Results for 'Descartes Galileo'

989 found
Order:
  1.  15
    Essay Review 'Neither Proper nor Useful': Jesuit Orthodoxy and Galilean Science.William Wallace, Ugo Baldini, Descartes Galileo & Christoph Grienberger - 2004 - Annals of Science 61 (2):213-218.
    For many years the intellectual activities of the Society of Jesus were dismissed as wholly conservative, as their Ratio studiorum clung to a Ptolemaic–Aristotelian world‐picture despite the rising...
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2.  4
    The World and Man.René Descartes - 2023 - Hackett Publishing Company.
    In late 1633, as Descartes was preparing _The World and Man _for publication, he learned that Galileo had been condemned by the Catholic Church for defending the motion of the earth. His reaction to the news was swift and powerful: as his own treatises also espoused the proposition deemed heretical, he canceled their publication. More than thirty years after Descartes had begun his project, these works were finally published, posthumously, both to acclaim and to controversy. Together, they (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  13
    Exploring the Limits of Preclassical Mechanics: A Study of Conceptual Development in Early Modern Science: Free Fall and Compounded Motion in the Work of Descartes, Galileo and Beeckman.Peter Damerow, Gideon Freudenthal, Peter McLaughlin & Jürgen Renn - 2011 - Springer.
    The question of when and how the basic concepts that characterize modern science arose in Western Europe has long been central to the history of science. This book examines the transition from Renaissance engineering and philosophy of nature to classical mechanics oriented on the central concept of velocity. For this new edition, the authors include a new discussion of the doctrine of proportions, an analysis of the role of traditional statics in the construction of Descartes' impact rules, and go (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  4.  4
    Leibniz’s Early Encounters with Descartes, Galileo, and Spinoza on Infinity.Ohad Nachtomy - 2018 - In Igor Agostini, Richard T. W. Arthur, Geoffrey Gorham, Paul Guyer, Mogens Lærke, Yitzhak Y. Melamed, Ohad Nachtomy, Sanja Särman, Anat Schechtman, Noa Shein & Reed Winegar (eds.), Infinity in Early Modern Philosophy. Cham: Springer Verlag. pp. 131-154.
    This chapter seeks to highlight some of the main threads that Leibniz used in developing his views on infinity in his early years in Paris. In particular, I will be focusing on Leibniz’s encounters with Descartes, Galileo, and Spinoza. Through these encounters, some of the most significant features of Leibniz’s view of infinity will begin to emerge. Leibniz’s response to Descartes reveals his positive attitude to infinity. He rejects Descartes’s view that, since we are finite, we (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  44
    Geometry, Time and Force in the Diagrams of Descartes, Galileo, Torricelli and Newton.Emily R. Grosholz - 1988 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1988:237 - 248.
    Cartesian method both organizes and impoverishes the domains to which Descartes applies it. It adjusts geometry so that it can be better integrated with algebra, and yet deflects a full-scale investigation of curves. It provides a comprehensive conceptual framework for physics, and yet interferes with the exploitation of its dynamical and temporal aspects. Most significantly, it bars a fuller unification of mathematics and physics, despite Descartes' claims to quantify nature. The work of his contemporaries Galileo and Torricelli, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6.  10
    Descartes and Galileo: Copernicanism and the Metaphysical Foundations of Physics.Michael Friedman - 2007 - In Janet Broughton & John Carriero (eds.), A Companion to Descartes. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 69–83.
    This chapter contains section titled: The Crime of Galileo A Discourse on Method The Metaphysical Foundations of Physics References and Further Reading.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  7.  45
    Galileo and Descartes on Copernicanism and the cause of the tides.Tad M. Schmaltz - 2015 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 51:70-81.
  8.  96
    Descartes as critic of Galileo's scientific methodology.Roger Ariew - 1986 - Synthese 67 (1):77 - 90.
    Some philosophers of science suggest that philosophical assumptions must influence historical scholarship, because history (like science) has no neutral data and because the treatment of any particular historical episode is going to be influenced to some degree by one's prior philosophical conceptions of what is important in science. However, if the history of science must be laden with philosophical assumptions, then how can the history of science be evidence for the philosophy of science? Would not an inductivist history of science (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9.  33
    Bacon, Galileo, and Descartes on Imagination and Analogy.Katharine Park, Lorraine Daston & Peter Galison - 1984 - Isis 75:287-289.
  10. Descartes and Galileo : the quantificatin of time and force.Emily Grosholz - 1991 - In Jules Vuillemin & Rushdī Rāshid (eds.), Mathématiques et philosophie de l'antiquité à l'age classique: hommage à Jules Vuillemin. Paris: Diffusion, Presses du CNRS.
  11. Descartes e Galileo.Antonio Nardi - 1981 - Giornale Critico Della Filosofia Italiana 1 (1):129.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. Descartes, Mersenne and Galileo's invisible philosophy.Massimo Bucciantini - 2007 - Giornale Critico Della Filosofia Italiana 3 (1):38-52.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  54
    Physics and metaphysics in Descartes and Galileo.Blake D. Dutton - 1999 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 37 (1):49-71.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Physics and Metaphysics in Descartes and GalileoBlake D. Duttonin his classic biography of Descartes, Charles Adam passes this judgment on the influence of Galileo’s condemnation on the development of Cartesian metaphysics:Sans la condemnation de Galilée, nous aurions eu tout de même la métaphysique de Descartes. Mais nous ne l’aurions problement pas eue sous la forme volumineuse qu’elle a prise avec toutes ces Objections et Reponses, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  14.  39
    Revisiting the Mathematisation Thesis: Galileo, Descartes, Newton, and the Language of Nature.Ladislav Kvasz - 2016 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 30 (4):399-406.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  48
    Galileo Studies.Alexandre Koyré - 1978 - Humanities Press.
  16. Descartes on Physical Vacuum: Rationalism in Natural-Philosophical Debate.Joseph Zepeda - 2013 - Society and Politics 7 (2):126-141.
    Descartes is notorious for holding a strong anti-vacuist position. On his view, according to the standard reading, empty space not only does not exist in nature, but it is logically impossible. The very notion of a void or vacuum is an incoherent one. Recently Eric Palmer has proposed a revisionist reading of Descartes on empty space, arguing that he is more sanguine about its possibility. Palmer makes use of Descartes’ early correspondence with Marin Mersenne, including his commentary (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  17.  91
    Hobbes, Galileo, and the Physics of Simple Circular Motions.John Henry - 2016 - Hobbes Studies 29 (1):9-38.
    _ Source: _Volume 29, Issue 1, pp 9 - 38 Hobbes tried to develop a strict version of the mechanical philosophy, in which all physical phenomena were explained only in terms of bodies in motion, and the only forces allowed were forces of collision or impact. This ambition puts Hobbes into a select group of original thinkers, alongside Galileo, Isaac Beeckman, and Descartes. No other early modern thinkers developed a strict version of the mechanical philosophy. Natural philosophies relying (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  18.  6
    Retrying Galileo, 1633–1992.Maurice A. Finocchiaro - 2005 - University of California Press.
    Preface and Acknowledgments Introduction. The Galileo Affair from Descartes to John Paul II: A Survey of Sources, Facts, and Issues 1. The Condemnation of Galileo 2. Promulgation and Diffusion of the News 3. Emblematic Reactions: Descartes, Peiresc, Galileo’s Daughter 4. Polarizations: Secularism, Liberalism, Fundamentalism 5. Compromises: Viviani, Auzout, Leibniz 6. Myth-making or Enlightenment? Pascal, Voltaire, the Encyclopedia 7. Incompetence or Enlightenment? Pope Benedict XIV 8. New Lies, Documents, Myths, Apologies 9. Napoleonic Wars and Trials 10. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  19.  40
    Space and motion in nature and Scripture: Galileo, Descartes, Newton.Andrew Janiak - 2015 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 51:89-99.
  20.  15
    Readings in epistemology: from Aquinas, Bacon, Galileo, Descartes, Locke, Berkeley, Hume, Kant.Vincent G. Potter (ed.) - 1993 - New York: Fordham University Press.
    A companion volume to On Understanding Understanding, this second edition incorporates corrections to the previous text and includes new readings. The works collected in this volume are mainly from the British Empiricists. The breadth of the selection is not so diverse that the pieces cannot be readily understood by a newcomer to Epistemology, they have a logical progression of development (from Locke to Berkeley to Hume), and all of the philosophers whose work is represented have had great influence on contemporary (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21.  15
    Readings in Epistemology: From Aquinas, Bacon, Galileo, Descartes, Locke, Hume, Kant.Vincent G. Potter - 1993 - New York: Fordham University Press.
    A companion volume to On Understanding Understanding, this second edition incorporates corrections to the previous text and includes new readings. The works collected in this volume are mainly from the British Empiricists. The breadth of the selection is not so diverse that the pieces cannot be readily understood by a newcomer to Epistemology, they have a logical progression of development (from Locke to Berkeley to Hume), and all of the philosophers whose work is represented have had great influence on contemporary (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. On the mathematization of free fall : Galileo, Descartes, and a history of misconstrual.Richard T. W. Arthur - 2016 - In Geoffrey Gorham (ed.), The Language of Nature: Reassessing the Mathematization of Natural Philosophy in the Seventeenth Century. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
  23. Un periodo di storia delle scienze: da Galileo a Newton. Parte I: Da Descartes a Pascal.G. Loria - 1926 - Scientia 20 (39):323.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  17
    Balestra and the Pythagorean Methodology of Galileo and Descartes.D. W. Mertz - 1999 - Modern Schoolman 76 (2-3):211-219.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. "Quantum in se Est": Newton, Kepler, Galileo, Descartes & Lucretius.I. Bernard Cohen - 1964 - Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 38:36.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26.  80
    The architecture of matter: Galileo to Kant.Thomas Anand Holden - 2004 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Thomas Holden presents a fascinating study of theories of matter in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries. These theories were plagued by a complex of interrelated problems concerning matter's divisibility, composition, and internal architecture. Is any material body infinitely divisible? Must we posit atoms or elemental minima from which bodies are ultimately composed? Are the parts of material bodies themselves material concreta? Or are they merely potentialities or possible existents? Questions such as these -- and the press of subtler questions hidden (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  27. Descartes on Nothing in Particular.Eric Palmer - 1999 - In Rocco J. Gennaro & Charles Huenemann (eds.), New Essays on the Rationalists. Oxford University Press. pp. 26-47.
    How coherent is Descartes' conception of vacuum in the Principles? Descartes' arguments attacking the possibility of vacuum are difficult to read and to understand because they reply to several distinct threads of discussion. I separate two strands that have received little careful attention: the scholastic topic of annihilation of space, particularly represented in Albert of Saxony, and the physical arguments concerning vacuum in Galileo that are also continued after the publication of the Principles in Pascal. The distinctness (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  28.  27
    Descartes and Sunspots: Matters of Fact and Systematizing Strategies in the Principia Philosophiae.John A. Schuster & Judit Brody - 2013 - Annals of Science 70 (1):1-45.
    Summary Descartes' two treatises of corpuscular-mechanical natural philosophy—Le Monde (1633) and the Principia philosophiae (1644/1647)—differ in many respects. Some historians of science have studied their significantly different theories of matter and elements. Others have routinely noted that the Principia cites much evidence regarding magnetism, sunspots, novae and variable stars which is absent from Le Monde. We argue that far from being unrelated or even opposed intellectual practices inside the Principles, Descartes' moves in matter and element theory and his (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  29.  16
    Descartes’s changing mind.Peter Machamer & J. E. McGuire - 2006 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 37 (3):398-419.
    Descartes is always concerned about knowledge. However, the Galileo affair in 1633, the reactions to his Discourse on method, and later his need to reply to objections to his Meditations provoked crises in Descartes’s intellectual development the import of which has not been sufficiently recognized. These events are the major reasons why Descartes’s philosophical position concerning how we know and what we may know is radically different at the end of his life from what it was (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  30. Descartes' Model of Mind.Ray Scott Percival - 2015 - In Robin L. Cautin & Scott O. Lilienfeld (eds.), The Encyclopedia of Clinical Psychology. Wiley-Blackwell.
    Rene Descartes (1596 – 1650) is considered the founder of modern philosophy. Profoundly influenced by the new physics and astronomy of Kepler and Galileo, Descartes was a scientist and mathematician whose most long-lasting contributions in science were the invention of Cartesian coordinates, the application of algebra to geometry, and the discovery of the law of refraction, what we now call Snell’s law.His most important books on philosophy were The discourse on method(1637) and The meditations(1642). Descartes’ writings (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  4
    Descartes.Harry M. Bracken - 2002 - ONEWorld Publications.
    Outlining the major ideas and achievements of the great French thinker Reneescartes, this is an introductory guide to a man whose ground-breakingheories have been rocking the status quo for over three centuries.;From hisirth into the brave new scientific world of Copernicus and Galileo to hisemise and the unusual fate of his body, this book first presents a soundntroduction to the context of Descartes's life and thought. Harry M. Brackenhen draws on the words of Descartes himself to introduce (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  32. Rene´ Descartes.J. Sutton - 2001 - In Encyclopedia of the life sciences. Macmillan. pp. 383-386.
    Descartes was born in La Haye (now Descartes) in Touraine and educated at the Jesuit college of La Fleche` in Anjou. Descartes’modern reputation as a rationalistic armchair philosopher, whose mind–body dualism is the source of damaging divisions between psychology and the life sciences, is almost entirely undeserved. Some 90% of his surviving correspondence is on mathematics and scientific matters, from acoustics and hydrostatics to chemistry and the practical problems of constructing scientific instruments. Descartes was just as (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Descartes' "Dioptrics" and Descartes' Optics.Jeffrey K. McDonough - 2016 - In Lawrence Nolan (ed.), The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon. New York, USA: Cambridge University Press.
    The Dioptrique, often translated as the Optics or, more literally, as the Dioptrics is one of Descartes’ earliest works. Likely begun in the mid to late 1620’s, Descartes refers to it by name in a letter to Mersenne of 25 November 1630 III, 29). Its subject matter partially overlaps with Descartes’ more foundational project The World or Treatise on Light in which he offers a general mechanistic account of the universe including the formation, transmission, and reception of (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  5
    Descartes on Mathematics, Method and Motion: On the Role of Cartesian Physics in the Scientific Revolution.Ladislav Kvasz - 2024 - Springer Nature Switzerland.
    This book argues that Descartes’ physics was a milestone on the road to modern mathematical physics. After Newton introduced a completely different approach to mathematical description of motion, Descartes’ physics became obsolete and even difficult to comprehend. This text follows the language of Descartes and the means of which motion can be described. It argues that Descartes achieved almost everything that later Newton was able to do—to describe the motion of interacting bodies- by different (i.e. algebraic) (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  25
    Descartes and the Notion of a Criterion of External Reality: May Brodbeck.May Brodbeck - 1971 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures 5:1-14.
    Descartes's greatest glory was to be the first to articulate, and systematically to defend, the new scientific ideal of explanation in terms of lawfulness. For the realm of matter, lawful connections replaced anthropomorphic volitions as the model of rational explanation. Descartes's use of explanation in terms of lawfulness, inspired by Galileo's beginnings in this enterprise, was vindicated by Newton's subsequent achievement. Replacement of anthropomorphic agency, by causal mechanism, as the explanatory model, was undoubtedly the most profound of (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36. Descartes on Nothing in Particular.Eric Palmer - 1999 - In Rocco J. Gennaro & Charles Huenemann (eds.), New essays on the rationalists. New York: Oxford University Press.
    This essay examines Descartes's conception of vacuum in the World and the Principles, relating that conception specifically to the natural philosophy of Galileo and Albert of Saxony. It is argued that understanding the historical context helps to explain Descartes's different attitudes toward the impossibility of vacua.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  39
    Spinoza, Boyle, Galileo: Was Spinoza a Strict Mechanical Philosopher?Filip Buyse - 2013 - Intellectual History Review 23 (1):45-64.
  38.  33
    Descartes and the Last Scholastics (review).Blake D. Dutton - 2000 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 38 (2):275-277.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Descartes and the Last ScholasticsBlake D. DuttonRoger Ariew. Descartes and the Last Scholastics. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1999. Pp. xi + 230. Cloth, $42.50.The attempt to understand Descartes vis-à-vis the scholastic tradition dates back to the studies of Etienne Gilson early in this century. Though Descartes saw himself as a revolutionary who would overthrow the Aristotelianism entrenched in the universities, Gilson was able to (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39. Descartes and the Principles of Scientific Knowledge (in Czech).Daniel Spelda - 2005 - Filosoficky Casopis 53 (2):243-265.
    This article attempts to explain Descartes's understanding of the possibilities, objectives, and functions of scientific knowledge in the Principia philosophiae. In the standard interpretation the scientific system in the Principia is constructed deductively, but a deeper examination shows that Descartes's understanding very much resembles the voluntarism of late medieval nominalist theology. He emphasizes the contingency of the created world, which at every moment is dependent on the power of God that sustains it. Descartes further believes that the (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  25
    René Descartes: Regulae ad directionem ingenii.Gregor Sebba - 1968 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 6 (1):82-83.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:82 HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY phy) than the aspects considered in the earlier chapters. The attempts of these men to formulate theories of the cosmos and of natural phenomena, to take the place of Aristotle's natural philosophy, are described as honest and original speculative endeavors, with a few features which can be construed as anticipations of seventeenth-century scientific philosophy, but basically lacking the soundness of method and evidence that could (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  56
    Natural or violent motion? Galileo's conjectures on the fall of heavy bodies.Roberto de Andrade Martins - 1998 - Dialoghi €“ Rivista di Studi Italici 2:45-67.
    According to Aristotelian physics, there was a fundamental distinction between natural and violent motion. When the cause of the motion was internal to the moving body, that motion was regarded as natural. Violent motion was supposed to have an external efficient cause. It should stop as soon as this external cause ceased its action. The fall of a body was believed to have an internal cause – the very nature of the heavy body – but the motion of a projectile (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  14
    Wallace on Galileo's Sources.Maurice A. Finocchiaro - 1985 - Review of Metaphysics 39 (2):335 - 344.
    PHILOSOPHERS have traditionally appreciated the relevance of Galileo in a number of ways. First, since his scientific contributions made him the "father of modern science," or at least one of its founders, philosophers like Husserl, Ortega y Gasset, and Burtt have studied his work to determine its epistemological implications and metaphysical foundations; this kind of approach is pursued more or less systematically by professional philosophers of science, for whom Galileo's work has become a standard test case for their (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  93
    Descartes Our Contemporary. [REVIEW]James Edwin Mahon - 1999 - The European Legacy 4 (4):98-101.
    In this review of two books, Descartes: An Intellectual Biography, by Stephen Gaukroger, and Descartes and his Contemporaries: Meditations, Objections, and Replies, edited by Roger Ariew and Marjorie Grene, I consider arguments about the motivation of Descartes for writing the Meditations on First Philosophy. According to Gaukroger, Descartes wrote the Meditations simply to legitimate his natural philosophy, which he had already worked out, for an audience of theologians and Scholastic philosophers, whom he feared would condemn it (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  6
    Descartes' Proof of the Existence of Matter.Desmond M. Clarke - 2006 - In Stephen Gaukroger (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Descartes' Meditations. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 160–178.
    This chapter contains section titled: Matter in the World Extension as a Property of Matter “Body” in the Meditations Body as Non‐Mind Basic Concepts A Proof of the Existence of Bodies Cartesian Limitations.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  19
    De Copernic à Descartes : l’Empyrée, la parallaxe stellaire et le mouvement de la Terre.Édouard Mehl - 2015 - Revue des Sciences Philosophiques Et Théologiques 99 (2):239-265.
    La révolution copernicienne a des conséquences cosmologiques sur lesquelles Copernic a été peu disert, et dont il faut attendre Giordano Bruno ou Descartes pour mesurer l’exacte portée. L’aspect le plus spectaculaire de cette révolution post-copernicienne est bien sûr la suppression de la sphère des étoiles fixes. L’article examine cette question sous deux aspects : (i) les conséquences problématiques de l’immobilisation copernicienne de la sphère des fixes par rapport à la fiction théologique d’un ciel empyrée, et (ii) la (vaine) recherche (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  77
    Phenomenology and Scientific Realism: Husserl's Critique of Galileo.Gail Soffer - 1990 - Review of Metaphysics 44 (1):67 - 94.
    ACCORDING TO HUSSERL, THE REVOLUTION brought about by the new mathematical science of the seventeenth century was primarily an ontological one: a shift in the conception of the real. That Husserl opposes the new Galilean-Cartesian ontology is clear. This much is evident from the potent rhetoric of the Crisis declaiming Galileo as an "entdeckender und verdeckender Genius", forgetful of the lifeworld, failing to grasp what the mathematical-empirical method he brought to such a degree of perfection actually achieves. Indeed, even (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  47.  52
    Newton and Descartes: Theology and natural philosophy.Andrew Janiak - 2012 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 50 (3):414-435.
    Scholars have long recognized that Newton regarded Descartes as his principal philosophical interlocutor when composing the first edition of Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica in 1687. The arguments in the Scholium on space and time, for instance, can profitably be interpreted as focusing on the conception of space and motion in part two of Descartes's Principles of Philosophy (1644). What is less well known, however, is that this Cartesian conception, along with Descartes's attempt to avoid Galileo's fate (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  48.  21
    Infinite Degrees of Speed Marin Mersenne and the Debate Over Galileo's Law of Free Fall.Carla Rita Palmerino - 1999 - Early Science and Medicine 4 (4):269-328.
    This article analyzes the evolution of Mersenne's views concerning the validity of Galileo's theory of acceleration. After publishing, in 1634, a treatise designed to present empirical evidence in favor of Galileo's odd-number law, Mersenne developed over the years the feeling that only the elaboration of a physical proof could provide sufficient confirmation of its validity. In the present article, I try to show that at the center of Mersenne's worries stood Galileo's assumption that a falling body had (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  49.  5
    René Descartes: Regulae ad directionem ingenii (review). [REVIEW]Gregor Sebba - 1968 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 6 (1):82-83.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:82 HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY phy) than the aspects considered in the earlier chapters. The attempts of these men to formulate theories of the cosmos and of natural phenomena, to take the place of Aristotle's natural philosophy, are described as honest and original speculative endeavors, with a few features which can be construed as anticipations of seventeenth-century scientific philosophy, but basically lacking the soundness of method and evidence that could (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  14
    A "new" Descartes edition?Gregor Sebba - 1963 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 1 (2):231-236.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:NOTES AND DISCUSSIONS 231 that neither Borro nor any of the Aristotelian writers on method mentioned by Randall seems to me to have influenced Galileo. If I were to begin looking for Aristotelian influences, I should think it much more promising to examine carefully those discussions on the relation between "most powerful demonstrations" and the proofs of mathematics carried on at Padua and elsewhere, to which I have (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 989