How is scientific analysis possible?

In Toby Handfield (ed.), Dispositions and Causes. Oxford University Press, Clarendon Press ; (2009)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

One of the most powerful tools in science is the analytic method, whereby we seek to understand complex systems by studying simpler sub-systems from which the complex is composed. If this method is to be successful, something about the sub-systems must remain invariant as we move from the relatively isolated conditions in which we study them, to the complex conditions in which we want to put our knowledge to use. This paper asks what this invariant could be. The paper shows that the kinds of thing that a Humean might point to – behaviour, laws, and dispositions – cannot play the role required of the invariant in question. Nor, indeed, can non-Humean causal powers of the kind advocated by contemporary metaphysicians such as Ellis and Lierse. The paper suggests that the analytic method presupposes a kind of entity that does not appear in standard ontologies – a metaphysically substantial notion of causal influence. This notion of causal influence is one that Cartwright has also seen the need for, though she does not seem to take the notion as seriously as she should.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,853

External links

  • This entry has no external links. Add one.
Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

The conditional analysis of dispositions and the intrinsic dispositions thesis.Sungho Choi - 2009 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 78 (3):568-590.
The metaphysics of forces.Olivier Massin - 2009 - Dialectica 63 (4):555-589.
Dispositions and ceteris paribus laws.Alice Drewery - 2001 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 52 (4):723-733.
An "at-at" theory of causal influence.Wesley C. Salmon - 1977 - Philosophy of Science 44 (2):215-224.
Causal realism and the laws of nature.Richard Corry - 2006 - Philosophy of Science 73 (3):261-276.
Substantial causes and nomic determination.Henry Byerly - 1979 - Philosophy of Science 46 (1):57-81.
Causation Without Influence.Tomasz Bigaj - 2012 - Erkenntnis 76 (1):1-22.
Causation, Laws and Dispositions.Andreas Hüttemann - 2007 - In Max Kistler & Bruno Gnassounou (eds.), Dispositions and Causal Powers. Ashgate.

Analytics

Added to PP
2009-01-28

Downloads
1 (#1,900,947)

6 months
1 (#1,469,946)

Historical graph of downloads

Sorry, there are not enough data points to plot this chart.
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Richard Corry
University of Tasmania

Citations of this work

Emerging from the causal drain.Richard Corry - 2013 - Philosophical Studies 165 (1):29-47.
Can Dispositional Essences Ground the Laws of Nature?Richard Corry - 2011 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 89 (2):263-275.
Belief as the Power to Judge.Nicholas Koziolek - 2020 - Topoi 39 (5):1167-1176.
Structural Equations and Analysis of Dispositions.Toby Friend - 2023 - Ergo: An Open Access Journal of Philosophy 10.

View all 10 citations / Add more citations

References found in this work

No references found.

Add more references