Results for 'persons and rights'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  18
    Japanese Right-Wing Discourse in International Context: Minoda Muneki's Interwar Writings on Class and Nation.John Person - 2018 - Journal of the History of Ideas 79 (4):635-657.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. Selected Papers: Volume Ii: Persons and Values.Joan and Penelope Mackie (ed.) - 1985 - Oxford University Press.
    This collection of John Mackie's papers on personal identity and topics in moral and political philosophy, some of which have not previously been published, deal with such issues as: multiple personality; the transcendental "I"; responsibility and language; aesthetic judgements; Sidgwick's pessimism; act-utiliarianism; right-based moral theories; cooperation, competition, and moral philosophy; universalization; rights, utility, and external costs; norms and dilemmas; Parfit's population paradox; and the combination of partially-ordered preferences.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  55
    Alterations in the three components of selfhood in persons with post-traumatic stress disorder symptoms: A pilot qEEG neuroimaging study.Andrew And Alexander Fingelkurts - 2018 - Open Neuroimaging Journal 12:42-54.
    Background and Objective: Understanding how trauma impacts the self-structure of individuals suffering from the Post-Traumatic Stress Disorder (PTSD) symptoms is a complex matter and despite several attempts to explain the relationship between trauma and the “Self”, this issue still lacks clarity. Therefore, adopting a new theoretical perspective may help understand PTSD deeper and to shed light on the underlying psychophysiological mechanisms. Methods: In this study, we employed the “three-dimensional construct model of the experiential selfhood” where three major components of selfhood (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  4.  21
    Double Recognition: Persons and Rights in T.H. Green.M. Hann - 2015 - Collingwood and British Idealism Studies 21 (1):63-80.
    The work of T.H. Green provides a justificatory argument for human rights which is a powerful alternative to the still prevailing account of rights, which sees them as somehow tied to human nature and argues that humans have rights qua humans, and independent of society. Green's account of rights turns on the process of social recognition. However, the precise mechanism for recognition is left slightly ambiguous. This paper argues that recognition in Green can be usefully divided (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  14
    Rights, Persons, and Organizations: A Legal Theory for Bureaucratic Society.Meir Dan-Cohen - 1986 - Quid Pro Books.
  6. Personal Bodily Rights, Abortion, and Unplugging the Violinist.Francis J. Beckwith - 1992 - International Philosophical Quarterly 32 (1):105-118.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  7. Toleration, Respect for Persons, and the Free Speech Right to do Moral Wrong.Kristian Skagen Ekeli - 2020 - In Mitja Sardoč (ed.), The Palgrave Handbook of Toleration. Palgrave-Macmillan. pp. 149-172.
    The purpose of this chapter is to consider the question of whether respect for persons requires toleration of the expression of any extremist political or religious viewpoint within public discourse. The starting point of my discussion is Steven Heyman and Jonathan Quong’s interesting defences of a negative answer to this question. They argue that respect for persons requires that liberal democracies should not tolerate the public expression of extremist speech that can be regarded as recognition-denying or respect-denying speech (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  28
    Multiple Personality and Moral Responsibility.Stephen E. Braude - 1996 - Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 3 (1):37-54.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Multiple Personality and Moral ResponsibilityStephen E. Braude (bio)AbstractThe philosophical literature on multiple personality has focused primarily on problems about personal identity and psychological explanation. But multiple personality and other dissociative phenomena raise equally important and even more urgent questions about moral responsibility, in particular: In what respect(s) and to what extent should a multiple be held responsible for the actions of his/her alternate personalities? Cases of dreaming help illustrate (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  9.  51
    Rights, Persons, and Organizations.Roger A. Shiner - 1989 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 19 (4):661-684.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  20
    Persons and their rights in law and morality.Denise Meyerson - unknown
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  46
    Patients' privacy of the person and human rights.Jay Woogara - 2005 - Nursing Ethics 12 (3):273-287.
    The UK Government published various circulars to indicate the importance of respecting the privacy and dignity of NHS patients following the implementation of the Human Rights Act, 1998. This research used an ethnographic method to determine the extent to which health professionals had in fact upheld the philosophy of these documents. Fieldwork using nonparticipant observation, and unstructured and semistructured interviews with patients and staff, took place over six months in three acute care wards in a large district NHS trust (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  12. The Rights of Future Persons and the Ontology of Time.Aaron M. Griffith - 2017 - Journal of Social Philosophy 48 (1):58-70.
    Many are committed to the idea that the present generation has obligations to future generations, for example, obligations to preserve the environment and certain natural resources for those generations. However, some philosophers want to explain why we have these obligations in terms of correlative rights that future persons have against persons in the present. Attributing such rights to future persons is controversial, for there seem to be compelling arguments against the position. According to the “nonexistence” (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  13.  37
    Can only one person be right? The development of objectivism and social preferences regarding widely shared and controversial moral beliefs.Larisa Heiphetz & Liane L. Young - 2017 - Cognition 167 (C):78-90.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  14.  22
    Person and Human Being in the UNESCO Declaration on Bioethics and Human Rights.John M. Haas - 2007 - The National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly 7 (1):41-50.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  20
    Empiricism and Rights Justify the Allocation of Health Care Resources to Persons with Disorders of Consciousness.Joseph T. Giacino, Yelena G. Bodien, David Zuckerman, Jaimie Henderson, Nicholas D. Schiff & Joseph J. Fins - 2021 - American Journal of Bioethics Neuroscience 12 (2-3):169-171.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. The rights of persons and the rights of property.Eran Asoulin - 2017 - Arena 151.
    Mirvac chief executive Susan Lloyd-Hurwitz, not one usually associated with sympathy for tenants on the rental market, said earlier this year that ‘renting in Australia is generally a very miserable customer experience…the whole industry is set up to serve the owner not the tenant’ Her observation is basically correct and the solution she offers is to change the current situation where small investors, supported by generous government tax concessions, provide effectively all of the country’s private rental housing. Lloyd-Hurwitz wants Mirvac, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  59
    Personal Integrity, Practical Recognition, and Rights.Eric Mack - 1993 - The Monist 76 (1):101-118.
    The intuitive core of moral individualism is the belief in the supreme moral importance of the individual. The task of the advocate of moral individualism is to provide a coherent explication of what is encompassed within this moral importance—an explication which extends and rationally reinforces the original intuitive core. My view is that there are two distinct, albeit fundamentally complementary, facets within a well-articulated doctrine of moral individualism. These two facets correspond to the common division of ethical theory into the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  18. Book Reviews-Persons and Their Bodies: Rights, Responsibilities, Relationships.Mark J. Cherry & Dahlian Kirby - 2001 - Bioethics 15 (2):172-173.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  21
    XI*—Neonates, Persons and the Right to Life.Edgar Page - 1989 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 89 (1):165-178.
    Edgar Page; XI*—Neonates, Persons and the Right to Life, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 89, Issue 1, 1 June 1989, Pages 165–178, https://doi.or.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. Ritual and Rightness in the Analects.Hagop Sarkissian - 2013 - In Amy Olberding (ed.), Dao Companion to the Analects. pp. 95-116.
    Li (禮) and yi (義) are two central moral concepts in the Analects. Li has a broad semantic range, referring to formal ceremonial rituals on the one hand, and basic rules of personal decorum on the other. What is similar across the range of referents is that the li comprise strictures of correct behavior. The li are a distinguishing characteristic of Confucian approaches to ethics and socio-political thought, a set of rules and protocols that were thought to constitute the wise (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  21.  10
    The Human Person and an International Bill of Rights.Tibor Payzs - 1946 - Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 21:130-147.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  4
    The Human Person and an International Bill of Rights.Tibor Payzs - 1946 - Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 21:130-147.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. Dignity, Rank, and Rights: The 2009 Tanner Lectures at UC Berkeley.Jeremy Waldron - 2009 - Ssrn Elibrary.
    st of these lectures, I present a conception of dignity that preserves its ancient association with rank and station, and a conception of human dignity that amounts to a generalization of high status across all human beings. The lectures argue that this provides a better understanding of human dignity and of the work it does in theories of rights than the better-known Kantian conception. The second lecture focuses particularly on the importance of dignity - understood in this way - (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  24. Problem: The Human Person and an International Bill of Rights.Tibor Payzs - 1946 - Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 21:111.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  1
    Introduction: Rights, Religion, Persons, and Justice.William Sweet - 2018 - Philosophy, Culture, and Traditions 14:1-5.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26. Minds, persons, and space: An fMRI investigation into the relational complexity of higher-order intentionality.Anna Abraham, Markus Werning, Hannes Rakoczy, D. Yves von Cramon & Ricarda I. Schubotz - 2008 - Consciousness and Cognition 17 (2):438-450.
    Mental state reasoning or theory-of-mind has been the subject of a rich body of imaging research. Although such investigations routinely tap a common set of regions, the precise function of each area remains a contentious matter. With the help of functional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI), we sought to determine which areas are involved when processing mental state or intentional metarepresentations by focusing on the relational aspect of such representations. Using non-intentional relational representations such as spatial relations between persons and (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  27.  19
    Persons and Bodies: Constitution Without Mereology?Dean Zimmerman - 2002 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64 (3):599-606.
    Lynne Rudder Baker and many others think that paradigmatic instances of one object constituting another—a piece of marble constituting a statue, or an aggregate of particles constituting a living body—involve two distinct objects in the same place at the same time. Some who say this believe in the doctrine of temporal parts; but others, like Baker, reject this doctrine. Such philosophers, whom one might call “coincidentalists”, cannot say that these objects manage to share space in virtue of sharing a temporal (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  28.  47
    ‘Even if you're positive, you still have rights because you are a person’: Human rights and the reproductive choice of hiv-positive persons.Leslie London, Phyllis J. Orner & Landon Myer - 2007 - Developing World Bioethics 8 (1):11-22.
    Global debates in approaches to HIV/AIDS control have recently moved away from a uniformly strong human rights-based focus. Public health utilitarianism has become increasingly important in shaping national and international policies. However, potentially contradictory imperatives may require reconciliation of individual reproductive and other human rights with public health objectives. Current reproductive health guidelines remain largely nonprescriptive on the advisability of pregnancy amongst HIV-positive couples, mainly relying on effective counselling to enable autonomous decision-making by clients. Yet, health care provider (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  29. Moral Status: Obligations to Persons and Other Living Things.Mary Anne Warren - 1997 - Oxford, GB: Clarendon Press.
    Mary Anne Warren investigates a theoretical question that is at the centre of practical and professional ethics: what are the criteria for having moral status? That is: what does it take to be an entity towards which people have moral considerations? Warren argues that no single property will do as a sole criterion, and puts forward seven basic principles which establish moral status. She then applies these principles to three controversial moral issues: voluntary euthanasia, abortion, and the status of non-human (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  30.  30
    Self-ownership and despotism: Locke on property in the person, divine dominium of human life, and rights-forfeiture.Johan Olsthoorn - 2019 - Social Philosophy and Policy 36 (2):242-263.
    :This essay explores the meaning and normative significance of Locke’s depiction of individuals as proprietors of their own person. I begin by reconsidering the long-standing puzzle concerning Locke’s simultaneous endorsement of divine proprietorship and self-ownership. Befuddlement vanishes, I contend, once we reject concurrent ownership in the same object: while God fully owns our lives, humans are initially sole proprietors of their own person. Locke employs two conceptions of “personhood”: as expressing legal independence vis-à-vis humans and moral accountability vis-à-vis God. Humans (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  31.  12
    Law, Person, and Community: Philosophical, Theological, and Comparative Perspectives on Canon Law.John J. Coughlin - 2012 - Oxford University Press USA.
    Law, Person, and Community: Philosophical, Theological, and Comparative Perspectives on Canon Law takes up the fundamental question "What is law?" through a consideration of the interrelation of the concepts of law, person, and community. As with the concept of law described by secular legal theorists, canon law aims to set a societal order that harmonizes the interests of individuals and communities, secures peace, guarantees freedom, and establishes justice. At the same time, canon law rests upon a traditional understanding of the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  57
    Justice and Rights in Aristotle's Politics.John M. Cooper - 1996 - Review of Metaphysics 49 (4):859-872.
    If now we turn to the recent translation of the Politics by Carnes Lord we see that the language of "rights" is completely avoided. Lord prefers to speak sometimes in terms of what a person or group of persons is "entitled to" under the laws, or of what is "open" or "permitted" to them; and he usually or always sticks to "justice" or a related term to translate δίκαιον and its derivatives--whether this is justice as established by the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33. Persons and values.Joan Mackie - 1985 - Oxford: Clarendon Press. Edited by Joan Mackie & Penelope Mackie.
    This collection of John Mackie's papers on personal identity and topics in moral and political philosophy, some of which have not previously been published, deal with such issues as: multiple personality; the transcendental "I"; responsibility and language; aesthetic judgements; Sidgwick's pessimism; act-utiliarianism; right-based moral theories; cooperation, competition, and moral philosophy; universalization; rights, utility, and external costs; norms and dilemmas; Parfit's population paradox; and the combination of partially-ordered preferences.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  34. Orangutans are persons with rights: Amicus Curiae brief in the Sandai case, requested by the Interspecies Justice Foundation.Gary Comstock, Adam Lerner, Macarena Montes Franceschini & Peter Singer - manuscript
    We argue on consequentialist grounds for the transfer of Sandai, an orangutan, to an orangutan sanctuary. First, we show that satisfying his interest in being transferred brings far greater value than the value achieved by keeping him confined. Second, we show that he has the capacities sufficient for personhood. Third, we show that all persons have a right to relative liberty insofar as they have interests they can exercise only under conditions of relative liberty. Fourth, we show that individuals (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Expanding a constricted moral lens : LGBTI persons, human rights, and the capabilities approach.Chloe Schwenke - 2019 - In Lori Keleher & Stacy Kosko (eds.), Agency and Democracy in Development Ethics. Cambridge University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  5
    Roles and rights in the context of just governance and just social mores.Seán Golden - 2023 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 49 (5):554-567.
    Who protects individual liberties and human dignity from domination by the State, by Civil Society or by individuals is a question under debate in China as well as the West, not from the point of view of Liberalism, but from the point of view of ‘Relationality’. Liberalism posits the individual as the measure of these matters but the ‘individual’ in question is an abstraction. Relationality posits social relations as the measure of these matters. Persons are not abstractions. They combine (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  56
    Possible Persons and the Problem of Prenatal Harm.Nicola Jane Williams - 2013 - The Journal of Ethics 17 (4):355-385.
    When attempting to determine which of our acts affect future generations and which affect the identities of those who make up such generations, accounts of personal identity that privilege psychological features and person affecting accounts of morality, whilst highly useful when discussing the rights and wrongs of acts relating to extant persons, seem to come up short. On such approaches it is often held that the intuition that future persons can be harmed by decisions made prior to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  38.  70
    Anarchism and Rights Violations.Charles Sayward - 1982 - Critica 14 (40):105-116.
    The justification of the existence of the state should precede the justification of any particular organization of the state. The paper tries to give a clear argument facing anyone who sets out to do the first thing, which is to justify the existence of the state. The problem facing such a person is to identify which premise of the argument is false and explain why it is false.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39. Personality : The Need for Liberty and Rights.Rubin Gotesky - 1973 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 163:487-488.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. Virtues, Skills, and Right Action.Matt Stichter - 2011 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 14 (1):73-86.
    According to Rosalind Hursthouse’s virtue based account of right action, an act is right if it is what a fully virtuous person would do in that situation. Robert Johnson has criticized the account on the grounds that the actions a non-virtuous person should take are often uncharacteristic of the virtuous person, and thus Hursthouse’s account of right action is too narrow. The non-virtuous need to take steps to improve themselves morally, and the fully virtuous person need not take these steps. (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  41.  26
    Corporations and rights.Nicholas J. Caste - 1992 - Journal of Value Inquiry 26 (2):199-209.
    Corporations despite their status as legally fictitious persons are not such, and to confound them with real persons in even the minimal legal sense is to negate much of the force of the concept of rights when applied to the society. When corporations have rights individual rights become meaningless. While corporations may need some form of protection to make them financially feasible investments, they need not be given the full protection of rights which are (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42.  66
    Paternalism and Right.Paul Schofield - 2017 - Journal of Political Philosophy 26 (1):65-83.
    Typically, we think of republicans and liberals as being suspicious of paternalistic law. But in this paper, I argue that enactment of paternalistic law is actually demanded by republican and liberal values, and that enacting certain paternalistic laws is one way that the republican or liberal state performs its core function. As I explain it, this core function is to create and to maintain conditions of right-conditions of freedom, non-domination, justice, etc.-among persons capable of making legitimate second-personal claims on (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  43.  65
    Human rights from the Nuremberg Doctors Trial to the Geneva Declaration. Persons and institutions in medical ethics and history.Andreas Frewer - 2010 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 13 (3):259-268.
    The “Universal Declaration of Human Rights” and the “Geneva Declaration” by the World Medical Association, both in 1948, were preceded by the foundation of the United Nations in New York (1945), the World Medical Association in London (1946) and the World Health Organization in Geneva (1948). After the end of World War II the community of nations strove to achieve and sustain their primary goals of peace and security, as well as their basic premise, namely the health of human (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44. Persons and bodies: Constitution without mereology? [REVIEW]Dean Zimmerman - 2002 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64 (3):599–606.
    Lynne Rudder Baker and many others think that paradigmatic instances of one object constituting another—a piece of marble constituting a statue, or an aggregate of particles constituting a living body—involve two distinct objects in the same place at the same time. Some who say this believe in the doctrine of temporal parts; but others, like Baker, reject this doctrine. Such philosophers, whom one might call “coincidentalists”, cannot say that these objects manage to share space in virtue of sharing a temporal (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  45.  70
    Self-Defense in International Law and Rights of Persons.Fernando R. Tesón - 2004 - Ethics and International Affairs 18 (1):87-91.
  46.  56
    Personal rights and rule-dependence.Matthew D. Adler - 2000 - Legal Theory 6 (4):337-389.
    Can constitutional rights be both personal and rule-dependent? Can it be true of constitutional adjudication (1) that a constitutional litigant must assert rights, and yet also (2) that the viability of a constitutional challenge depends (or sometimes depends) on whether a particular type of legal rule, for example, a discriminatory or poorly tailored rule, is in force?
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  15
    Correlativity, Personality, and the Emerging Consensus on Corrective Justice.Ernest J. Weinrib - 2001 - Theoretical Inquiries in Law 2 (1).
    Over the last few decades, corrective justice has established itself as central to serious academic discussion of the normative dimension of tort liability. This article describes the consensus about corrective justice that is presently emerging, as is evident from work of the author and from recent work of other tort theorists. The framework for discussing this emerging consensus is what the article calls "the juridical conception of corrective justice." The juridical conception seeks to explicate the most general ideas implicit in (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48. Personal and Common Good – Personal and Common Evil. Liberation Theology perspectives.Tim Noble & Petr Jandejsek - 2020 - European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 12 (4):45-62.
    Whatever its grammatical status, the verb “to discern” has an implicit transitive element. That is to say, we always discern about something or between two options. What is the right course of action in this situation and in these circumstances? In our paper, we want to look at responses to this question from the perspective of the theology of liberation. As the name implies, this is first and foremost a theology, a way of seeking to understand and articulate the faith (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  53
    Experiencing Left and Right in a Non‐Orientable World.Jonathan A. Simon - 2021 - Analytic Philosophy 62 (3):201-222.
    Imagine that the person you see through the looking glass is a real person, with her own experiences, living in an environment that is the mirror-reverse of yours. You look at your right-hand glove as you put it on your right hand; she looks at her left-hand glove as she puts it on her left hand. You feel your heart beating on your left side; she feels her heart beating on her right side. You hear a bird chirping out the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  50. Virtuous Persons and Social Roles.Sean Cordell - 2011 - Journal of Social Philosophy 42 (3):254-272.
    The article discusses the characteristics of virtuous persons in relation to their social role(s). It explores the key features of the neo-Aristotelian account of right action and some problems for this account in the context of a certain social role. The problem can be characterized as a dilemma. When evaluating an action in some role, one view is that the obligations and requirements of roles could be taken as something already given by social or professional role descriptions, such that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000