Theoretical Relicts: Progress, Reduction, and Autonomy

British Journal for the Philosophy of Science (forthcoming)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

When once-successful physical theories are abandoned, common wisdom has it that their characteristic theoretical entities are abandoned with them: examples include phlogiston, light rays, Newtonian forces, Euclidean space. But sometimes a theory sees ongoing use, despite being superseded. What should scientific realists say about the characteristic entities of the theories in such cases? The standard answer is that these ‘theoretical relicts’ are merely useful fictions. In this paper we offer a different answer. We start by distinguishing horizontal reduction (in which a superseded theory approximates the successor theory) from vertical reduction (in which a higher-level theory abstracts away from the lower-level theory, but nonetheless can be constructed from it); these are usually regarded as having different ontological consequences. We describe a ‘verticalization’ procedure which transforms horizontal reductions into vertical reductions. The resulting verticalized theories are abstractions rather than approximations, with restricted domains. We identify a sense in which the higher-level theory describes distinct subject matters from the lower-level theory, enabling in certain cases the higher-level theory to retain distinctive explanatory power even in the presence of reduction. We suggest that theoretical entities from superseded theories should be retained in a scientific realist worldview just when, reinterpreted as higher-level abstractions, those theories and their characteristic entities continue to perform distinctive explanatory work in providing the best explanation for less-fundamental phenomena of interest. In slogan form: a good relict is an emergent relict.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,628

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

What is theoretical progress of science?Juha Saatsi - 2019 - Synthese 196 (2):611-631.
Autonomy, reduction and the artificiality of mental properties.Francis X. Williamson - 1998 - South African Journal of Philosophy 17 (1):1-7.
The ontological autonomy of the chemical world.Olimpia Lombardi & Martín Labarca - 2004 - Foundations of Chemistry 7 (2):125-148.
Women's reproductive autonomy: medicalisation and beyond.L. Purdy - 2006 - Journal of Medical Ethics 32 (5):287-291.
The autonomy of chemistry: old and new problems. [REVIEW]Rein Vihalemm - 2010 - Foundations of Chemistry 13 (2):97-107.
Algebra of Theoretical Term Reductions in the Sciences.Dale Jacquette - 2014 - Symposion: Theoretical and Applied Inquiries in Philosophy and Social Sciences 1 (1): 51-67.
The Evolution of Autonomy.Trevor Stammers - 2015 - The New Bioethics 21 (2):155-163.
Kantian Harm Reduction.Sarah Hoffman - 2020 - Health Care Analysis 28 (4):335-342.

Analytics

Added to PP
2023-03-19

Downloads
56 (#284,244)

6 months
39 (#97,986)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author Profiles

Citations of this work

Effective Ontic Structural Realism.James Ladyman & Lorenzo Lorenzetti - forthcoming - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Every Thing Must Go: Metaphysics Naturalized.James Ladyman & Don Ross - 2007 - In James Ladyman & Don Ross (eds.), Every thing must go: metaphysics naturalized. New York: Oxford University Press.
Mental causation.Stephen Yablo - 1992 - Philosophical Review 101 (2):245-280.
Unity of Science as a Working Hypothesis.Paul Oppenheim & Hilary Putnam - 1958 - Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 2:3-36.
Explanatory unification.Philip Kitcher - 1981 - Philosophy of Science 48 (4):507-531.

View all 54 references / Add more references