Normativity, system-integration, natural detachment and the hybrid hominin

Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 20 (1):21-37 (2020)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

From a subjective point of view, we take the existence of integrated entities, i.e., ourselves as the most unproblematic given, and blithely project such integrity onto untold many “entities” far and wide. However, from a naturalistic perspective, accounting for anything more integral than the attachments and attractions that are explicable in terms of the four fundamental forces of physics has been anything but straightforward. If we take it that the universe begins as an integral unity and explodes into progressive stages of internal detachment, then we can also fathom the idea that eddies of relative detachment becoming increasingly integral. Helmuth Plessner made a powerful case for the onset of “positionality” constituting one of the major transitions in nature. Surely, the emergence of “entities” that position themselves in relation to their surround marks a decisive transition in relative levels of detachment and some would say “autonomy.” It would follow, with no less force, that where and when entities can be seen to be normatively integrated, and indeed to be the agents of their own normativity, that another threshold of detachment has been crossed. The paper introduces and explores the idea that normativity, embedded in a wide-ranging theory of natural detachment, can be considered an emergent force of nature that is requisite to accounting for levels of integration beyond that which is explicable in terms of the four fundamental forces of physics. Following this line of enquiry, we argue that the first expression of a fully, normatively-integrated life-form is neither a spoken language user nor for that matter an individual but rather the neoteny-based, Homo erectus Group. In so doing we claim to have made an inroad into embedding the force of normativity into a wide-ranging naturalist framework, to have provided philosophical anthropology with a new point of departure, and at least playfully, to have given some naturalistic grist to Hegel’s proclamation that spirit is the truth of nature.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,709

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

A simplified form of condensed detachment.M. W. Bunder - 1995 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 4 (2):169-173.
Law and the Normativity of Obligation.Thomas Pink - 2014 - Jurisprudence 5 (1):1-28.
Two Objections to Wide-Scoping.Daan Evers - 2011 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 83 (1):251-255.
Deontic Logic with Defeasible Detachment.Xiaochang Yu - 1995 - Dissertation, University of Georgia
The Dialectics of Myth.Aleksei Losev - 2001 - Russian Studies in Philosophy 40 (3):4-29.
The two-property and condensed detachment.J. A. Kalman - 1982 - Studia Logica 41 (2-3):173 - 179.
Legal Positivism and the Normativity of Law.Guangwei Ouyang - 1996 - Dissertation, University of Alberta (Canada)
Ethiek en onthechting.Xavier Vanmechelen - 2009 - Bijdragen 70 (3):337-358.
The Epistemology of Illumination in Meister Eckhart.Michael Kurak - 2001 - Philosophy and Theology 13 (2):275-286.

Analytics

Added to PP
2020-06-19

Downloads
23 (#679,329)

6 months
10 (#263,328)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Lenny Moss
University of Exeter

References found in this work

Facing up to the problem of consciousness.David Chalmers - 1995 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 2 (3):200-19.
Facing up to the problem of consciousness.D. J. Chalmers - 1996 - Toward a Science of Consciousness:5-28.
A Spirit of Trust: A Reading of Hegel’s phenomenology.Robert Brandom - 2019 - Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.
Ontogeny and Phylogeny.Stephen Jay Gould - 1978 - Philosophy of Science 45 (4):652-653.

View all 15 references / Add more references