Rigidity, Ontology, and Semantic Structure

Journal of Philosophy 89 (8):410 (1992)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

The phenomenon of rigid designation - in particular, de jure rigidity - is typically treated metaphysically. The picture is: reference is gained in a way that puts no constraints on what an object in other worlds, or counterfactual situations must be like, in order to be the referent of that term, other than 'being this thing'. This allows 'pure metaphysical' investigation into, and discovery of 'the nature' of the referent. It is argued that this presupposes a 'privileged' ontology, of a sort that is far from obvious. An alternative picture of rigidity is sketched, terms have associated criteria of identity and criteria of application for counterfactual situations. A term is rigid when these coincide. Aside from being a better account of rigidity, it also undermines the picture of rigid terms allowing us to 'metaphysically' investigate the nature of the referent: matters of identity and essence for the referent are settled by these semantic constraints (though it can be done in a way that allows are a posteriori necessities).

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,853

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Rigidity, ontology, and semantic structure.Alan Sidelle - 1992 - Journal of Philosophy 89 (8):410-430.
A semantic account of rigidity.Alan Sidelle - 1995 - Philosophical Studies 80 (1):69 - 105.
Critical Notice: Beyond Rigidity. [REVIEW]Arthur Sullivan - 2003 - Philosophical Books 44 (4):317-334.
Propositions, semantic values, and rigidity.Dilip Ninan - 2012 - Philosophical Studies 158 (3):401-413.
Are proper names rigid designators?Pierre Baumann - 2010 - Axiomathes 20 (2-3):333-346.
Rigid designation and semantic structure.Arthur Sullivan - 2007 - Philosophers' Imprint 7:1-22.
Demonstratives without rigidity or ambiguity.Ethan Nowak - 2014 - Linguistics and Philosophy 37 (5):409-436.
Bill Gates is not a parking meter: Philosophical quality control in automated ontology building.Catherine Legg & Samuel Sarjant - 2012 - Proceedings of the Symposium on Computational Philosophy, AISB/IACAP World Congress 2012 (Birmingham, England, July 2-6).
Identity Syntax.Roger Wertheimer - 1999 - In Tom Rockmore (ed.), The Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy. Philosophy Document Center. pp. 171-186.
Semantic structure in short-term memory.Nancy M. Henley, Harvey L. Noyes & James Deese - 1968 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 77 (4):587.
Kinds, general terms, and rigidity: A reply to LaPorte.Stephen P. Schwartz - 2002 - Philosophical Studies 109 (3):265 - 277.
Rigidity, natural kind terms and metasemantics.Corine Besson - 2010 - In Helen Beebee & Nigel Sabbarton-Leary (eds.), The Semantics and Metaphysics of Natural Kinds. Routledge. pp. 25--44.
Explanation in the Semantic Conception of Theory Structure.Paul Thompson - 1988 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1988:286 - 296.

Analytics

Added to PP
2016-06-30

Downloads
26 (#610,229)

6 months
7 (#428,584)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Alan Sidelle
University of Wisconsin, Madison

Citations of this work

Ordinary objects.Daniel Z. Korman - 2011 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Spatio-temporal coincidence and the grounding problem.Karen Bennett - 2004 - Philosophical Studies 118 (3):339-371.
Natural Kinds and Natural Kind Terms: Myth and Reality.Sören Häggqvist & Åsa Wikforss - 2018 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 69 (4):911-933.
Rigid Application.Michael Devitt - 2005 - Philosophical Studies 125 (2):139-165.

View all 23 citations / Add more citations

References found in this work

No references found.

Add more references