Results for 'Friderike Heuer'

130 found
Order:
  1.  31
    The quantity, not the quality, of affect predicts memory vividness.Daniel Reisberg, Friderike Heuer, John Mclean & Mark O’Shaughnessy - 1988 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 26 (2):100-103.
  2.  5
    Total global?: Ethnologie, bildungsarbeit und ethische kontexte im globalisierungszeitalter.Friderike Seithel - 2006 - In Annette Hornbacher (ed.), Ethik, Ethos, Ethnos: Aspekte Und Probleme Interkultureller Ethik. Transcript Verlag. pp. 233-260.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. The ‘Arguments Instead of Intuitions’ Account of Thought Experiments.Friderik Klampfer - 2018 - Croatian Journal of Philosophy 18 (1):191-203.
    After decades of receiving a lot of attention on the epistemological level, the so-called ‘problem of intuitions’ is now in the center of debates on the metaphilosophical level. One of the reasons for this lies in the unfruitfulness of the epistemological discussions that recently subsided without producing any significant or broadly accepted theory of intuitions. Consequently, the metaphilosophical level of discussion of the ‘problem of intuitions’ inherits the same difficulties of the epistemological level. The significance of Max Deutsch’s book The (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4.  22
    The Counterproductiveness Argument against Animal Rights Violence.Nico Müller & Friderike Spang - forthcoming - Journal of Applied Philosophy.
    Arguments against inflicting violence on people to defend animal rights have relied on the view that inflicting violence is always wrong. But these arguments end up prohibiting too much, as defensive violence should be permissible in certain extreme cases. We argue that considerations about the counterproductiveness of defensive violence are better at distinguishing permissible and impermissible instances of animal rights violence than a blanket rejection of violence. We respond to the objection that assuming violence to be counterproductive is ad hoc, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. Consequentializing Moral Responsibility.Friderik Klampfer - 2014 - Croatian Journal of Philosophy (40):121-150.
    In the paper, I try to cast some doubt on traditional attempts to define, or explicate, moral responsibility in terms of deserved praise and blame. Desert-based accounts of moral responsibility, though no doubt more faithful to our ordinary notion of moral responsibility, tend to run into trouble in the face of challenges posed by a deterministic picture of the world on the one hand and the impact of moral luck on human action on the other. Besides, grounding responsibility in desert (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  6. The False Promise of Thought Experimentation in Moral and Political Philosophy.Friderik Klampfer - 2017 - In Borstner Bojan & Gartner Smiljana (ed.), Thought Experiments between Nature and Society. A Festschrift for Nenad Miščević. Newcastle upon Tyne, UK: Cambridge Scholars Publishing. pp. 328-348.
    Prof. Miščević has long been an ardent defender of the use of thought experiments in philosophy, foremost metaphysics, epistemology and philosophy of mind. Recently he has, in his typically sophisticated manner, extended his general account of philosophical thought-experimenting to the domain of normative politics. Not only can the history of political philosophy be better understood and appreciated, according to Miščević, when seen as a more or less continuous, yet covert, practice of thought-experimenting, the very progress of the discipline may crucially (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7. Should we Consult Kant when Assessing Agent’s Moral Responsibility for Harm?Friderik Klampfer - 2009 - Balkan Journal of Philosophy 1 (2):131-156.
    The paper focuses on the conditions under which an agent can be justifiably held responsible or liable for the harmful consequences of his or her actions. Kant has famously argued that as long as the agent fulfills his or her moral duty, he or she cannot be blamed for any potential harm that might result from his or her action, no matter how foreseeable these may (have) be(en). I call this the Duty-Absolves-Thesis or DA. I begin by stating the thesis (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  8. Suicide, Euthanasia and Human Dignity.Friderik Klampfer - 2001 - Acta Analytica 16:7-34.
    Kant has famously argued that human beings or persons, in virtue of their capacity for rational and autonomous choice and agency, possess dignity, which is an intrinsic, final, unconditional, inviolable, incomparable and irreplaceable value. This value, wherever found, commands respect and imposes rather strict moral constraints on our deliberations, intentions and actions. This paper deals with the question of whether, as some Kantians have recently argued, certain types of (physician-assisted) suicide and active euthanasia, most notably the intentional destruction of the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  9. Euthanasia Laws, Slippery Slopes, and (Un)reasonable Precaution.Friderik Klampfer - 2019 - Prolegomena: Časopis Za Filozofiju 18 (2):121-147.
    The article examines the so-called slippery slope argument (SSA) against the legalization of active voluntary euthanasia (AVE). According to the SSA, by legalizing AVE, the least morally controversial type of euthanasia, we will take the first step onto a slippery slope and inevitably end up in the moral abyss of widespread abuse and violations of the rights of the weakest and most vulnerable patients. In the first part of the paper, empirical evidence to the contrary is presented and analyzed: None (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. Euthanasia Laws, Slippery Slopes, and (Un)reasonable Precaution.Friderik Klampfer - 2019 - Prolegomena: Časopis Za Filozofiju 18 (2):121-147.
    The article examines the so-called slippery slope argument (SSA) against the legalization of active voluntary euthanasia (AVE). According to the SSA, by legalizing AVE, the least morally controversial type of euthanasia, we will take the first step onto a slippery slope and inevitably end up in the moral abyss of widespread abuse and violations of the rights of the weakest and most vulnerable patients. In the first part of the paper, empirical evidence to the contrary is presented and analyzed: None (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Three Comments on Joseph Raz's Conception of Normativity.George Pavlakos, Niko Kolodny, Ulrike Heuer & Douglas Lavin - 2011 - Jurisprudence 2 (2):329-378.
    This section is a discussion of Joseph Raz's Conception of Normativity introduced by Georgios Pavlakos.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  12.  39
    Contextualism and Moral Justification.Friderik Klampfer - 2005 - Croatian Journal of Philosophy 5 (3):569-582.
    In his insightful and stimulating book Morality Without Foundations: A Defense of Ethical Contextualism, Mark Timmons presents a strong case for embracing contextualism as a vibrant alternative to the two rival accounts that used to dominate moral epistemology in the past, foundationalism and coherentism. His sophisticated version of contextualist moral epistemology (CME) comprises of several intriguing and mind-boggling theses: (i) moral beliefs that lack Justification altogether can nevertheless be held in an epistemically responsible way; (ii) such unjustified beliefs can provide (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  32
    Contextualism and Moral Justification.Friderik Klampfer - 2005 - Croatian Journal of Philosophy 5 (3):569-582.
    In his insightful and stimulating book Morality Without Foundations: A Defense of Ethical Contextualism, Mark Timmons presents a strong case for embracing contextualism as a vibrant alternative to the two rival accounts that used to dominate moral epistemology in the past, foundationalism and coherentism. His sophisticated version of contextualist moral epistemology (CME) comprises of several intriguing and mind-boggling theses: (i) moral beliefs that lack Justification altogether can nevertheless be held in an epistemically responsible way; (ii) such unjustified beliefs can provide (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  88
    Moral responsibility for unprevented harm.Friderik Klampfer - 2004 - Acta Analytica 19 (33):119-161.
    That we are morally responsible for what we do willingly and knowingly is a commonplace. That our moral responsibility extends as far as to cover at least the intended consequences of our voluntary actions and perhaps also the ones we did not intend, but could or did foresee, is equally beyond dispute. But what about omissions? Are we, or can we be, (equally) morally responsible for the harm that has occured because we did not prevent it, even though we could (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  36
    On the space group of MgAl2O4spinel.L. Hwang, A. H. Heuer & T. E. Mitchell - 1973 - Philosophical Magazine 28 (1):241-243.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  16.  7
    Ontologie: zur Aktualität einer umstrittenen Disziplin.Kathi Beier & Peter Heuer (eds.) - 2010 - [Leipzig]: Leipziger Universitätsverlag.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  28
    Agency and Luck.Andrei Marmor, Ulrike Heuer, Rebecca Prebble & Nandi Theunissen - 2012 - In Ulrike Heuer & Gerald Lang (eds.), Luck, Value, and Commitment: Themes From the Ethics of Bernard Williams. Oxford University Press, Usa.
  18.  15
    Functional independence of explicit and implicit motor adjustments.Sandra Sülzenbrück & Herbert Heuer - 2009 - Consciousness and Cognition 18 (1):145-159.
    Adaptation to novel visuomotor transformations for example when navigating a cursor on a computer monitor by using a computer mouse, can be explicit or implicit. Explicit adjustments are made when people are informed about the occurrence and the type of a novel visuomotor transformation and intentionally modify their movements. Implicit adjustments, in contrast, are made without reportable knowledge of a novel visuomotor transformation and without a change intention. The relation of implicit adjustments to explicit adjustments needs further clarification. Here we (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  19.  13
    Machine learning in tutorials – Universal applicability, underinformed application, and other misconceptions.Andreas Breiter, Juliane Jarke & Hendrik Heuer - 2021 - Big Data and Society 8 (1).
    Machine learning has become a key component of contemporary information systems. Unlike prior information systems explicitly programmed in formal languages, ML systems infer rules from data. This paper shows what this difference means for the critical analysis of socio-technical systems based on machine learning. To provide a foundation for future critical analysis of machine learning-based systems, we engage with how the term is framed and constructed in self-education resources. For this, we analyze machine learning tutorials, an important information source for (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20.  13
    Precipitation in non-stoichiometric magnesium aluminate spinel.G. K. Bansal & A. H. Heuer - 1974 - Philosophical Magazine 29 (4):709-722.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  22
    Die ontologischen Grundlagen der aristotelischen Ethik.Falk Hamann & Peter Heuer (eds.) - 2019 - Leipzig, Germany: Leipziger Universitätsverlag.
    Die Beiträge dieses Bandes machen deutlich, dass die Untersuchung der ontologischen Grundlagen der aristotelischen Ethik ein breites Spektrum an philosophischen Fragen betrifft, die in der aktuellen Diskussion noch nicht zureichend beantwortet sind. Diese betreffen sowohl die aristotelische Ethik selbst als auch die aktuellen Versuche einer systematischen Wiederaneignung derselben in der praktischen Philosophie. Dieser Band soll einen Beitrag dazu leisten, in diesen Fragen zu größerer Klarheit zu gelangen.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. Einleitung.Falk Hamann & Peter Heuer - 2019 - In Falk Hamann & Peter Heuer (eds.), Die ontologischen Grundlagen der aristotelischen Ethik. Leipzig, Germany: pp. 9–17.
    Diese Einleitung skizziert verschiedene Problemfelder des Verhältnisses von Ethik und Ontologie bei Aristoteles und diskutiert überblicksartig entsprechende Lösungsansätze, die innerhalb des zeitgenössischen Neo-Aristotelismus entwickelt wurden.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  25
    Dislocation dissociation in stoichiometric MgAl2O4spinel observed by weak-beam electron microscopy.G. Welsch, L. Hwang, A. H. Heuer & T. E. Mitchell - 1974 - Philosophical Magazine 29 (6):1371-1379.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24.  14
    Otto Gross and Else Jaffé and Max Weber.Sam Whimster & Gottfried Heuer - 1998 - Theory, Culture and Society 15 (3-4):129-160.
    Section one of this article gives the narrative background to the love affair between Otto Gross and Else Jaffé. Otto Gross took Freud's psychoanalytic method in a libertarian direction and he became an influential figure in German anarchist circles shortly before 1914. Else Jaffé was a leading figure in Heidelberg's academic community. Section 2 provides the first complete translation of the Gross-Jaffé letters. Section 3 contrasts the positions of Gross and Max Weber to Nietzsche and comments on Else Jaffé's intermediate (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. Reasons for actions and desires.Ulrike Heuer - 2004 - Philosophical Studies 121 (1):43–63.
    It is an assumption common to many theories of rationality that all practical reasons are based on a person's given desires. I shall call any approach to practical reasons which accepts this assumption a "Humean approach". In spite of many criticisms, the Humean approach has numerous followers who take it to be the natural and inevitable view of practical reason. I will develop an argument against the Humean view aiming to explain its appeal, as well as to expose its mistake. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  26. Reasons and impossibility.Ulrike Heuer - 2010 - Philosophical Studies 147 (2):235 - 246.
    In this paper, I argue that a person can have a reason to do what she cannot do. In a nutshell, the argument is that a person can have derivate reasons relating to an action that she has a non-derivative reason to perform. There are clear examples of derivative reasons that a person has in cases where she cannot do what she (non-derivatively) has reason to do. She couldn’t have those derivative reasons, unless she also had the non-derivative reason to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  27. Luck, Value, and Commitment: Themes from the Ethics of Bernard Williams.Ulrike Heuer & Gerald R. Lang (eds.) - 2012 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press USA.
    Luck, Value, and Commitment comprises eleven new essays which engage with, or take their point of departure from, the influential work in moral and political philosophy of Bernard Williams (1929-2003).
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  28. The Paradox of Deontology, Revisited.Ulrike Heuer - 2011 - In Mark Timmons (ed.), Oxford Studies in Normative Ethics, Volume 1. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press. pp. 236-67.
    It appears to be a feature of our ordinary understanding of morality that we ought not to act in certain ways at all. We ought not to kill, torture, deceive, break our promises (say)—exceptional circumstances apart. Many moral duties are thought of in this way. Killing another person would be wrong even if it achieved a great good, and even if it led to preventing the deaths of several others. This feature of moral thinking is at the core of deontological (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  29. Introduction.Gerald Lang & Ulrike Heuer - 2012 - In Ulrike Heuer & Gerald Lang (eds.), Luck, Value, and Commitment: Themes From the Ethics of Bernard Williams. Oxford University Press. pp. 1-16.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  30.  21
    Effects of Reliability and Global Context on Explicit and Implicit Measures of Sensed Hand Position in Cursor-Control Tasks.Miya K. Rand & Herbert Heuer - 2015 - Frontiers in Psychology 6.
  31. Intentions and the Reasons for Which We Act.Ulrike Heuer - 2014 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 114 (3pt3):291-315.
    Many of the things we do in the course of a day we don't do intentionally: blushing, sneezing, breathing, blinking, smiling—to name but a few. But we also do act intentionally, and often when we do we act for reasons. Whether we always act for reasons when we act intentionally is controversial. But at least the converse is generally accepted: when we act for reasons we always act intentionally. Necessarily, it seems. In this paper, I argue that acting intentionally is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  32.  67
    Explaining Reasons: Where Does the Buck Stop?Ulrike Heuer - 2005 - Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 1 (3):1-25.
    The buck-passing account of values offers an explanation of the close relation of values and reasons for action: of why it is that the question whether something that is of value provides reasons is not ”open.” Being of value simply is, its defenders claim, a property that something has in virtue of its having other reason-providing properties. The generic idea of buck-passing is that the property of being good or being of value does not provide reasons. It is other properties (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  33.  15
    Effects of Hand and Hemispace on Multisensory Integration of Hand Position and Visual Feedback.Miya K. Rand & Herbert Heuer - 2019 - Frontiers in Psychology 10.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34. Beyond Wrong Reasons: The Buck-Passing Account of Value.Ulrike Heuer - 2010 - In Michael Brady (ed.), New Waves in Metaethics. New York: Palgrave-Macmillan.
    The buck-passing account of value (BPA) is very fertile ground that has given rise to a number of interpretations and controversies. It has originally been proposed by T.M. Scanlon as an analysis of value: according to it, being good ‘is not a property that itself provides a reason to respond to a thing in certain ways. Rather, to be good or valuable is to have other properties that constitute such reasons’. Buck-passing stands in a complicated relation to the fitting-attitude analysis (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  35.  17
    Inhibition of return is unimpressed by emotional cues.Wolf-Gero Lange, Kathrin Heuer, Andrea Reinecke, Eni S. Becker & Mike Rinck - 2008 - Cognition and Emotion 22 (8):1433-1456.
  36. Wrongness and reasons.Ulrike Heuer - 2010 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 13 (2):137 - 152.
    Is the wrongness of an action a reason not to perform it? Of course it is, you may answer. That an action is wrong both explains and justifies not doing it. Yet, there are doubts. Thinking that wrongness is a reason is confused, so an argument by Jonathan Dancy. There can’t be such a reason if ‘ϕ-ing is wrong’ is verdictive, and an all things considered judgment about what (not) to do in a certain situation. Such judgments are based on (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  37.  77
    Promising-Part 1.Ulrike Heuer - 2012 - Philosophy Compass 7 (12):832-841.
    The explanation of promising is fraught with problems. In particular the problem that promises can be valid even when nothing good comes of keeping the promise (the problem of ‘bare wrongings’), and the bootstrapping problem with explaining how the mere intention to put oneself under an obligation can create such an obligation have been recognized since Hume’s famous discussion of the topic. There are two influential accounts of promising, and promissory obligation, which attempt to solve the problems: The expectation account (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  38.  71
    Thick concepts and internal reasons.Ulrike Heuer - 2012 - In Ulrike Heuer & Gerald Lang (eds.), Luck, Value, and Commitment: Themes from the Ethics of Bernard Williams. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press USA. pp. 219.
    It has become common to distinguish between two kinds of ethical concepts: thick and thin ones. Bernard Williams, who coined the terms, explains that thick concepts such as “coward, lie, brutality, gratitude and so forth” are marked by having greater empirical content than thin ones. They are both action-guiding and world-guided: -/- If a concept of this kind applies, this often provides someone with a reason for action… At the same time, their application is guided by the world. A concept (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  39. Vivid memories of emotional events-the accuracy of remembered minutiae.F. Heuer & D. Reisberg - 1987 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 25 (5):338-338.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  40.  55
    Promising - Part 2.Ulrike Heuer - 2012 - Philosophy Compass 7 (12):842-851.
    The explanation of promising is fraught with problems. In particular the problem that promises can be valid even when nothing good comes of keeping the promise , and the bootstrapping problem with explaining how the mere intention to put oneself under an obligation can create such an obligation have been recognized since Hume’s famous discussion of the topic. In part 1, I showed that two main views of promising which attempt to solve these problems fall short of explaining the promissory (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  41. The Relevance of the Wrong Kind of Reasons.Ulrike Heuer - 2018 - In C. McHugh, J. Way & D. Whiting (eds.), Normativity: Epistemic and Practical. Oxford, UK:
    There is currently a wide-ranging philosophical discussion of two kinds of reasons for attitudes which are sometimes called the right and wrong kinds of reasons for those attitudes. The question is what the distinction shows about the nature of the attitudes, and about reasons and normativity in general. The distinction is deemed to apply to reasons for different kinds of attitudes such as beliefs and intentions, as well as so-called proattitudes, e.g. admiration or desire. Wlodek Rabinowicz’s and Toni Rønnow-Rasmussen’s paper (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  42.  8
    A condition that produces sensory recalibration and abolishes multisensory integration.Miya K. Rand & Herbert Heuer - 2020 - Cognition 202:104326.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  44
    The Roots of Normativity.Joseph Raz & Ulrike Heuer (eds.) - 2022 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    Joseph Raz addresses one of the most basic philosophical questions: how to explain normativity in its many guises. His value-based account is brought to bear on many aspects of the lives of rational beings and their agency, such as their ability to maintain relationships, and to live their lives as social beings with a sense of their identity.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. Anticipations and afterthoughts-how far does the present extend.D. Reisberg, F. Heuer & G. Lenoir - 1989 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 27 (6):499-499.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. Intentions, Permissibility and the Reasons for Which We Act.Ulrike Heuer - 2015 - In George Pavlakos & Veronica Rodriguez Blanco (eds.), Practical Normativity. Essays on Reasons and Intentions in Law and Practical Reason. Cambridge University Press. pp. 11-30.
    If you injure me, it matters morally whether it was an accident or you did it intentionally, and whether you did it because you thought it would be fun. I take it that any ethical theory will have to include some explanation of why this is. There are two dominant views in the current debate about the moral significance of an agent’s intentions: The one is that the intention with which someone acts at least sometimes determines whether what she does (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  46. Europe and its refugees: Arendt on the politicization of minorities.Wolfgang Heuer - 2007 - Social Research: An International Quarterly 74 (4):1159-1172.
  47.  34
    Does a hand preference indicate a hemispheric specialization?Herbert Heuer - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):277-278.
  48.  13
    The cognitive and neural architecture of sequence representation.Steven W. Keele, Richard Ivry, Ulrich Mayr, Eliot Hazeltine & Herbert Heuer - 2003 - Psychological Review 110 (2):316-339.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  49. Rights and the second-person standpoint: A challenge to Darwall's account.Kelly Heuer - manuscript
    Stephen Darwall’s The Second Person Standpoint is built around an analysis of the “second-person standpoint,” which he argues builds in a series of presuppositions which help shape (and perhaps even give content to) morality. This paper argues that there is a kind of paradox tied up in the two central claims at the heart of this project – that second-personal address directs one practically rather than epistemically by giving reasons for action one otherwise would not have had, and that all (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  50. Reasons to Intend.Ulrike Heuer - 2018 - In Daniel Star (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Reasons and Normativity. New York, NY, United States of America: Oxford University Press. pp. 865-890.
    Donald Davidson writes that “[r]easons for intending to do something are very much like reasons for action, indeed one might hold that they are exactly the same except for time.” That the reasons for forming an intention and the reasons for acting as intended are in some way related is a widely accepted claim. But it can take different forms: (1) the reasons may mirror each other so that there is a (derivative) reason to intend whenever there is a reason (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 130