On Experiencing Meanings

Southern Journal of Philosophy 53 (4):481-492 (2015)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Do we perceptually experience meanings? For example, when we hear an utterance of a sentence like ‘Bertrand is British’ do we hear its meaning in the sense of being auditorily aware of it? Several philosophers like Tim Bayne and Susanna Siegel have suggested that we do (Bayne 2009: 390, Siegel 2006: 490-491, 2011: 99-100). They argue roughly as follows: 1) experiencing speech/writing in a language you are incompetent in is phenomenally different from experiencing speech/writing you are competent in; 2) this contrast is best explained by the fact that we experience meanings in the latter case, but not the former. In contrast, in an important recent discussion Casey O’Callaghan has argued that we do not (O’Callaghan 2011). He responds to the above contrast argument by claiming that this phenomenal contrast is instead best explained by the fact that we hear language-specific phonological properties in the latter case, but not in the former. In this paper I argue that O’Callaghan’s response to the popular contrast argument is too limited in scope, provide a more general response, and present a new case against experiencing meanings.

Similar books and articles

On Experiencing High-Level Properties.Indrek Reiland - 2014 - American Philosophical Quarterly 51 (3):177-187.
Against hearing meanings.Casey O'Callaghan - 2011 - Philosophical Quarterly 61 (245):783-807.
Wittgenstein on seeing aspects and experiencing meanings.David B. Seligman - 1976 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 37 (2):205-217.
Meaning and Compositional Structure.Gary Martin Ebbs - 1988 - Dissertation, University of Michigan
Grammar, Ontology, and the Unity of Meaning.Ulrich Reichard - 2013 - Dissertation, University of Durham
Can we see natural kind properties?René Jagnow - 2015 - Epistemology and Philosophy of Science 44 (2):183-205.
Unarticulated meaning.James Blachowicz - 1994 - Erkenntnis 40 (1):43 - 70.
Experiencing speech.Casey O’Callaghan - 2010 - Philosophical Issues 20 (1):305-332.
Intention, meaning and truth-conditions.Robert Cummins - 1979 - Philosophical Studies 35 (4):345 - 360.
Lakṣaṇā as a Creative Function of Language.Nirmalya Guha - 2012 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 40 (5):489-509.
What Is a Text?: A Pragmatic Theory.Mark Bevir - 2002 - International Philosophical Quarterly 42 (4):493-508.
John Dewey's Developmental Account of Meaning.Martin A. Coleman - 2003 - Dissertation, Southern Illinois University at Carbondale

Analytics

Added to PP
2015-10-06

Downloads
697 (#23,715)

6 months
93 (#49,168)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Indrek Reiland
University of Vienna

Citations of this work

In defense of hearing meanings.Berit Brogaard - 2018 - Synthese 195 (7):2967-2983.
On experiencing moral properties.Indrek Reiland - 2021 - Synthese 198 (1):315-325.
Do we hear meanings? – between perception and cognition.Anna Drożdżowicz - 2019 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 66 (2):196-228.
On what we experience when we hear people speak.Anders Nes - 2016 - Phenomenology and Mind 10:58-85.

View all 18 citations / Add more citations

References found in this work

How to do things with words.John Langshaw Austin - 1962 - Oxford [Eng.]: Clarendon Press. Edited by Marina Sbisá & J. O. Urmson.
Demonstratives: An Essay on the Semantics, Logic, Metaphysics and Epistemology of Demonstratives and other Indexicals.David Kaplan - 1989 - In Joseph Almog, John Perry & Howard Wettstein (eds.), Themes From Kaplan. Oxford University Press. pp. 481-563.
Studies in the way of words.Herbert Paul Grice - 1989 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Themes From Kaplan.Joseph Almog, John Perry & Howard Wettstein (eds.) - 1989 - New York: Oxford University Press.
The Contents of Visual Experience.Susanna Siegel - 2010 - , US: Oxford University Press USA.

View all 22 references / Add more references