A theory of normal and ideal conditions

Philosophical Studies 96 (1):21-44 (1999)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

It is a priori on many accounts of colour concepts that something is red if and only if it is such that it would look red to normal observers in normal circumstances: it is such that it would look red, as we can say, under normal conditions of observation. And as this sort of formula is widely applied to colour concepts, so similar schemas are commonly defended in relation to a variety of other concepts too. Not only are colour concepts connected in such a fashion with human responses, so by many accounts are secondary quality concepts in general; aesthetic concepts, moral concepts and evaluative concepts of all kinds; modal concepts that serve to pick out the possible and the necessary; and so on. The fashion for resorting to such formulas should not be surprising. Most of us suppose that whether a given, ostensively introduced term has a certain semantic value – whether, for example, it designates a certain property – ought to show up in people’s tending to use it of things, and only of things, that apparently have that property. The obvious way of expressing this expectation is to require that the use of the ostensive term covary with the presence of the property in conditions that are normal in some sense for detecting that property. Thus there is prima facie reason to hold, and hold as an a priori matter, that for any ostensively introduced term, ‘P’, something is P if and only if it is such that it would seem P – people would be disposed to use ‘P’ to ascribe the corresponding property to it – under normal conditions of observation. The schemas invoked under this motivation may vary in many different ways, of course. First, they may not connect the bare or simple reality of being P with a normalised human response, as Philosophical Studies 96: 21–44, 1999. © 1999 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands. 22.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,928

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

On the dual referent approach to colour theory.Derek H. Brown - 2006 - Philosophical Quarterly 56 (222):96-113.
Looks as powers.Philip Pettit - 2003 - Philosophical Issues 13 (1):221-52.
Colour for representationalists.Frank Jackson - 2007 - Erkenntnis 66 (1-2):169--85.
Response-Dependence.Christine Tappolet & Roberto Casati - 1998 - European Review of Philosophy 3:227.
A modest solution to the problem of rule-following.Frank A. Hindriks - 2004 - Philosophical Studies 121 (1):65-98.
A note on a result of Kunen and Pelletier.Julius B. Barbanel - 1992 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 57 (2):461-465.
Response-Intentionalism About Color.Nenad Miščević - 2004 - Croatian Journal of Philosophy 4 (2):179-191.
Dispositions and normal conditions.Jan Hauska - 2008 - Philosophical Studies 139 (2):219 - 232.
How (not) to specify normal conditions for response-dependent concepts.Jussi Haukioja - 2007 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 85 (2):325 – 331.

Analytics

Added to PP
2009-01-28

Downloads
78 (#213,402)

6 months
2 (#1,198,893)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Philip Pettit
Australian National University

References found in this work

Assertion.Robert Stalnaker - 1978 - Syntax and Semantics (New York Academic Press) 9:315-332.
Assertion.Robert Stalnaker - 1978 - In Maite Ezcurdia & Robert J. Stainton (eds.), The Semantics-Pragmatics Boundary in Philosophy. Broadview Press. pp. 179.
Dispositional Theories of Value.Michael Smith, David Lewis & Mark Johnston - 1989 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 63 (1):89-174.
Realism and response-dependence.Philip Pettit - 1991 - Mind 100 (4):587-626.

View all 8 references / Add more references