20 found
Order:
Disambiguations
James Messina [17]James P. Messina [2]James Anthony Messina [1]
  1. Kant on the Unity of Space and the Synthetic Unity of Apperception.James Messina - 2014 - Kant Studien 105 (1):5-40.
    In the Transcendental Aesthetic, Kant famously characterizes space as a unity, understood as an essentially singular whole. He further develops his account of the unity of space in the B-Deduction, where he relates the unity of space to the original synthetic unity of apperception, and draws an infamous distinction between form of intuition and formal intuition. Kant ’s cryptic remarks in this part of the Critique have given rise to two widespread and diametrically opposed readings, which I call the Synthesis (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  2. Kant's Necessitation Account of Laws and the Nature of Natures.James Messina - 2017 - In Michela Massimi & Angela Breitenbach (eds.), Kant and the Laws of Nature. New York: Cambridge University Press.
    I elaborate and defend a "necessitarian" interpretation of Kant's account of laws.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  3. The Content of Kant's Pure Category of Substance and Its Use on Phenomena and Noumena.James Messina - 2021 - Philosophers' Imprint 21 (29).
    I begin by arguing that, for Kant, the pure category of substance has both a general content that is in play whenever we think of any entity as a substance as well as a more specific content that arises in conjunction with the thought of what Kant calls a positive noumenon. Drawing on this new “Dual Content” account of the pure category of substance, I offer new answers to two contested questions: What is the relation of the pure category to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  4.  60
    Looking for laws in all the wrong spaces: Kant on laws, the understanding, and space.James Anthony Messina - 2018 - European Journal of Philosophy 26 (1):589-613.
    Prolegomena §38 is intended to elucidate the claim that the understanding legislates a priori laws to nature. Kant cites various laws of geometry as examples and discusses a derivation of the inverse-square law from such laws. I address 4 key interpretive questions about this cryptic text that have not yet received satisfying answers: How exactly are Kant's examples of laws supposed to elucidate the Legislation Thesis? What is Kant's view of the epistemic status of the inverse-square law and, relatedly, of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  5. Conceptual Analysis and the Essence of Space: Kant’s Metaphysical Exposition Revisited.James Messina - 2015 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 97 (4):416-457.
    Name der Zeitschrift: Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie Jahrgang: 97 Heft: 4 Seiten: 416-457.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  6. Leibniz on compossibility.James Messina & Donald Rutherford - 2009 - Philosophy Compass 4 (6):962-977.
    Leibniz's well-known thesis that the actual world is just one among many possible worlds relies on the claim that some possibles are incompossible , meaning that they cannot belong to the same world. Notwithstanding its central role in Leibniz's philosophy, commentators have disagreed about how to understand the compossibility relation. We examine several influential interpretations and demonstrate their shortcomings. We then sketch a new reading, the cosmological interpretation, and argue that it accommodates two key conditions that any successful interpretation must (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  7. The relationship between space and mutual interaction: Kant contra Newton and Leibniz.James Messina - 2017 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 47 (1):43-65.
    Kant claims that we cannot cognize the mutual interaction of substances without their being in space; he also claims that we cannot cognize a ‘spatial community’ among substances without their being in mutual interaction. I situate these theses in their historical context and consider Kant’s reasons for accepting them. I argue that they rest on commitments regarding the metaphysical grounding of, first, the possibility of mutual interaction among substances-as-appearances and, second, the actuality of specific distance-relations among such substances. By illuminating (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  8.  58
    Kant's Stance on the Relationalist-Substantivalist Debate and Its Justification.James Messina - 2018 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 56 (4):697-726.
    kant famously claims that space is merely a feature of the mind—something subjective—rather than a mind-independent feature of reality in itself.1 In accepting the subjectivity thesis, Kant rejects the transcendental realist assumption that he thinks has traditionally, albeit tacitly, been made in debates about the nature of space. According to this assumption, space has to do with things in themselves. For the Newtonians, as Kant understands their position, space is a substance-like thing in itself; for the Leibnizians, space consists in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9.  15
    Where the Laws of Physics Lie: A Reading of Prolegomena § 38.James Messina - 2018 - In Violetta L. Waibel, Margit Ruffing & David Wagner (eds.), Natur und Freiheit. Akten des XII. Internationalen Kant-Kongresses. De Gruyter. pp. 1091-1098.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10. Answering aenesidemus: Schulze's attack on Reinholdian representationalism and its importance for Fichte.James Messina - 2011 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 49 (3):339-369.
    The importance of Gottlob Ernst Schulze's Aenesidemus 1 for the history of German Idealism has been widely recognized. Much as Hume had awoken Kant, Aenesidemus jolted the young Fichte out of his slumbering adherence to Reinhold's formulation of Kant's philosophy, leading him to re-evaluate the claims, methods, and foundations of the Critical philosophy. In his "Review of the Aenesidemus" 2 Fichte set out the results of this re-evaluation, which included his doctrine of intellectual intuition with remarkable and uncharacteristic clarity. 3 (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  11. Space, Pure Intuition, and Laws in the Metaphysical Foundations.James Messina - manuscript
    I am interested in the use Kant makes of the pure intuition of space, and of properties and principles of space and spaces (i.e. figures, like spheres and lines), in the special metaphysical project of MAN. This is a large topic, so I will focus here on an aspect of it: the role of these things in his treatment of some of the laws of matter treated in the Dynamics and Mechanics Chapters. In MAN and other texts, Kant speaks of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. The Marriage of Metaphysics and Geometry in Kant's Prolegomena (Forthcoming in Cambridge Critical Guide to Kant’s Prolegomena).James Messina - 2021 - In Peter Thiekle (ed.), Cambridge Critical Guide to Kant’s Prolegomena. Cambridge.
    Kant was engaged in a lifelong struggle to achieve what he calls in the 1756 Physical Monadology (PM) a “marriage” of metaphysics and geometry (1:475). On one hand, this involved showing that metaphysics and geometry are complementary, despite the seemingly irreconcilable conflicts between these disciplines and between their respective advocates, the Leibnizian-Wolffians and the Newtonians. On the other hand, this involved defining the terms of their union, which meant among other things, articulating their respective roles in grounding Newtonian natural science. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  32
    Resistance at the Border: Kantian Political Theory and the Refugee Crisis.James P. Messina - 2021 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 38 (4):702-718.
    Journal of Applied Philosophy, EarlyView.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  19
    Kant and the Priority of Self-Knowledge.James P. Messina - unknown
    In The Metaphysics of Morals, Kant claims that “the first command” of all self-regarding duties is to know our “heart.” Kant ostensibly identifies our heart with our moral disposition. Strangely, this appears to be precisely the sort of knowledge that, elsewhere, Kant claims is epistemically inaccessible to us. While the more sophisticated attempts to resolve this difficulty succeed in situating an injunction to know the quality of one’s disposition within a Kantian epistemic framework, no account is wholly successful in explaining (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  59
    Kantian Space, Supersubstantivalism, and the Spirit of Spinoza.James Messina - 2014 - Kant Yearbook 6 (1).
    In the first edition of Concerning the Doctrine of Spinoza in Letters to Mendelssohn, Jacobi claims that Kant’s account of space is “wholly in the spirit of Spinoza”. In the first part of the paper, I argue that Jacobi is correct: Spinoza and Kant have surprisingly similar views regarding the unity of space and the metaphysics of spatial properties and laws. Perhaps even more surprisingly, they both are committed to a form of parallelism. In the second part of the paper, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. The marriage of metaphysics and geometry in Kant's Prolegomena.James Messina - 2021 - In Peter Thielke (ed.), Kant's Prolegomena: A Critical Guide. Cambridge University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  17
    Brigitte Falkenburg, Kant’s Cosmology: From the Pre-Critical System to the Antinomy of Pure Reason Cham: Springer Nature Switzerland, 2020 Pp. xvii. + 284 ISBN 9783030522896 (hbk), $84.99. [REVIEW]James Messina - 2022 - Kantian Review 27 (1):165-169.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  22
    Review of Kant on Laws, by Eric Watkins. [REVIEW]James Messina - 2020 - Mind.
    _ Kant on Laws _, by WatkinsEric. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2019. Pp. xv + 297.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. Review of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason: A Critical Guide. [REVIEW]James Messina - 2017 - Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 1.
    Review of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason: A Critical Guide (ed. James O'Shea).
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  38
    The Actual and the Possible: Modality and Metaphysics in Modern Philosophy ed. by Mark Sinclair. [REVIEW]James Messina - 2019 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 57 (4):767-768.
    This edited collection, which grows out of a 2013 British Society for the History of Philosophy conference on the topic of "the actual and the possible" at which early versions of some of the nine essays were presented, explores various episodes in the history of modern metaphysics of modality. It is broad and self-consciously eclectic in its coverage of figures and issues. There are chapters dealing with Spinoza, Wolff, Leibniz and Kant, Kant, Hegel, Russell, Meinong and Łukasiewicz, Heidegger, and Quine. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark