Does Brock’s theory of migration justice adequately account for climate refugees?

Ethics and Global Politics 14 (2):75-85 (2021)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

In Justice for People on the Move, Gillian Brock develops a promising, original account of migration justice. In her view, states have a robust (though conditional) right to self-determination, which includes a reasonably strong right to regulate migration. However, in order for these rights to be justified, three legitimacy requirements must be met. Most obviously, states must respect the human rights of their own citizens and the international state system itself must be legitimate. This latter condition also requires states to do their part in sustaining a justified state system, which includes helping to alleviate “legitimacy gaps,” including significant human rights violations in other states. Brock uses this framework to address several pressing migration-related policy issues, including Muslim bans, the deportation of unauthorized migrants, temporary labor migration, and refugee protection. However, one topic is notably absent from her analysis: climate-related displacement. Some theorists insist that climate change migrants should not be considered refugees because they do not fit the standard definition of a refugee. In particular, climate migrants were displaced by droughts, floods, storms, or sea level rise rather than by war or persecution, and many are able to remain in their homes at present but will be forced to relocate at some point in the future. This paper explores the implications of Brock’s theory of migration justice for climate migration. I suggest that although her approach to refugee protection may initially appear to exclude climate migrants, her understanding of right to self-determination yields strong obligations to assist them. I take this to be a strength of her framework, which makes an important, albeit indirect, contribution to current debates on climate change migration.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 93,891

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Migration Justice and Legitimacy.Peter W. Higgins - 2022 - Res Publica 28 (3):425-433.
Labor Migration and Climate Change Adaptation.Jamie Draper - 2022 - American Political Science Review 116 (3):1012-1024.
Self-determination, Democracy, Human Rights, and Migrants’ Rights.Gillian Brock - 2020 - International Journal of Applied Philosophy 34 (2):295-309.
Climate Displacement.Jamie Draper - 2023 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Deportation, harms, and human rights.Lukas Schmid - 2021 - Ethics and Global Politics 14 (2):98-109.
Climate Change Refugees.Matthew Lister - 2014 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 17 (5):618-634.
Justice in Migration: Are Human Rights Enough?Anna Stilz - 2020 - International Journal of Applied Philosophy 34 (2):271-285.
Justice in Migration: Are Human Rights Enough? in advance.Anna Stilz - 2020 - International Journal of Applied Philosophy 34 (2):271-285.

Analytics

Added to PP
2021-05-29

Downloads
34 (#458,073)

6 months
5 (#837,449)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Shelley Wilcox
San Francisco State University

Citations of this work

Add more citations

References found in this work

Who is a refugee?Andrew E. Shacknove - 1985 - Ethics 95 (2):274-284.
Climate Change Refugees.Matthew Lister - 2014 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 17 (5):618-634.
Floating Provisos and Sinking Islands.Avery Kolers - 2012 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 29 (3):333-343.

Add more references