Reply to Eaton and Pickavance

Philosophical Studies 173 (12):3231-3233 (2016)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

David Eaton and Timothy Pickavance argued that interest-relative invariantism has a surprising and interesting consequence. They take this consequence to be so implausible that it refutes interest-relative invariantism. But in fact it is a consequence that any theory of knowledge that has the resources to explain familiar puzzles must have.

Similar books and articles

Defending interest-relative invariantism.Brian Weatherson - 2011 - Logos and Episteme 2 (4):591-609.
Interest-Relative Invariantism. [REVIEW]Stephen Schiffer - 2007 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 75 (1):188 - 195.
Interests, evidence and games.Brian Weatherson - 2018 - Episteme 15 (3):329-344.
Epistemic Contextualism: A Normative Approach.Robin Mckenna - 2012 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 94 (1):101-123.
Experiments on Contextualism and Interest Relative Invariantism.Ángel Pinillos - 2016 - In Wesley Buckwalter & Justin Sytsma (eds.), Blackwell Companion to Experimental Philosophy. Malden, MA: Blackwell. pp. 349–358.
Stanley's Three Flaws.Stefan Riedener - 2010 - Swiss Philosophical Preprints.

Analytics

Added to PP
2016-03-11

Downloads
300 (#8,882)

6 months
61 (#255,957)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Brian Weatherson
University of Michigan, Ann Arbor

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Knowledge: A Very Short Introduction.Jennifer Nagel - 2014 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Counter-Closure.Federico Luzzi - 2010 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 88 (4):673-683.
Evidence against pragmatic encroachment.Daniel Eaton & Timothy Pickavance - 2015 - Philosophical Studies 172 (12):3135-3143.
Probability and scepticism.Brian Weatherson - 2013 - In Dylan Dodd & Elia Zardini (eds.), Scepticism and Perceptual Justification. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 71-86.

Add more references