Results for 'Archimedean continuum'

992 found
Order:
  1. The absolute arithmetic continuum and the unification of all numbers great and small.Philip Ehrlich - 2012 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 18 (1):1-45.
    In his monograph On Numbers and Games, J. H. Conway introduced a real-closed field containing the reals and the ordinals as well as a great many less familiar numbers including $-\omega, \,\omega/2, \,1/\omega, \sqrt{\omega}$ and $\omega-\pi$ to name only a few. Indeed, this particular real-closed field, which Conway calls No, is so remarkably inclusive that, subject to the proviso that numbers—construed here as members of ordered fields—be individually definable in terms of sets of NBG, it may be said to contain (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  2. The classical continuum without points.Geoffrey Hellman & Stewart Shapiro - 2013 - Review of Symbolic Logic 6 (3):488-512.
    We develop a point-free construction of the classical one- dimensional continuum, with an interval structure based on mereology and either a weak set theory or logic of plural quantification. In some respects this realizes ideas going back to Aristotle,although, unlike Aristotle, we make free use of classical "actual infinity". Also, in contrast to intuitionistic, Bishop, and smooth infinitesimal analysis, we follow classical analysis in allowing partitioning of our "gunky line" into mutually exclusive and exhaustive disjoint parts, thereby demonstrating the (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  3.  1
    The Absolute Arithmetic Continuum and Its Geometric Counterpart.Philip Ehrlich - 2024 - In Bharath Sriraman (ed.), Handbook of the History and Philosophy of Mathematical Practice. Cham: Springer. pp. 1677-1718.
    In a number of works, we have suggested that whereas the ordered field R of real numbers should merely be regarded as constituting an arithmetic continuum (modulo the Archimedean axiom), the ordered field No of surreal numbers may be regarded as a sort of absolute arithmetic continuum (modulo NBG). In the present chapter, as part of a more general exposition of the absolute arithmetic continuum, we will outline some of the properties of the system of surreal (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Hittcry of Science.Archimedean Fortunes - forthcoming - History of Science.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  91
    Who Gave You the Cauchy–Weierstrass Tale? The Dual History of Rigorous Calculus.Alexandre Borovik & Mikhail G. Katz - 2012 - Foundations of Science 17 (3):245-276.
    Cauchy’s contribution to the foundations of analysis is often viewed through the lens of developments that occurred some decades later, namely the formalisation of analysis on the basis of the epsilon-delta doctrine in the context of an Archimedean continuum. What does one see if one refrains from viewing Cauchy as if he had read Weierstrass already? One sees, with Felix Klein, a parallel thread for the development of analysis, in the context of an infinitesimal-enriched continuum. One sees, (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  6. Ten Misconceptions from the History of Analysis and Their Debunking.Piotr Błaszczyk, Mikhail G. Katz & David Sherry - 2013 - Foundations of Science 18 (1):43-74.
    The widespread idea that infinitesimals were “eliminated” by the “great triumvirate” of Cantor, Dedekind, and Weierstrass is refuted by an uninterrupted chain of work on infinitesimal-enriched number systems. The elimination claim is an oversimplification created by triumvirate followers, who tend to view the history of analysis as a pre-ordained march toward the radiant future of Weierstrassian epsilontics. In the present text, we document distortions of the history of analysis stemming from the triumvirate ideology of ontological minimalism, which identified the (...) with a single number system. Such anachronistic distortions characterize the received interpretation of Stevin, Leibniz, d’Alembert, Cauchy, and others. (shrink)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  7.  89
    A Burgessian Critique of Nominalistic Tendencies in Contemporary Mathematics and its Historiography.Karin Usadi Katz & Mikhail G. Katz - 2012 - Foundations of Science 17 (1):51-89.
    We analyze the developments in mathematical rigor from the viewpoint of a Burgessian critique of nominalistic reconstructions. We apply such a critique to the reconstruction of infinitesimal analysis accomplished through the efforts of Cantor, Dedekind, and Weierstrass; to the reconstruction of Cauchy’s foundational work associated with the work of Boyer and Grabiner; and to Bishop’s constructivist reconstruction of classical analysis. We examine the effects of a nominalist disposition on historiography, teaching, and research.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  8. The role of epistemological models in Veronese's and Bettazzi's theory of magnitudes.Paola Cantù - 2010 - In M. D'Agostino, G. Giorello, F. Laudisa, T. Pievani & C. Sinigaglia (eds.), New Essays in Logic and Philosophy of Science. College Publications.
    The philosophy of mathematics has been accused of paying insufficient attention to mathematical practice: one way to cope with the problem, the one we will follow in this paper on extensive magnitudes, is to combine the `history of ideas' and the `philosophy of models' in a logical and epistemological perspective. The history of ideas allows the reconstruction of the theory of extensive magnitudes as a theory of ordered algebraic structures; the philosophy of models allows an investigation into the way epistemology (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  58
    Leibniz’s syncategorematic infinitesimals II: their existence, their use and their role in the justification of the differential calculus.David Rabouin & Richard T. W. Arthur - 2020 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 74 (5):401-443.
    In this paper, we endeavour to give a historically accurate presentation of how Leibniz understood his infinitesimals, and how he justified their use. Some authors claim that when Leibniz called them “fictions” in response to the criticisms of the calculus by Rolle and others at the turn of the century, he had in mind a different meaning of “fiction” than in his earlier work, involving a commitment to their existence as non-Archimedean elements of the continuum. Against this, we (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  10. Leibniz's syncategorematic infinitesimals, smooth infinitesimal analysis, and Newton's proposition.Richard Arthur - manuscript
    In contrast with some recent theories of infinitesimals as non-Archimedean entities, Leibniz’s mature interpretation was fully in accord with the Archimedean Axiom: infinitesimals are fictions, whose treatment as entities incomparably smaller than finite quantities is justifiable wholly in terms of variable finite quantities that can be taken as small as desired, i.e. syncategorematically. In this paper I explain this syncategorematic interpretation, and how Leibniz used it to justify the calculus. I then compare it with the approach of Smooth (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11.  56
    Many-valued logic and sequence arguments in value theory.Simon Knutsson - 2021 - Synthese 199 (3-4):10793-10825.
    Some find it plausible that a sufficiently long duration of torture is worse than any duration of mild headaches. Similarly, it has been claimed that a million humans living great lives is better than any number of worm-like creatures feeling a few seconds of pleasure each. Some have related bad things to good things along the same lines. For example, one may hold that a future in which a sufficient number of beings experience a lifetime of torture is bad, regardless (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  12. John L. BELL. The continuous and the infinitesimal in mathematics and philosophy. Monza: Polimetrica, 2005. Pp. 349. ISBN 88-7699-015-. [REVIEW]Jean-Pierre Marquis - 2006 - Philosophia Mathematica 14 (3):394-400.
    Some concepts that are now part and parcel of mathematics used to be, at least until the beginning of the twentieth century, a central preoccupation of mathematicians and philosophers. The concept of continuity, or the continuous, is one of them. Nowadays, many philosophers of mathematics take it for granted that mathematicians of the last quarter of the nineteenth century found an adequate conceptual analysis of the continuous in terms of limits and that serious philosophical thinking is no longer required, except (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13. Non-Archimedean Probability.Vieri Benci, Leon Horsten & Sylvia Wenmackers - 2013 - Milan Journal of Mathematics 81 (1):121-151.
    We propose an alternative approach to probability theory closely related to the framework of numerosity theory: non-Archimedean probability (NAP). In our approach, unlike in classical probability theory, all subsets of an infinite sample space are measurable and only the empty set gets assigned probability zero (in other words: the probability functions are regular). We use a non-Archimedean field as the range of the probability function. As a result, the property of countable additivity in Kolmogorov’s axiomatization of probability is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  14. Non-Archimedean Preferences Over Countable Lotteries.Jeffrey Sanford Russell - 2020 - Journal of Mathematical Economics 88 (May 2020):180-186.
    We prove a representation theorem for preference relations over countably infinite lotteries that satisfy a generalized form of the Independence axiom, without assuming Continuity. The representing space consists of lexicographically ordered transfinite sequences of bounded real numbers. This result is generalized to preference orders on abstract superconvex spaces.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  15. The Archimedean trap: Why traditional reinforcement learning will probably not yield AGI.Samuel Allen Alexander - 2020 - Journal of Artificial General Intelligence 11 (1):70-85.
    After generalizing the Archimedean property of real numbers in such a way as to make it adaptable to non-numeric structures, we demonstrate that the real numbers cannot be used to accurately measure non-Archimedean structures. We argue that, since an agent with Artificial General Intelligence (AGI) should have no problem engaging in tasks that inherently involve non-Archimedean rewards, and since traditional reinforcement learning rewards are real numbers, therefore traditional reinforcement learning probably will not lead to AGI. We indicate (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16. Non-Archimedean population axiologies.Calvin Baker - forthcoming - Economics and Philosophy.
    Non-Archimedean population axiologies – also known as lexical views – claim (i) that a sufficient number of lives at a very high positive welfare level would be better than any number of lives at a very low positive welfare level and/or (ii) that a sufficient number of lives at a very low negative welfare level would be worse than any number of lives at a very high negative welfare level. Such axiologies are popular because they can avoid the (Negative) (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  29
    Non-Archimedean fuzzy and probability logic.Andrew Schumann - 2008 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 18 (1):29-48.
    In this paper the non-Archimedean multiple-validity is proposed for basic fuzzy logic BL∀∞ that is built as an ω-order extension of the logic BL∀. Probabilities are defined on the class of fuzzy subsets and, as a result, for the first time the non-Archimedean valued probability logic is constructed on the base of BL∀∞.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  18.  32
    Non-Archimedean Utility Theory.H. J. Skala - 1978 - Noûs 12 (1):69-72.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  19. The Archimedean Urge.Amia Srinivasan - 2015 - Philosophical Perspectives 29 (1):325-362.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  20.  58
    Archimedean Metanorms.J. Adam Carter - 2021 - Topoi 40 (5):1075-1085.
    One notable line of argument for epistemic relativism appeals to considerations to do with non-neutrality: in certain dialectical contexts—take for instance the famous dispute between Galileo and Cardinal Bellarmine concerning geocentrism—it seems as though a lack of suitably neutral epistemic standards that either side could appeal to in order to resolve their first-order dispute is itself—as Rorty influentially thought—evidence for epistemic relativism. In this essay, my aim is first to present a more charitable reformulation of this line of reasoning, one (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  21. Archimedeanism and Why Metaethics Matters.Paul Bloomfield - 2009 - Oxford Studies in Metaethics 4:283-302.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  22. Archimedean metaethics defended.Kenneth M. Ehrenberg - 2008 - Metaphilosophy 39 (4-5):508-529.
    Abstract: We sometimes say our moral claims are "objectively true," or are "right, even if nobody believes it." These additional claims are often taken to be staking out metaethical positions, representative of a certain kind of theorizing about morality that "steps outside" the practice in order to comment on its status. Ronald Dworkin has argued that skepticism about these claims so understood is not tenable because it is impossible to step outside such practices. I show that externally skeptical metaethical theory (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  23.  38
    Archimedean classes in integral commutative residuated chains.Rostislav Horčík & Franco Montagna - 2009 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 55 (3):320-336.
    This paper investigates a quasi-variety of representable integral commutative residuated lattices axiomatized by the quasi-identity resulting from the well-known Wajsberg identity → q ≤ → p if it is written as a quasi-identity, i. e., → q ≈ 1 ⇒ → p ≈ 1. We prove that this quasi-identity is strictly weaker than the corresponding identity. On the other hand, we show that the resulting quasi-variety is in fact a variety and provide an axiomatization. The obtained results shed some light (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  11
    Archimedean Principles and Mathematical Heritage: A Synthesis.Abhiroop Chattopadhyay & Brett Kaufman - 2021 - Axiomathes 31 (2):145-155.
    This paper aims to provide an updated synthesis on the works of Archimedes and the fundamental impact these have had on subsequent mathematical practice. The influence his mathematical processes have had on modern mathematics and how these have helped develop the field is discussed in historical perspective. Some of the recent investigations into the Archimedes Palimpsest are discussed and synthesized, namely, how they alter our understanding of some of his earlier works, and how Archimedean principles are seen to have (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  31
    The Archimedean Point: From Fixed Positions to the Limits of Theory.Jocelyn Holland & Edgar Landgraf - 2014 - Substance 43 (3):3-11.
    There is no authoritative biography of Archimedes, but there are moments from his life which, apocryphal or not, have become the stuff of legend. These include accounts of Archimedes running naked through the streets after realizing that his body displaces water in the bath , how he sat musing over diagrams in the sand as sword-bearing Romans descended upon him during a siege of Syracuse, and of course, his mechanically-informed claim that a firm resting place is all he would need (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  4
    The Archimedean ‘sambukē’ of Damis in Biton.Paul T. Keyser - 2021 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 76 (2):153-172.
    Biton’s Construction of Machines of War and Catapults describes six machines by five engineers or inventors; the fourth machine is a rolling elevatable scaling ladder, named sambukē, designed by one Damis of Kolophōn. The first sambukē was invented by Herakleides of Taras, in 214 BCE, for the Roman siege of Syracuse. Biton is often dismissed as incomprehensible or preposterous. I here argue that the account of Damis’ device is largely coherent and shows that Biton understood that Damis had built a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  57
    Archimedean Intuitions.Matthew E. Moore - 2002 - Theoria 68 (3):185-204.
    The Archimedean Axiom is often held to be an intuitively obvious truth about the geometry of physical space. After a general discussion of the varieties of geometrical intuition that have been proposed, I single out one variety which we can plausibly be held to have and then argue that it does not underwrite the intuitive obviousness of the Archimedean Axiom. Generalizing that result, I conclude that the Axiom is not intuitively obvious.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  28.  22
    Non‐archimedean stratifications of tangent cones.Erick García Ramírez - 2017 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 63 (3-4):299-312.
    We study the impact of a kind of non‐archimedean stratifications (t‐stratifications) on tangent cones of definable sets in real closed fields. We prove that such stratifications induce stratifications of the same nature on the tangent cone of a definable set at a fixed point. As a consequence, the archimedean counterpart of a t‐stratification is shown to induce Whitney stratifications on the tangent cones of a semi‐algebraic set. Extensions of these results are proposed for real closed fields with further (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  29.  10
    Generalized Archimedean fields.John Cowles & Robert LaGrange - 1983 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 24 (1):133-140.
  30.  25
    Non-Archimedean valued predicate logic.Andrew Schumann - 2007 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 36 (1/2):67-78.
  31.  65
    Measurement without archimedean axioms.Louis Narens - 1974 - Philosophy of Science 41 (4):374-393.
    Axiomatizations of measurement systems usually require an axiom--called an Archimedean axiom--that allows quantities to be compared. This type of axiom has a different form from the other measurement axioms, and cannot--except in the most trivial cases--be empirically verified. In this paper, representation theorems for extensive measurement structures without Archimedean axioms are given. Such structures are represented in measurement spaces that are generalizations of the real number system. Furthermore, a precise description of "Archimedean axioms" is given and it (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  32.  5
    A Hierarchy on Non-Archimedean Polish Groups Admitting a Compatible Complete Left-Invariant Metric.Longyun Ding & Xu Wang - forthcoming - Journal of Symbolic Logic:1-19.
    In this article, we introduce a hierarchy on the class of non-archimedean Polish groups that admit a compatible complete left-invariant metric. We denote this hierarchy by $\alpha $ -CLI and L- $\alpha $ -CLI where $\alpha $ is a countable ordinal. We establish three results: (1) G is $0$ -CLI iff $G=\{1_G\}$ ; (2) G is $1$ -CLI iff G admits a compatible complete two-sided invariant metric; and (3) G is L- $\alpha $ -CLI iff G is locally $\alpha (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  12
    Hyper-Archimedean BL-algebras are MV-algebras.Esko Turunen - 2007 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 53 (2):170-175.
    Generalizations of Boolean elements of a BL-algebra L are studied. By utilizing the MV-center MV(L) of L, it is reproved that an element x L is Boolean iff x x * = 1. L is called semi-Boolean if for all x L, x * is Boolean. An MV-algebra L is semi-Boolean iff L is a Boolean algebra. A BL-algebra L is semi-Boolean iff L is an SBL-algebra. A BL-algebra L is called hyper-Archimedean if for all x L, xn is (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34. An Archimedean Point for Philosophy.Shyam Ranganathan - 2011 - Metaphilosophy 42 (4):479-519.
    According to the orthodox account of meaning and translation in the literature, meaning is a property of expressions of a language, and translation is a matching of synonymous expressions across languages. This linguistic account of translation gives rise to well-known skeptical conclusions about translation, objectivity, meaning and truth, but it does not conform to our best translational practices. In contrast, I argue for a textual account of meaning based on the concept of a TEXT-TYPE that does conform to our best (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35. Anti-archimedeanism.Arthur Ripstein - 2007 - In Ronald Dworkin. Cambridge University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  36. The Continuum of Inductive Methods.Rudolf Carnap - 1953 - Philosophy 28 (106):272-273.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   136 citations  
  37. Expressivism, Anti-Archimedeanism and Supervenience.Christine Tiefensee - 2014 - Res Publica 20 (2):163-181.
    Metaethics is traditionally understood as a non-moral discipline that examines moral judgements from a standpoint outside of ethics. This orthodox understanding has recently come under pressure from anti-Archimedeans, such as Ronald Dworkin and Matthew Kramer, who proclaim that rather than assessing morality from an external perspective, metaethical theses are themselves substantive moral claims. In this paper, I scrutinise this anti-Archimedean challenge as applied to the metaethical position of expressivism. More precisely, I examine the claim that expressivists do not avoid (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  38.  49
    Triangulating non-archimedean probability.Hazel Brickhill & Leon Horsten - 2018 - Review of Symbolic Logic 11 (3):519-546.
    We relate Popper functions to regular and perfectly additive such non-Archimedean probability functions by means of a representation theorem: every such non-Archimedean probability function is infinitesimally close to some Popper function, and vice versa. We also show that regular and perfectly additive non-Archimedean probability functions can be given a lexicographic representation. Thus Popper functions, a specific kind of non-Archimedean probability functions, and lexicographic probability functions triangulate to the same place: they are in a good sense interchangeable.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  39. A continuum of intentionality: linking the biogenic and anthropogenic approaches to cognition.Matthew Sims - 2021 - Biology and Philosophy 36 (6):1-31.
    Biogenic approaches investigate cognition from the standpoint of evolutionary function, asking what cognition does for a living system and then looking for common principles and exhibitions of cognitive strategies in a vast array of living systems—non-neural to neural. One worry which arises for the biogenic approach is that it is overly permissive in terms of what it construes as cognition. In this paper I critically engage with a recent instance of this way of criticising biogenic approaches in order to clarify (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  40. The continuum of inductive methods.Rudolf Carnap - 1952 - [Chicago]: University of Chicago Press.
  41.  8
    Cognitive Continuum Theory: Can it contribute to the examination of confidentiality and risk‐actuated disclosure decisions of nurses practising in mental health?Darren Conlon, Toby Raeburn & Timothy Wand - 2023 - Nursing Inquiry 30 (2):e12520.
    Nurses practising in mental health are faced with challenging decisions concerning confidentiality if a patient is deemed a potential risk to self or others, because releasing pertinent information pertaining to the patient may be necessary to circumvent harm. However, decisions to withhold or disclose confidential information that are inappropriately made may lead to adverse outcomes for stakeholders, including nurses and their patients. Nonetheless, there is a dearth of contemporary research literature to advise nurses in these circumstances. Cognitive Continuum Theory (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  4
    The Archimedean Point – Kierkegaard on History and Identity.Claus-Dieter Osthövener, Theodor Jørgensen, Richard Crouter & Niels Jørgen Cappelørn - 2006 - In Claus-Dieter Osthövener, Theodor Jørgensen, Richard Crouter & Niels Jørgen Cappelørn (eds.), Schleiermacher Und Kierkegaard: Subjektivität Und Wahrheit / Subjectivity and Truth. Akten des Schleiermacher-Kierkegaard-Kongresses in Kopenhagen Oktober 2003 / Proceedings From the Schleiermacher-Kierkegaard Congress in Copenhagen October, 2003. Walter de Gruyter.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. A Continuum Argument for Intransitivity.Larry S. Temkin - 1996 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 25 (3):175-210.
  44.  85
    In Defense of Anti‐Archimedean Moral Realism: A Response to Recent Critics.Patrick Clipsham - 2013 - Metaphilosophy 44 (4):470-484.
    Ronald Dworkin famously argued that many putatively nonmoral metaethical theories can only be understood as being internal to the moral domain. If correct, this position, referred to as anti-archimedeanism, has profound implications for the methodology of metaethics. This is particularly true for skeptical metaethical theories. This article defends a version of anti-archimedeanism that is true to the spirit rather than the letter of Dworkin's original thesis from several recent objections. First, it addresses Kenneth Ehrenberg's recent attempt to demonstrate how certain (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  72
    The Continuum companion to the philosophy of language.Manuel García-Carpintero & Max Kölbel (eds.) - 2012 - New York: Continuum International.
    The Continuum Companion to Philosophy of Language offers the definitive guide to contemporary philosophy of language. The book covers all the fundamental questions asked by the philosophy of language - areas that have continued to attract interest historically as well as topics that have emerged more recently as active areas of research. Ten specially commissioned essays from an international team of experts reveal where important work continues to be done in the area and, most valuably, the exciting new directions (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  46.  35
    Mengzi and the Archimedean Point for Moral Life.Xinyan Jiang - 2014 - Journal of Chinese Philosophy 41 (1-2):74-90.
    “The Archimedean point for moral life” discussed in this article refers to the starting point of one's moral reasoning and what ultimately makes moral life possible. The article intends to show that Mengzi's doctrine of the Four Beginnings may throw some light on our search for such an Archimedean point. More specifically, it argues for the following: Mengzi's doctrine of the Four Beginnings actually takes moral sentiments as the Archimedean point for moral life; Mengzi's view of the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  21
    The Archimedean point: Consciousness, praxis, and the present in Lukács and Bloch.Cat Moir - 2020 - Thesis Eleven 157 (1):3-23.
    This article consists of an original translation of Ernst Bloch’s 1923 review of Lukács History and Class Consciousness, preceded by a translator’s introduction contextualising Bloch’s review and interpreting what it tells us about the intellectual and personal relationship between Bloch and Lukács. I argue that Bloch’s review highlights some of the key differences and points of intersection between their thinking. Written when their personal relationship had already soured for both political and intellectual reasons, Bloch’s review makes clear his ongoing commitment (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  51
    Archimedean Points in a Network of Cosmological Metaphors: Fontenelle, Locke, Fichte, and Kant.Monika Tokarzewska - 2014 - Substance 43 (3):27-45.
    Johann Gottlieb Fichte’s first treatise, “Concerning the Concept of the ‘Wissenschaftslehre’” , is a text built in no small measure upon metaphors. Unlike the increasingly abstract lectures on the theory of knowledge, the 1794 treatise is organized around two fields of imagery: construction and cosmology. These two fields overlap in that the Earth doubles as a planet in the universe and the foundation upon which people raise buildings. Both metaphorical fields come together most prominently when Fichte draws on the anecdote (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  9
    An Archimedean Proof of Heron's Formula for the Area of a Triangle; Reconstructed.Chr M. Taisbak* - 1980 - Centaurus 24 (1):110-116.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50.  74
    The archimedean point and eccentricity: Hannah Arendt's philosophy of science and technology.Pieter Tijmes - 1992 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 35 (3-4):389 – 406.
    In this contribution I discuss Hannah Arendt's philosophy of culture in three rounds. First I give an account of my view on Hannah Arendt's main work The Human Condition. In this frame of reference I distance myself from the importance attached to Hannah Arendt as a political philosopher and hold a warm plea for her as a philosopher of culture (I and II). Second I pay attention to her view on science and technology in their cultural meaning, expressed in the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 992