclassical logics, and if so, which nonclassical logics, and still less to demonstrate whether he himself contributed, in any manner, to the development of nonclassical logic. Rather, I want merely to explore and insofar as possible document, whether, and to what extent, if any, Russell interacted with the various, either the various candidates or their, ideas that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Modern Origins of Modal Logic.Roberta Ballarin - 2010 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Which modal models are the right ones (for logical necessity)?John P. Burgess - 2003 - Theoria 18 (2):145-158.
    Recently it has become almost the received wisdom in certain quarters that Kripke models are appropriate only for something like metaphysical modalities, and not for logical modalities. Here the line of thought leading to Kripke models, and reasons why they are no less appropriate for logical than for other modalities, are explained. It is also indicated where the fallacy in the argument leading to the contrary conclusion lies. The lessons learned are then applied to the question of the status of (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Preface.Matteo Pascucci & Adam Tamas Tuboly - 2019 - Organon F: Medzinárodný Časopis Pre Analytickú Filozofiu 26 (3):318-322.
    Special issue: "Reflecting on the Legacy of C.I. Lewis: Contemporary and Historical Perspectives on Modal Logic".
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark