How to do things with (recorded) words

Philosophical Studies 167 (2):485-495 (2014)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

The aim of this paper is to evaluate which context determines the illocutionary force of written or recorded utterances—those involved in written texts, films and images, conceived as recordings that can be seen or heard in different occasions. More precisely, my paper deals with the “metaphysical” or constitutive role of context—as opposed to its epistemic or evidential role: my goal is to determine which context is semantically relevant in order to fix the illocutionary force of a speech act, as distinct from the information the addressee uses to ascertain the semantically relevant context. In particular I will try to assess two different perspectives on this problem, a Conventionalist Perspective and an Intentionalist Perspective. Drawing on the literature on indexicals in written texts and recorded messages, I will argue in favor of the Intentionalist Perspective: the relevant context is the one intended by the speaker. Bringing intentions into the picture, however, requires qualification; in particular, I will distinguish my Weak Intentionalist proposal from a Strong Intentionalist one. I will show that the Weak Intentionalist Perspective is flexible enough to deal with cases of delayed communication, but not so unrestricted as to yield counter-intuitive consequences

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,829

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Three Approaches to the Study of Speech Acts.Maciej Witek - 2013 - Dialogue and Universalism 23 (1):129-141.
Naturalising Illocutionary Rules.Maciej Witek - 2010 - In Marcin Miłkowski & Konrad Talmont-Kaminski (eds.), Beyond Description. Naturalism and Normativity. College Publications.
Context of utterance and intended context.Claudia Bianchi - 2001 - Lecture Notes in Computer Science 2116:73-86.
Failing to do things with words.Nicole Wyatt - 2009 - Southwest Philosophy Review 25 (1):135-142.
‘Nobody Loves Me’: Quantification and Context.Claudia Bianchi - 2006 - Philosophical Studies 130 (2):377 - 397.
Recorded music: philosophical and critical reflections.Mine Doğantan (ed.) - 2008 - London: Middlesex University Press.
Reference and Monstrosity.Paolo Santorio - 2012 - Philosophical Review 121 (3):359-406.
A plea for pragmatics.Jonas Åkerman - 2009 - Synthese 170 (1):155 - 167.
The semantics of symbolic speech.Paul Berckmans - 1997 - Law and Philosophy 16 (2):145-176.
The Forgiveness We Speak: The Illocutionary Force of Forgiving.Glen Pettigrove - 2004 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 42 (3):371-392.

Analytics

Added to PP
2013-03-08

Downloads
130 (#140,357)

6 months
15 (#165,714)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Claudia Bianchi
Università Vita-Salute San Raffaele (Milan)

References found in this work

How to do things with words.John Langshaw Austin - 1962 - Oxford [Eng.]: Clarendon Press. Edited by Marina Sbisá & J. O. Urmson.
Thought and reference.Kent Bach - 1987 - New York: Clarendon Press.
Intention and convention in speech acts.Peter F. Strawson - 1964 - Philosophical Review 73 (4):439-460.
Thought and Reference.Bernard W. Kobes - 1991 - Philosophical Review 100 (3):469.

View all 25 references / Add more references