From “Paradigm” to “Disciplinary Matrix”: A Fatal Step

Epistemology and Philosophy of Science 59 (4):73-91 (2022)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

The citation index of Thomas Kuhn’s work may strike any imagination. “The Structure of Scientific Revolutions” is undoubtedly a twentieth-century record-breaker in the field of philosophy of science in terms of such a scientometric parameter. But such fame has been bitter in many ways and placed a heavy burden on the author. For several decades he has been the target of the harshest and most severe criticism. Often the concept of “normal science” and the “scientific revolution” as a “Gestalt switch” was declared ridiculous and absurd. The paper analyses three lines of criticism of Kuhn’s concept: the first came from practicing scientists, the second from specialists in the philosophy of science, and the third from the field of social epistemology. Reproaches about the political bias of Kuhn’s concept were taken to extremes, since his views were widely popular. In our opinion, Kuhn should be called a victim of spontaneous hypercriticism. This circumstance did not allow him to improve the original model of scientific revolutions. In this respect, replacing the concept of “paradigm” with the concept of “disciplinary matrix” was a step backwards, not forwards. However, it is impossible to deny that in the field of the historiography of science, he acted as a real reformer. With the courage of Don Quixote, he defended the rights of historical reconstruction, the preservation of the historical past of science, which should not be completely assimilated within the framework of the modern system of knowledge. His motto was – “penetrate the minds of other people who lived in the past.” He boldly argued that in the process of historical development, science changes not only ideas about the object of knowledge, but also the reference of its ideas and concepts. Such a formulation of the question has not yet been fully reflected in modern epistemological concepts.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,435

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Teaching scientific creativity through philosophy of science.Rasmus Jaksland - 2021 - European Journal for Philosophy of Science 11 (4):1-17.
Ethics and its disciplinary matrix.Gabriel Bello - 2011 - Azafea: Revista de Filosofia 13:221-240.
Disciplinary classifications and normative regulation of science.Ilya T. Kasavin - 2018 - Epistemology and Philosophy of Science 55 (1):23-30.
3 From Paradigm to Disciplinary Matrix and Exemplar.James A. Marcum - 2012 - In Vasō Kintē & Theodore Arabatzis (eds.), Kuhn's The structure of scientific revolutions revisited. New York: Routledge. pp. 41.
Hegelian Legacy and Marxian Paradigm.Krishna Chandra Sharma - 2005 - Journal of Philosophy: A Cross-Disciplinary Inquiry 1 (1):4-5.
Framework.Darrell Patrick Rowbottom - 2015 - In Kocku von Stuckrad & Robert A. Segal (eds.), Vocabulary for the Study of Religion: F-O. Brill.
Conceptual Framework.Darrell Patrick Rowbottom - 2015 - Vocabulary for the Study of Religion.
Production of knowledge about the knowledge.Olga Koshovets - 2017 - Epistemology and Philosophy of Science 52 (2):40-46.

Analytics

Added to PP
2022-11-17

Downloads
5 (#1,526,240)

6 months
4 (#787,091)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

No references found.

Add more references