Results for ' 68Q30'

5 found
Order:
  1.  54
    Truth-table Schnorr randomness and truth-table reducible randomness.Kenshi Miyabe - 2011 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 57 (3):323-338.
    Schnorr randomness and computable randomness are natural concepts of random sequences. However van Lambalgen’s Theorem fails for both randomnesses. In this paper we define truth-table Schnorr randomness and truth-table reducible randomness, for which we prove that van Lambalgen's Theorem holds. We also show that the classes of truth-table Schnorr random reals relative to a high set contain reals Turing equivalent to the high set. It follows that each high Schnorr random real is half of a real for which van Lambalgen's (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  2.  19
    Characterizing Lowness for Demuth Randomness.Laurent Bienvenu, Rod Downey, Noam Greenberg, André Nies & Dan Turetsky - 2014 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 79 (2):526-560.
    We show the existence of noncomputable oracles which are low for Demuth randomness, answering a question in [15] (also Problem 5.5.19 in [34]). We fully characterize lowness for Demuth randomness using an appropriate notion of traceability. Central to this characterization is a partial relativization of Demuth randomness, which may be more natural than the fully relativized version. We also show that an oracle is low for weak Demuth randomness if and only if it is computable.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  3.  13
    Some Consequences of And.Yinhe Peng, W. U. Liuzhen & Y. U. Liang - 2023 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 88 (4):1573-1589.
    Strong Turing Determinacy, or ${\mathrm {sTD}}$, is the statement that for every set A of reals, if $\forall x\exists y\geq _T x (y\in A)$, then there is a pointed set $P\subseteq A$. We prove the following consequences of Turing Determinacy ( ${\mathrm {TD}}$ ) and ${\mathrm {sTD}}$ over ${\mathrm {ZF}}$ —the Zermelo–Fraenkel axiomatic set theory without the Axiom of Choice: (1) ${\mathrm {ZF}}+{\mathrm {TD}}$ implies $\mathrm {wDC}_{\mathbb {R}}$ —a weaker version of $\mathrm {DC}_{\mathbb {R}}$.(2) ${\mathrm {ZF}}+{\mathrm {sTD}}$ implies that every (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  7
    Regainingly Approximable Numbers and Sets.Peter Hertling, Rupert Hölzl & Philip Janicki - forthcoming - Journal of Symbolic Logic.
    We call an $\alpha \in \mathbb {R}$ regainingly approximable if there exists a computable nondecreasing sequence $(a_n)_n$ of rational numbers converging to $\alpha $ with $\alpha - a_n n}$ for infinitely many n. Similarly, there exist regainingly approximable sets whose initial segment complexity infinitely often reaches the maximum possible for c.e. sets. Finally, there is a uniform algorithm splitting regular real numbers into two regainingly approximable numbers that are still regular.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  12
    Degrees of randomized computability.Rupert Hölzl & Christopher P. Porter - 2022 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 28 (1):27-70.
    In this survey we discuss work of Levin and V’yugin on collections of sequences that are non-negligible in the sense that they can be computed by a probabilistic algorithm with positive probability. More precisely, Levin and V’yugin introduced an ordering on collections of sequences that are closed under Turing equivalence. Roughly speaking, given two such collections $\mathcal {A}$ and $\mathcal {B}$, $\mathcal {A}$ is below $\mathcal {B}$ in this ordering if $\mathcal {A}\setminus \mathcal {B}$ is negligible. The degree structure associated (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark