Conflicting and complementary conceptions of discursive practice in non-metaphysical interpretations of Hegel

Philosophy and Social Criticism 39 (6):559-576 (2013)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Pippin, Pinkard and Brandom are rightly seen as representatives of a distinct approach in contemporary Hegel scholarship. Still, their interpretations diverge due to different definitions and uses of conceptions of discursive practice. We focus on three ways in which such definitions and uses bear on their interpretations. First, while Lumsden has recently criticized Pinkard and Brandom for ‘discursive bias’ in their accounts of the contestation and upheaval of normative authority in Hegel’s Phenomenology, we note that Pinkard distinguishes between various modes of reason-giving, and we argue that a further qualification of interdependencies between these modes may support his interpretation against such criticism. Second, Pinkard and Pippin have recently criticized Brandom’s conception of discursive score-keeping practice, and Pippin in particular has argued that the latter rests on an individualistic reductionism about content foreign to Hegel. However, we find that the real issue is that the modes of methodological abstraction and idealization assumed for Brandom’s conception of discursive practice leave out of account the historical alteration as well as the institutional embodiment of normative authority as emphasized by Pippin and Pinkard. Third, while Pippin and Pinkard both make Hegel’s notion of modern ethical life bear on a conception of practical rationality, their uses of a conception of discursive practice in such an undertaking betray divergent conceptions of the sociality of rational agents.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,853

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

‘Hegel’s Epistemology? Reflections on Some Recent Expositions’.Kenneth R. Westphal - 1999 - Clio: A Journal of Literature, History, and the Philosophy of History 28 (3):303-323.
Phenomenology and De Re Interpretation: A Critique of Brandom’s Reading of Hegel.Stephen Houlgate - 2009 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 17 (1):29 – 47.
On participation and membership in discursive practices.Kenneth Shockley - 2006 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 36 (1):67-85.
Habermas and Kant: Judgement and communicative experience.Ståle R. S. Finke - 2000 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 26 (6):21-45.
Philosophy of medical practice: A discursive approach.Evert Van Leeuwen & Gerrit K. Kimsma - 1997 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 18 (1-2):99-112.
Tales of the mighty tautologists?Frank Scalambrino - 2012 - Normative Funtionalism and the Pittsburgh School.

Analytics

Added to PP
2013-01-25

Downloads
134 (#137,315)

6 months
6 (#520,848)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Citations of this work

Capitalism as a space of reasons: Analytic, neo-Hegelian Marxism?Justin Evans - 2021 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 47 (7):789-813.
The spirit of ethical life as syllogism.Anna Katsman - forthcoming - Philosophy and Social Criticism.
Hegel, Political Theology and Apocalypticism.Thomas Lynch - 2014 - Dissertation, Durham University

Add more citations

References found in this work

Articulating reasons: an introduction to inferentialism.Robert Brandom - 2000 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Making it Explicit.Isaac Levi & Robert B. Brandom - 1996 - Journal of Philosophy 93 (3):145.
Articulating Reasons: An Introduction to Inferentialism.Robert Brandom - 2000 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Reason in philosophy: animating ideas.Robert Brandom - 2009 - Cambridge, Mass.: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

View all 21 references / Add more references