Results for 'incorruptibility'

79 found
Order:
  1.  22
    Acquiring Incorruption: Maximian Theosis and Scientific Transhumanism.Eugenia Torrance - 2019 - Studies in Christian Ethics 32 (2):177-186.
    Several theologians have pointed to resonances between the Greek Patristic doctrine of deification or theosis and recent transhumanist narratives: both discourses indicate death as the final enemy of humankind and invest heavily in a hoped-for transcendence of life as we know it. These resonances will be investigated further by comparing the approach to human nature found in Maximus the Confessor and in the prominent transhumanists Nick Bostrom and John Harris. In addition to sharing with transhumanists a disavowal of death and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  2
    Incorruptible Socrates?Jordi Pàmias - 2012 - Hermes 140 (3):369-374.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  33
    Born incorruptibly: The third canon of the lateran council (A. D. 649).Michael Hurley & J. S. - 1961 - Heythrop Journal 2 (3):216–236.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  4
    Born Incorruptibly: The Third Canon of the Lateran Council (A. D. 649).Michael Hurley - 1961 - Heythrop Journal 2 (3):216-236.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  46
    Aquinas and the Incorruptibility of the Soul.Joseph A. Novak - 1987 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 4 (4):405 - 421.
  6.  40
    St. Thomas on the Incorruptibility of the Human Soul: A Reassessment of His Argument from Natural Desire.Eike-Henner W. Kluge - 2015 - Review of Metaphysics 68 (4):742-757.
    St. Thomas’s argument for the immortality of the human soul in question 75, article 6 of his Summa Theologica has historically been rejected, most famously perhaps by Duns Scotus, who said that it was inconclusive at best and question begging at worst. This article argues that Scotus’s critique may be unfair because it rests on a mistaken understanding of what St. Thomas means by the phrase “natural desire,” and that if one unpacks the ontological assumptions that underlie St. Thomas’s reasoning (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. The Gray Area for Incorruptible Scientific Research.An Exploration Guided Merton’S. & Norms Conceived - 2010 - In M. Dorato M. Suàrez (ed.), Epsa Epistemology and Methodology of Science. Springer. pp. 149.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  57
    Avicenna and Aquinas on Incorruptibility.Mary F. Rousseau - 1977 - New Scholasticism 51 (4):524-536.
  9.  73
    Codes of Ethics, Orientation Programs, and the Perceived Importance of Employee Incorruptibility.Sean Valentine & Anthony Johnson - 2005 - Journal of Business Ethics 61 (1):45-53.
    The purpose of this study was to determine the degree to which the review of corporate ethics codes is associated with individuals’ perceptions of the importance of virtue ethics, or more specifically, employee incorruptibility. A convenience sample of individuals working for a university or one of several business organizations located in the Mountain West region of the United States was compiled with a self-report questionnaire. A usable sample of 143 persons representing both the public and private industries was secured (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  10. Hindu inheritance incorruptible: studies mainly in the philosophy of the state and community.Basanta Kumar Mallik - 1967 - Calcutta: Published for the Basanta Kumar Mallik Trust by K.L. Mukhopadhyay.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  42
    Oikos, The Incorruptible: The Ecological Reasons of the Sacred.Sergio Manghi - 2013 - World Futures 69 (3):119-166.
    In this article, I will show how the notion of ecology of mind developed by Gregory Bateson (1972, 1979; Bateson and Bateson 1987), constitutes a third way, with respect to those two trends that I have here called naturism and realism. I will try to show how Bateson's notion of ecology of mind (that sometimes I will call briefly ecosystemic) is closely linked to notions of epistemology and of the sacred, and how it can highlight potential complementarities between the realist (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. Not that simple : Avicenna, Rāzī, and Ṭūsī on the incorruptibility of the human soul at Ishārāt VII.6.Davlat Dadikhuda - 2018 - In Abdelkader Al Ghouz (ed.), Islamic philosophy from the 12th to the 14th century. Bonn: Bonn University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  6
    Les modes de rattachements instinctifs, fonctions incorruptibLes.E. De Greeff - 1951 - Dialectica 5 (3-4):376-392.
    SummaryStarting with an analysis of the respiratory function and of the way it automatically connects the living organism with the physical milieu without any conscious or voluntary effort, Dr De Greeff then asserts that, on the Psychological level, similar basic mechanisms connect the individual with the social environment, and more generally with the Cosmos.Typical disorders of these mechanisms are to be seen in melancholic depressions and in the feelings of strangeness and loneliness they bring about. These mechanisms have à neural (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. Léon Bardales et les juges généraux ou la corruption des incorruptibles.I. Sevçenko - 1949 - Byzantion 19:247-59.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  5
    Les modes de rattachements instinctifs, fonctions incorruptibLes.E. De Greeff - 1951 - Dialectica 5 (3‐4):376-392.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  10
    Acting from the Motive of Duty and the Incorruptible Ideal Moral Agent.Margit Ruffing, Guido A. De Almeida, Ricardo R. Terra & Valerio Rohden - 2008 - In Margit Ruffing, Guido A. De Almeida, Ricardo R. Terra & Valerio Rohden (eds.), Law and Peace in Kant's Philosophy/Recht und Frieden in der Philosophie Kants: Proceedings of the 10th International Kant Congress/Akten des X. Internationalen Kant-Kongresses. Walter de Gruyter.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  37
    A Note on Contraries and the Incorruptibility of the Human Soul In St. Thomas Aquinas.Frederick D. Wilhelmsen - 1993 - American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 67 (3):333-338.
  18.  20
    Dominus Mortis: Martin Luther on the Incorruptibility of God in Christ. By David J. Luy. Pp. x, 266, Minneapolis, Fortress Press, 2014, $25.99. [REVIEW]Patrick Madigan - 2017 - Heythrop Journal 58 (3):448-449.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  68
    The Faces of Simplicity in Descartes’s Soul.Marleen Rozemond - 2014 - In K. Corcilius, D. Perler & C. Helmig (eds.), The Parts of the Soul. De Gruyter. pp. 219-244.
    In this paper I explain several ways in which Descartes denied that the human soul or mind is composite and the role this idea played in his thought. The mind is whole in the whole and whole in the parts of the body because it has no parts. Unlike body, the mind is indivisible, and this is a different idea from the thought that mind and body are incorruptible. Descartes connects the immortality of the soul with its status as a (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  20.  8
    Eternality.Joshua Hoffman & Gary S. Rosenkrantz - 2002 - In The Divine Attributes. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 97–110.
    This chapter contains section titled: Temporal Versus Atemporal Eternality A Defense of Temporal Eternality Incorruptibility Versus Immutability.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. Уявна зустріч при вході до храму аполлона в дельфах: Самопізнання і само-любність у йогана ґеорґа гамана і григорія сковороди. Порівняльний аналіз.Роланд Піч - 2018 - Sententiae 37 (1):65-86.
    This paper argues that the foundation for Skovoroda’s philosophical evolution was laid by the elements of his existential experience: overcoming the fear of death; uncertainty of an individual’s existence in the world; friendship; a series of events in his social life, simultaneous to changes in his works. The most fundamental factor of this experience was Skovoroda’s Christian identity, particularly his continuous efforts to grasp the meaning of the most crucial dogma of Christian religion – the mystery of Resurrection.The totality of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  22.  95
    Personal Identity and Resurrection: How Do We Survive Our Death?Georg Gasser - 2010 - Ashgate.
    What happens to us when we die? According to Christian faith, we will rise again bodily from the dead. This claim raises a series of philosophical and theological conundrums: Is it rational to hope for life after death in bodily form? Will it truly be “we” who are raised again or will it be post-mortem duplicates of us? How can personal identity be secured? What is God's role in resurrection and everlasting life? In response to these conundrums, this volume presents (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  23.  31
    Descartes on persistence and temporal parts.Geoffrey Gorham - 2010 - In Joseph Keim Campbell, Michael O'Rourke & Harry Silverstein (eds.), Time and Identity. MIT Press.
    This chapter discusses the “real distinction” between the mind and the body and a demonstration of the immortality of the soul as demonstrated in Descartes’s Meditations. Early readers of Descartes’s work like Arnauld and Mersenne rejected the idea on the grounds that “it does not seem to follow from the fact that the mind is distinct from the body that it is incorruptible or immortal.” In light of this, Descartes devised a more detailed proof of immortality based on two assumptions (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  24. Cartesian Substances, Individual Bodies, and Corruptibility.Dan Kaufman - 2014 - Res Philosophica 91 (1):71-102.
    According to the Monist Interpretation of Descartes, there is really only one corporeal substance—the entire extended plenum. Evidence for this interpretation seems to be provided by Descartes in the Synopsis of the Meditations, where he claims that all substances are incorruptible. Finite bodies, being corruptible, would then fail to be substances. On the other hand, ‘body, taken in the general sense,’ being incorruptible, would be a corporeal substance. In this paper, I defend a Pluralist Interpretation of Descartes, according to which (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  25. Neither 'Good' in Terms of 'Better' nor 'Better' in Terms of 'Good'.Johan E. Gustafsson - 2014 - Noûs 48 (1):466-473.
    In this paper, I argue against defining either of ‘good’ and ‘better’ in terms of the other. According to definitions of ‘good’ in terms of ‘better’, something is good if and only if it is better than some indifference point. Against this approach, I argue that the indifference point cannot be defined in terms of ‘better’ without ruling out some reasonable axiologies. Against defining ‘better’ in terms of ‘good’, I argue that this approach either cannot allow for the incorruptibility (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  26. Hyperventilating about intrinsic value.Fred Feldman - 1998 - The Journal of Ethics 2 (4):339-354.
    Plato, Aristotle, Kant, Brentano, Moore, and Chisholm have suggested marks or criteria of intrinsic goodness. I distinguish among eight of these. I focus in this paper on four: (a) unimprovability, (b) unqualifiedness, (c) dependence upon intrinsic natures, and (d) incorruptibility. I try to show that each of these is problematic in some way. I also try to show that they are not equivalent – they point toward distinct conceptions of intrinsic goodness. In the end it appears that none of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  27.  49
    Hyperventilating about Intrinsic Value.Fred Feldman - 1998 - The Journal of Ethics 2 (4):339-354.
    Plato, Aristotle, Kant, Brentano, Moore, and Chisholm have suggested ’’marks‘‘ or criteria of intrinsic goodness. I distinguish among eight of these. I focus in this paper on four: (a) unimprovability, (b) unqualifiedness, (c) dependence upon intrinsic natures, and (d) incorruptibility. I try to show that each of these is problematic in some way. I also try to show that they are not equivalent – they point toward distinct conceptions of intrinsic goodness. In the end it appears that none of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  28. Permanent Creation: A Study in the Thought of Thomas Aquinas.Montague Brown - 1986 - Dissertation, Boston College
    The intellectual climate in which Aquinas matured was one of conflict. On the one hand, he inherited a philosophical tradition from the Greeks which held that "nothing comes from nothing." On the other, a strong theological tradition held that, since the world was created from nothing, it tends toward nothing and will, in fact, finally return to nothing. ;Aquinas counters that both traditions are mistaken in considering all making as change. Besides the making that is of this particular thing, besides (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  18
    The Evolution of Gregory Skovoroda’s Philosophical Views as related to his Spiritual Biography.Victor Chernyshov - 2018 - Sententiae 37 (1):65-86.
    This paper argues that the foundation for Skovoroda’s philosophical evolution was laid by the elements of his existential experience: overcoming the fear of death; uncertainty of an individual’s existence in the world; friendship; a series of events in his social life, simultaneous to changes in his works. The most fundamental factor of this experience was Skovoroda’s Christian identity, particularly his continuous efforts to grasp the meaning of the most crucial dogma of Christian religion – the mystery of Resurrection. The totality (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30. : Facts and texts. des Chene - unknown
    The science of the soul exceeds all other parts of philosophy not only in “dignity and exactness”, but also in “usefulness, necessity, charm, and, above all, in difficulty”.1 As the body is the subject of health and disease, so too the soul is the subject of virtue and vice; and just as the physician must devote great effort to knowing the body, anyone who treats morals “must take care to have a clear understanding of things pertaining to the scientia de (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31. Why the View of Intellect in De Anima I 4 Isn’t Aristotle’s Own.Caleb Cohoe - 2018 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 26 (2):241-254.
    In De Anima I 4, Aristotle describes the intellect (nous) as a sort of substance, separate and incorruptible. Myles Burnyeat and Lloyd Gerson take this as proof that, for Aristotle, the intellect is a separate eternal entity, not a power belonging to individual humans. Against this reading, I show that this passage does not express Aristotle’s own views, but dialectically examines a reputable position (endoxon) about the intellect that seems to show that it can be subject to change. The passage’s (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. How Can Satan Cast Out Satan?: Violence and the Birth of the Sacred in Christopher Nolan’s The Dark Knight.Nicholas Bott - 2013 - Contagion: Journal of Violence, Mimesis, and Culture 20:239-251.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:How Can Satan Cast Out Satan? Violence and the Birth of the Sacred in Christopher Nolan’s The Dark Knight1Nicholas Bott (bio)Last Summer, Christopher Nolan’s final installment of the Batman trilogy hit theaters. The Dark Knight Rises promised to be the epic conclusion of a hero’s journey, a journey of a man’s transformation into a legend. Little was revealed in the official trailers, except that evil was rising in Gotham (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  7
    Teaching sunspots: Disciplinary identity and scholarly practice in the Collegio Romano.Renee Raphael - 2014 - History of Science 52 (2):130-152.
    This article examines how Jesuit Gabriele Beati taught the subject of sunspots in two textbooks commemorating his teaching of natural philosophy and mathematics at the Collegio Romano. Whereas Beati defended the incorruptibility of the heavens in his natural philosophical course, he argued that sunspots were located on the face of the sun itself and generated and corrupted like terrestrial clouds in his mathematical one. While it may be tempting to attribute these different presentations to censorship practices within the Jesuit (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34.  22
    'They Tend into Nothing by Their Own Nature': Rufus and an Anonymous De Generatione Commentary on the Principles of Corruptibility.Zita V. Toth - 2021 - In Lydia Schumacher (ed.), Early Thirteenth-Century English Franciscan Thought. De Gruyter. pp. 199--220.
    In this paper, I consider Richard Rufus’ account of generation and corrup- tion. This is a fundamental metaphysical question in the Aristotelian framework. Given that there are things that are corruptible (such as trees and cats and the human body), and things that are incorruptible (such as the celestial bodies and angels), what is it that makes one one, and the other the other? In other words, what is the ultimate explanation (in Rufus' terminology, the principle or principles) of corruptibility (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  23
    “Cuerpo” en la tradición antioquena.Patricio de Navascués Benlloch - 2011 - Augustinianum 51 (1):21-45.
    Faced with an Alexandrian (Arian) anthropology of Neoplatonic inspiration, Eustathius adopts a strong position in several statements that is similar to astoic Aristotelianism of the 4th century. Nevertheless, Eustathius's reflection is more genuinely theological, than it is reflective of any particular philosophical trend. For him, the human body is a dynamic concept which finds its full meaning in light of the history of salvation, wherein the incarnate and glorified Logos, the second Adam, brings to completion the perfection and incorruptibility (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  30
    The Scrutiny of Song: Pindar, Politics, and Poetry.Anne Burnett - 1987 - Critical Inquiry 13 (3):434-449.
    Pindar’s songs were composed for men at play, but his poetry was political in its impulse and in its function. The men in question were rich and powerful, and their games were a display of exclusive class attributes, vicariously shared by lesser mortals who responded with gratitude and loyalty . Victories were counted as princely benefactions and laid up as city treasure like the wealth deposited in the treasuries at Delphi . Athletic victory was thus both a manifestation and an (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  7
    Aquinas and Themistius on Intellect.Lorelle Lamascus - 2006 - Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 80:255-273.
    Aquinas puts forward two different, and conflicting, interpretations of Themistius’s account of the intellect. In his earlier interpretation of Themistius, Aquinas understands him to hold the position that both the possible and agent intellect are separate and incorruptible, existing apart from individual human souls but shared in by individual souls in the process of knowing. In De unitate intellectus contra averroistas, however, Aquinas radically departs from this reading, hailing Themistius as a genuine interpreter of the Peripatetic position, while decrying Averroes’s (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  76
    Aquinas and Themistius on Intellect.Lorelle Lamascus - 2006 - Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 80:255-273.
    Aquinas puts forward two different, and conflicting, interpretations of Themistius’s account of the intellect. In his earlier interpretation of Themistius, Aquinas understands him to hold the position that both the possible and agent intellect are separate and incorruptible, existing apart from individual human souls but shared in by individual souls in the process of knowing. In De unitate intellectus contra averroistas, however, Aquinas radically departs from this reading, hailing Themistius as a genuine interpreter of the Peripatetic position, while decrying Averroes’s (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  65
    Spinoza’s Bible.Nancy Levene - 2001 - Philosophy and Theology 13 (1):93-142.
    My essay explores the connections between Spinoza’s theory of biblical interpretation and his conception of prophecy, linking the two through what he calls “moral certainty.” The question of what prophecy conveys is connected to the question of how to read Scripture because readers are in a similar position to both the prophets, who attain sure knowledge of some matter revealed by God, and the audience of prophecy, who have access to this knowledge only through faith. Like prophets, readers are interpreters (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  8
    Spinoza’s Bible.Nancy Levene - 2001 - Philosophy and Theology 13 (1):93-142.
    My essay explores the connections between Spinoza’s theory of biblical interpretation and his conception of prophecy, linking the two through what he calls “moral certainty.” The question of what prophecy conveys is connected to the question of how to read Scripture because readers are in a similar position to both the prophets, who attain sure knowledge of some matter revealed by God, and the audience of prophecy, who have access to this knowledge only through faith. Like prophets, readers are interpreters (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  34
    Paralogismi e Antinomie. Riflessioni Kantiane Sui Concetti di Seele e Ich Denke.Davide Poggi - 2014 - Trans/Form/Ação 37 (s1):37-58.
    This essay focuses on the presence, in the section of the Dialektikdedicated to the issue of the Seele and the psychological paralogisms, of an "antinomic" approach regarding, in particular, the debate on the simplicity of the soul. In the examination of Mendelssohn's thesis concerning the soul's incorruptibility, Kant shows that it is possible to assume, together with the "extensive" criterion, an "intensive" criterion which leads to admitting the "decomposability" of the soul and the possibility of its annihilatio per remissionem. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  73
    Commerce of Human Body Parts: An Eastern Orthodox Response.Patrick Henry Reardon - 2000 - Christian Bioethics 6 (2):205-213.
    The Orthodox Church teaches that the bodies of those in Christ are to be regarded as sanctified by the hearing of the Word and faithful participation in the Sacraments, most particularly the Holy Eucharist; because of the indwelling Holy Spirit the consecrated bodies of Christians do not belong to them but to Christ; with respect to the indwelling Holy Spirit there is no difference between the bodies of Christians before and after death; whether before or after death, the Christian body (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43.  6
    Two ancient theologians’ interpretations of the withered fig tree (Mt 21:18–22).Hennie F. Stander - 2021 - HTS Theological Studies 77 (4):8.
    This article is an investigation on how two theologians from the Early Church interpreted the withered fig tree, as narrated by the evangelist Matthew (Mt 21:18–22). The two theologians referred to are Origen of Alexandria, who belongs to the pre-Nicene era and represents the Alexandrian School, and Ps.-Chrysostom who belongs to the post-Nicene era, and represents the School of Antioch. Origen believed that when the fig tree withered, it referred to Israel’s withering. This interpretation of the narrative surrounding the withered (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  14
    Mind the Gap?Adam Wood - 2015 - Oxford Studies in Medieval Philosophy 3 (1).
    Most contemporary interpreters of Aquinas have assumed that Thomas subscribed to a “non-repeatability principle” such that created entities, once destroyed entirely, cannot be “brought back" into existence, even by God's power. Souls persisting in the interim between death and resurrection thus play an essential identity-preserving role between our death and rising again. No separated souls, no resurrection. Two of Aquinas’s best medieval interpreters, however, reject this interpretation. Leaning largely on one of Aquinas’s late quodlibetal questions, they deny that Thomas held (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  45. Descartes on the Metaphysics of the Material World.Tad M. Schmaltz - 2018 - Philosophical Review 127 (1):1-40.
    It is a matter of continuing scholarly dispute whether Descartes offers a metaphysics of the material world that is “monist” or “pluralist.” One passage that has become crucial to this debate is from the Synopsis of the Meditations, in which Descartes argues that since “body taken in general” is a substance, and since all substances are “by their nature incorruptible,” this sort of body is incorruptible as well. In this article I defend a pluralist reading of this passage, according to (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46.  60
    The Metaphysics of Resurrection.Jason T. Eberl - 2000 - Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 74:215-230.
    Thomas Aquinas was concerned with developing a metaphysical account of the article of Christian faith which asserts that a human person will experience a bodily resurrection at some point after death. This article of faith is prima facie in line with Aquinas’ Aristotelian assertions that a human soul is incorruptible per se and that it is in its natural state only when it is united to a material body of which it is the informing principle. But how is personal identity (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  47. Plato's noble lie: from Kallipolis to Magnesia.David Williams - 2013 - History of Political Thought 34 (3):363-392.
    The tradition of the political lie infamously commences with Platos Noble Lie in the Republic. It is woven with great care into his utopian state on the premise that Philosopher-Rulers are incorruptible wielders of political power.Most treatments of the Noble Lie understand this and then proceed to dismiss Plato on the basis of his unrealistic assumptions about human nature. But when consideration is extended to the Laws, one finds a far more nuanced and relevant Plato uncomfortable with the > practice (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  48.  51
    God, Indivisibles, and Logic in the Later Middle Ages: Adam Wodeham's Response to Henry of Harclay.Edith Dudley Sylla - 1998 - Journal of Nietzsche Studies 7 (1):69-87.
    As its modern edition appears in the Synthese Historical Library, Adam WodehamThis book is an important contribution to the history of philosophy.It will be of interest to all medievalists, particularly to those concerned with medieval science, philosophy, and logic. Theologians and historians of mathematics will also find it useful.Whether charity or [any] other incorruptible form is composed of indivisible forms.Because this difficulty is the same for all composite divisible things, whether intensive or extensive, which are of one and the same (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  49.  43
    Heavenly Matter in Aristotle, Metaphysics Lambda 2.Silvia Fazzo - 2013 - Phronesis 58 (2):160-175.
    This paper emphasizes an unnoticed connection between two lines in Aristotle, Metaphysics Λ.1, 1069a32, and Λ.2, 1069b26. It argues that the Greek text of the former has been obscured in standard editions by unnecessary emendation: if the reading of the mss. is preserved, the text here sets out a programme for research into the elements of heavenly bodies which is taken up in the second part of Λ.2. There, Aristotle distinguishes the matter of heavenly substance as if it were matter (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50.  5
    Slava LISZEK, Marie Guillot. De l’émancipation des femmes à celle du syndicalisme.Christine Bard - 1996 - Clio 3.
    On comprend aisément pourquoi Slava Liszek, qui fut l’une des rédactrices d’Antoinette - le journal féminin de la CGT - a été touchée par Marie Guillot, au point de lui consacrer plusieurs années de recherche et, finalement, une biographie. À l’évidence, il s’agit d’un hommage rendu à une militante lucide et « incorruptible ». Le style trahit une profonde sympathie pour « Marie », qui pourra, selon les goûts, charmer, ou agacer. De toutes façons, le redoutable défi d’une biographie de (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 79