Results for 'Pseudocleft'

7 found
Order:
  1. Roger Schwarzschild and Karina Wilkinson.Specificational Pseudoclefts, Barbara Abbott & Donkey Demonstratives - 2002 - Natural Language Semantics 10 (305).
  2.  53
    Pseudoclefts Crosslinguistically.Sabine Iatridou & Spyridola Varlokosta - 1998 - Natural Language Semantics 6 (1):3-28.
    Pseudoclefts have been divided into two types, specificational and predicational (Akmajian 1970; Higgins 1979). The two types differ in interpretive as well as syntactic characteristics. In this paper we argue that the availability of the specificational type depends on the particular lexical items that a language employs to form pseudoclefts. We discuss the significance of these findings for linguistic theory.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  3.  16
    On The Relation of Connectivity and Specificational Pseudoclefts.Daphna Heller - 2002 - Natural Language Semantics 10 (4):243-284.
    From Higgins (1973) to Iatridou and Varlokosta (1998), connectivity has been considered in the literature to be a defining characteristic of specificational pseudoclefts. This paper argues against this view based on an analysis of specificational pseudoclefts in Hebrew. Pseudoclefts in Hebrew are interesting in two ways. First, predicational and specificational pseudoclefts are distinguished lexically in the choice of the copula. Second, specificational pseudoclefts fall into two classes, each exhibiting a different set of connectivity effects. The connectivity pattern in Hebrew is (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  4. Ask, and tell as well: Question–Answer Clauses in American Sign Language.Ivano Caponigro & Kathryn Davidson - 2011 - Natural Language Semantics 19 (4):323-371.
    A construction is found in American Sign Language that we call a Question–Answer Clause. It is made of two parts: the first part looks like an interrogative clause conveying a question, while the second part resembles a declarative clause answering that question. The very same signer has to sign both, the entire construction is interpreted as truth-conditionally equivalent to a declarative sentence, and it can be uttered only under certain discourse conditions. These and other properties of Question–Answer Clauses are discussed, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  5.  82
    “Two be or not two be”: Identity, predication and the Welsh copula.Laurie Zaring - 1996 - Linguistics and Philosophy 19 (2):103 - 142.
    The availability in universal grammar of two separate copulas of predication & identity is supported by an analysis of pseudoclefts in Welsh. A single-copula analysis of the ambiguity between predicational & specificational interpretations of pseudoclefts in English cannot be extended to Welsh, where specificational interpretation (1) is permitted by only one of three copular paradigms, all of which may have a predicational interpretation, & (2) is possible with both of the D-structures used in the single-copula analysis to distinguish between the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  6. On Triggered Inversion in Hebrew.Erez Levon - unknown
    Triggered Inversion (TI) in Hebrew has been previously analyzed as canonical A'-movement to the specificer position of a functional projection in the CP-layer (Doron & Shlonsky 1990, Shlonsky 1997). This article examines the semantic properties of TI constructions in Hebrew, specifically the cross-linguistic similarities between TI in Hebrew and pseudoclefts (PC) in English, as discussed in Heycock & Kroch (1999). A structure is proposed for Hebrew TI that parallels the structure given for equatives in Hebrew by Rothstein (1995), in which (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  11
    The Attractions of Agreement: Why Person Is Different.Marcel den Dikken - 2019 - Frontiers in Psychology 10:430180.
    This paper establishes the generalisation that whenever agreement with the finite verb is controlled by a constituent that is not in a Spec–Head relation with the inflectional head of the clause, this agreement cannot affect person. A syntactic representation for person inside the noun phrase and on the clausal spine is proposed which, in conjunction with the workings of agreement and concord, accommodates this empirical generalisation and derives Baker’s Structural Condition on Person Agreement (SCOPA). The proposal also provides an explanation (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation