Results for ' good reasons to believe in God'

999 found
Order:
  1. Is it reasonable to believe in God?Linda Zagzebski -
    When philosophers talk about whether it is reasonable to believe in God, they might take the high intellectual approach of presenting one or more of the traditional arguments for God’s existence, all of which have contemporary forms. Or they might take the opposite approach made popular by some Calvinist philosophers such as Alvin Plantinga who argue that a person can be reasonable in believing something without reasons to support it, and belief in God is like that. There are (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  2. The Wager Renewed: Believing in God is Good for You. [REVIEW]Justin P. McBrayer - 2014 - Science, Religion and Culture 1 (3):130.
    Not all of our reasons for belief are epistemic in nature. Some of our reasons for belief are prudential in the sense that believing a certain thing advances our personal goals. When it comes to belief in God, the most famous formulation of a prudential reason for belief is Pascal’s Wager. And although Pascal’s Wager fails, its failure is instructive. Pascal’s Wager fails because it relies on unjustified assumptions about what happens in the afterlife to those who (...) in God verses those who do not. A renewed wager can avoid this difficulty by relying solely on well-documented differences between those who believe in God verses those who do not. Social scientists have put together an impressive set of data that shows that theists do better in terms of happiness, health, longevity, inter- personal relationships, and charitable giving. Hence, most people have a strong reason to believe in God regardless of the evidence. (shrink)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  3.  30
    Why I Believe.Why I. Believe In God - 1986 - In John Perry, Michael Bratman & John Martin Fischer (eds.), Introduction to philosophy: classical and contemporary readings. New York: Oxford University Press.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  51
    Is it reasonable to believe in God?J. Houston (ed.) - 1984 - Edinburgh: Handsel Press.
  5.  16
    Is it Reasonable to Believe in God?A. Millar - 1986 - Philosophical Quarterly 36 (142):103-105.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  8
    J. Houston , "Is it Reasonable to Believe in God?". [REVIEW]A. Millar - 1986 - Philosophical Quarterly 36 (42):103.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  7
    Reasons for Believing in God.David M. Holley - 2010 - In Meaning and Mystery. Oxford, UK: Wiley‐Blackwell. pp. 51–68.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Theoretical and Practical Points of View Life‐Orienting Stories Stories About God Reflecting on a Theistic Story Attitudes and the Discernment of Meaning Priority of the Story Notes.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  30
    Retroductive Analogy: How to and How Not to Make Claims of Good Reasons to Believe in Evolutionary and Anti-Evolutionary Hypotheses. [REVIEW]Chuck Ward & Steven Gimbel - 2010 - Argumentation 24 (1):71-84.
    This paper describes an argumentative fallacy we call ‘Retroductive Analogy.’ It occurs when the ability of a favored hypothesis to explain some phenomena, together with the fact that hypotheses of a similar sort are well supported, is taken to be sufficient evidence to accept the hypothesis. This fallacy derives from the retroductive or abductive form of reasoning described by Charles Sanders Peirce. According to Peirce’s account, retroduction can provide good reasons to pursue a hypothesis but does not, by (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  28
    Is Coming to Believe in God Reasonable or Unreasonable?R. T. Herbert - 1991 - Faith and Philosophy 8 (1):36-50.
  10.  78
    The 'will to believe' in science and religion.William J. Gavin - 1984 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 15 (3):139 - 148.
    “The Will to Believe” defines the religious question as forced, living and momentous, but even in this article James asserts that more objective factors are involved. The competing religious hypotheses must both be equally coherent and correspond to experimental data to an equal degree. Otherwise the option is not a live one. “If I say to you ‘Be a theosophist or be a Mohammedan’, it is probably a dead option, because for you neither hypothesis is likely to be alive.” (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Grounds for belief in God aside, does evil make atheism more reasonable than theism?Daniel Howard-Snyder & Michael Bergmann - 2003 - In Michael Peterson & Raymond Van Arrogan (eds.), Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Religion. Blackwell. pp. 140--55.
    Preprinted in God and the Problem of Evil(Blackwell 2001), ed. William Rowe. Many people deny that evil makes belief in atheism more reasonable for us than belief in theism. After all, they say, the grounds for belief in God are much better than the evidence for atheism, including the evidence provided by evil. We will not join their ranks on this occasion. Rather, we wish to consider the proposition that, setting aside grounds for belief in God and relying only on (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12.  44
    Is It Natural to Believe In God?Mark R. Talbot - 1989 - Faith and Philosophy 6 (2):155-171.
    Believing that traditional Christian theism implies there is something epistemically wrong with religious unbelief, I examine John Calvin’s claim that everybody would believe in God if it weren’t for sin. I show why this claim ought to be more common than it is; develop it in terms of our naturally having certain reliable epistemic sets; utilize that development to specify exactly what is wrong with unbelief; and then argue that even unbelievers have some reason to think it is true.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  13. Is the fact that other people believe in God a reason to believe? Remarks on the consensus gentium argument.Marek Dobrzeniecki - 2018 - European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 10 (3):133-153.
    According to The Consensus Gentium Argument from the premise: “Everyone believes that God exists” one can conclude that God does exist. In my paper I analyze two ways of defending the claim that somebody’s belief in God is a prima facie reason to believe. Kelly takes the fact of the commonness of the belief in God as a datum to explain and argues that the best explanation has to indicate the truthfulness of the theistic belief. Trinkaus Zagzebski grounds her (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  14.  4
    Believing in God: reason and religious belief.Patrick McGrath - 1995 - Dublin, Ireland: Wolfhound Press.
    Subjects the claims of religious faith to the scrutiny of reason, Examining: Faith, Reason, Authority, Infallibility, Divorce, the ontological argument, Miracles, and theodicy. Includes two of the 'articles prejudicial to ecclesiastical authority' th.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  1
    Good God: the one we want to believe in but are afraid to embrace.Lucas Miles - 2016 - Franklin, TN: Worthy Publishing.
    If we are honest, at some point we all struggle with the question, 'Why does God allow pain, suffering, and evil?'.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  10
    God Is Great, God Is Good: Why Believing in God Is Reasonable and Responsible; Contending With Christianity’s Critics: Answering New Atheists & Other Objectors.Tawa J. Anderson - 2010 - Philosophia Christi 12 (2):493-497.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  53
    I Believe in God the Father, Almighty.Kelly James Clark - 1995 - International Philosophical Quarterly 35 (1):59-69.
    The theist affirms God's paternal care and his unsurpassable ability. If God is Father, he is obliged to prevent harms in a manner similar to earthly fathers; but he has not. This essay refutes the claim that God has obligations closely analogous to those of earthly parents. The essay is a conceptual analysis of what the father/ child relationship entails with respect to moral obligations and permissions. The dissimilarities between the divine and human parent create differences in obligation so great (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  18. Reasons to Believe - Theoretical Arguments.Marcus Hunt - 2020 - In Beau Branson, Hans Van Eyghen, Marcus Hunt, Tim Knepper, Robert Sloan Lee & Steven Steyl (eds.), Introduction to Philosophy: Philosophy of Religion. Rebus Community Press. pp. 22-33.
    A summary of common arguments for belief in God - teleological, cosmological, ontological, and reformed epistemology.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  64
    The ethics of believing in God.T. J. Mawson - 2010 - Think 9 (25):93-100.
    In this paper, I aim to discuss not the issue of whether or not we do in fact have reasons to suppose that there is or that there is not a God, but rather an issue which looks at first glance like it might have a certain methodological priority, the issue of what is the right ‘ethics of belief’ for belief in God: should one believe in God only if one has positive reasons in favour of doing (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. Can an Atheist Believe in God?Andrew S. Eshleman - 2005 - Religious Studies 41 (2):183 - 199.
    Some have proposed that it is reasonable for an atheist to pursue a form of life shaped by engagement with theistic religious language and practice, once language and belief in God are interpreted in the appropriate non-realist manner. My aim is to defend this proposal in the face of several objections that have been raised against it. First, I engage in some conceptual spadework to distinguish more clearly some varieties of religious non-realism. Then, in response to two central objections, I (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  21.  7
    God, evil, and design: an introduction to the philosophical issues.David O'Connor - 2008 - Oxford: Blackwell.
    Although vast and complex, the universe is orderly in many ways, and conditions at its beginning were right for the eventual evolution of life on this planet. But with life there is death, and with sentient life there is great pain and suffering, often with no apparent justification or purpose. Taking these things together, is it reasonable to conclude that the universe was brought about by God? Moreover, does the magnitude of seemingly pointless suffering square with the idea that God (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22. To Believe in Belief.Herman C. D. G. De Regt - 2006 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 37 (1):21-39.
    Take the following version of scientific realism: we have good reason to believe that (some of the) current scientific theories tell us something specific about the underlying, i.e. unobservable, structures of the world, for instance that there are electrons with a certain electric charge, or that there are viruses that cause certain diseases. Popper, the rationalist, would not have adhered to the proposed formulation of scientific realism in terms of the rationality of existential beliefs concerning unobservables. Popper did (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  2
    To Believe in Belief.Herman C. D. G. de Regt - 2006 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 37 (1):21-39.
    SummaryTake the following version of scientific realism: we have good reason to believe that (some of the) current scientific theories tell us something specific about the underlying, i.e. unobservable, structures of the world, for instance that there are electrons with a certain electric charge, or that there are viruses that cause certain diseases. Popper, the rationalist, would not have adhered to the proposed formulation of scientific realism in terms of the rationality of existential beliefs concerning unobservables. Popper did (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  5
    To Believe in Belief.Herman C. De Regt - 2006 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 37 (1):21-39.
    SummaryTake the following version of scientific realism: we have good reason to believe that (some of the) current scientific theories tell us something specific about the underlying, i.e. unobservable, structures of the world, for instance that there are electrons with a certain electric charge, or that there are viruses that cause certain diseases. Popper, the rationalist, would not have adhered to the proposed formulation of scientific realism in terms of the rationality of existential beliefs concerning unobservables. Popper did (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  3
    Can a smart person believe in God?Michael Guillen - 2004 - Nashville: Nelson Books.
    Depth perception -- The difference is in the SQ -- What's the problem? -- The gift that keeps on giving -- Turning a blind eye -- Faith by any other name -- Hope springs eternal -- Can a smart person believe in God? -- What's your SQ? -- Key to the SQ test.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  1
    God Is Great, God Is Good: Why Believing in God Is Reasonable and Responsible; Contending With Christianity’s Critics: Answering New Atheists & Other Objectors. [REVIEW]Tawa J. Anderson - 2010 - Philosophia Christi 12 (2):493-497.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. What to believe about your belief that you're in the good case.Alex Worsnip - 2019 - Oxford Studies in Epistemology 6:206-233.
    Going about our daily lives in an orderly manner requires us, once we are aware of them, to dismiss many metaphysical possibilities. We take it for granted that we are not brains in vats, or living in the Matrix, or in an extended dream. Call these things that we take for granted “anti-skeptical assumptions”. What should a reflective agent who believes these things think of these beliefs? For various reasons, it can seem that we do not have evidence for (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28. Is it Reasonable to Believe that Miracles Occur?Alberto Oya - 2019 - Teorema: International Journal of Philosophy 38 (2):39-50.
    Traditionally, miracles have been defined as supernaturally caused events which are outside the scope of scientific explicability. In this paper I will criticize the argument that, when we lack a scientific explanation for an event but it has an adequate explanation in theistic terms, then the most reasonable conclusion is to claim that the event is a miracle. I will defend that this argument would not work unless we had prior independent evidence for God’s existence. Furthermore, I will argue that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  29. Safety and Knowledge in God.T. J. Mawson - 2014 - European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 6 (2):81--100.
    In recent ”secular’ Epistemology, much attention has been paid to formulating an ”anti-luck’ or ”safety’ condition; it is now widely held that such a condition is an essential part of any satisfactory post-Gettier reflection on the nature of knowledge. In this paper, I explain the safety condition as it has emerged and then explore some implications of and for it arising from considering the God issue. It looks at the outset as if safety might be ”good news’ for a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  80
    A Thomistic Answer to the Evil‐God Challenge.B. Kyle Keltz - 2019 - Heythrop Journal 60 (5):689-698.
    Stephen Law’s evil-god challenge is the argument that since an evil god is just as likely as the God of theism, there is no reason to believe that theism is true over believing there is a god who is omnipotent, omniscient, and omnimalevolent. There have been several attempts to answer the challenge, but recently John Collins has defended the evil-god challenge and also extended the argument past Law’s original formulation. In this article, I defend the classical theism of Thomas (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  31. The Highest Good and Kant's Proof(s) of God's Existence.Courtney Fugate - 2014 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 31 (2).
    This paper explains a way of understanding Kant's proof of God's existence in the Critique of Practical Reason that has hitherto gone unnoticed and argues that this interpretation possesses several advantages over its rivals. By first looking at examples where Kant indicates the role that faith plays in moral life and then reconstructing the proof of the second Critique with this in view, I argue that, for Kant, we must adopt a certain conception of the highest good, and so (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  32. Reason and responsibility: readings in some basic problems of philosophy.Joel Feinberg (ed.) - 1966 - Encino, Calif.: Dickenson Pub. Co..
    Joel Feinberg : In Memoriam. Preface. Part I: INTRODUCTION TO THE NATURE AND VALUE OF PHILOSOPHY. 1. Joel Feinberg: A Logic Lesson. 2. Plato: "Apology." 3. Bertrand Russell: The Value of Philosophy. PART II: REASON AND RELIGIOUS BELIEF. 1. The Existence and Nature of God. 1.1 Anselm of Canterbury: The Ontological Argument, from Proslogion. 1.2 Gaunilo of Marmoutiers: On Behalf of the Fool. 1.3 L. Rowe: The Ontological Argument. 1.4 Saint Thomas Aquinas: The Five Ways, from Summa Theologica. 1.5 Samuel (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  33.  16
    Human Being Believes in God: Unfoundationally?Debamitra Dey - 2016 - Dialogue and Universalism 26 (1):99-105.
    From the dawn of human intelligence to the present era, the question ‘does God really exist?’ has been important for human being. Is there any proof of his existence? Philosophers, scholars, preceptors, monks and even atheists have tried to find the answer in their own ways. Various schools of Indian philosophy have also expressed their views about God’s existence. Some schools of Indian philosophy have accepted the ideas of karma, karmaphala, rebirth etc. They have denied to admit the existence of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  3
    A reasonable belief: why God and faith make sense.William Greenway - 2015 - Louisville, Kentucky: Westminster John Knox Press.
    "Insofar as the essence of this philosophical spirituality is continuous with the essence of Christian spirituality, I am able to specify how... we can be utterly confident that it is wholly reasonable and good to affirm, give thanks for, live, and testify to faith in God."--from the preface While it's clear that a lot of people believe in God, whether they should is a matter of loud debate. Since the Enlightenment, and especially in the last 150 years, a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  44
    Good Reasons for Better Arguments: An Introduction to the Skills and Values of Critical Thinking.Jerome E. Bickenbach & Jacqueline M. Davies - 1996 - Peterborough, CA: Broadview Press.
    This text introduces university students to the philosophical ethos of critical thinking, as well as to the essential skills required to practice it. The authors believe that Critical Thinking should engage students with issues of broader philosophical interest while they develop their skills in reasoning and argumentation. The text is informed throughout by philosophical theory concerning argument and communication—from Aristotle's recognition of the importance of evaluating argument in terms of its purpose to Habermas's developing of the concept of communicative (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  36. God, Horrors, and Our Deepest Good.Bruce Langtry - 2020 - Faith and Philosophy 37 (1):77-95.
    J.L. Schellenberg argues that since God, if God exists, possesses both full knowledge by acquaintance of horrific suffering and also infinite compassion, the occurrence of horrific suffering is metaphysically incompatible with the existence of God. In this paper I begin by raising doubts about Schellenberg’s assumptions about divine knowledge by acquaintance and infinite compassion. I then focus on Schellenberg’s claim that necessarily, if God exists and the deepest good of finite persons is unsurpassably great and can be achieved without (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Hearing God speak? Debunking arguments and everyday religious experiences.Lari Launonen - 2023 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion (2):187-203.
    Against claims that cognitive science of religion undercuts belief in God, many defenders of theistic belief have invoked the Religious Reasons Reply: science cannot undercut belief in God if one has good independent reasons to believe. However, it is unclear whether this response helps salvage the god beliefs of most people. This paper considers four questions: (1) What reasons do Christians have for believing in God? (2) What kinds of beliefs about God can the (...) support? (3) Are the reasons rationalizations? (4) Can cognitive science undercut the reasons? Many Christians invoke everyday religious experiences (EREs)—such as experiences of divine presence, guidance, and communication—as reasons to believe. Unlike another popular reason to believe in God (the appearance of design and beauty in nature), EREs can support beliefs about a relational God who is present to me, who guides my life, and who speaks to me. EREs are not rationalizations since they seem to cause and sustain such beliefs. Nonetheless, EREs like experiences of hearing God speak are problematic reasons to believe. ‘Soft’ voice-hearing experiences are easily undercut. ‘Hard’ experiences of an external, audible voice are probably underpinned by similar cognitive processes as audio-verbal hallucinations. (shrink)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. The Christian God.Richard Swinburne - 1994 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    What is it for there to be a God, and what reason is there for supposing him to conform to the claims of Christian doctrine? In this pivotal volume of his tetralogy, Richard Swinburne builds a rigorous metaphysical system for describing the world, and applies this to assessing the worth of the Christian tenets of the Trinity and the Incarnation. Part I is dedicated to analyzing the categories needed to address accounts of the divine nature--substance, cause, time, and necessity. Part (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   98 citations  
  39.  8
    God, Evil and Design: An Introduction to the Philosophical Issues.David O'Connor - 2008 - Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.
    Although vast and complex, the universe is orderly in many ways, and conditions at its beginning were right for the eventual evolution of life on this planet. But with life there is death, and with sentient life there is great pain and suffering, often with no apparent justification or purpose. Taking these things together, is it reasonable to conclude that the universe was brought about by God? Moreover, does the magnitude of seemingly pointless suffering square with the idea that God (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  5
    God, Evil and Design: An Introduction to the Philosophical Issues.David O'Connor - 2008 - Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.
    Although vast and complex, the universe is orderly in many ways, and conditions at its beginning were right for the eventual evolution of life on this planet. But with life there is death, and with sentient life there is great pain and suffering, often with no apparent justification or purpose. Taking these things together, is it reasonable to conclude that the universe was brought about by God? Moreover, does the magnitude of seemingly pointless suffering square with the idea that God (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  90
    Fundamentality and the Existence of God.Joshua R. Sijuwade - 2021 - Manuscrito 44 (4):93-168.
    In this article, I seek to assess the extent to which Theism, the claim that there is a God, can provide a true fundamental explanation for the existence of certain entities within the layered structure of reality. More precisely, I assume the cogency of Swinburne’s explanatory framework and seek to resituate it within a new philosophical context-that of the field of contemporary metaphysics-which will enable me to develop a true fundamental explanation for the existence of the non-fundamental entities that fill (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  42. A reason to believe in mind-body identity.Robert M. Martin - 1972 - Personalist 53 (1):80-83.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. A Reason to Believe in Mind-Body Identity.Robert M. Martin - 1972 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 53 (1):80.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  10
    An Essay in Aid of a Grammar of Assent.John Henry Newman & Nicholas Lash - 1870 - Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press. Edited by Charles Frederick Harrold.
    This classic of Christian apologetics seeks to persuade the skeptic that there are good reasons to believe in God even though it si impossible to understand the Deity fully. First written over a century ago, the _Grammar of Assent _speaks as powerfully to us today as it did to its first readers. Because of the informal, non-technical character of Newman's work, it still retains its immediacy as an invaluable guide to the nature of religious belief. An introduction (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45. Skeptheism: Is Knowledge of God’s Existence Possible?Moti Mizrahi - 2017 - European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 9 (1):41-64.
    In this paper, I sketch an argument for the view that we cannot know (or have good reasons to believe) that God exists. Some call this view “strong agnosticism” but I prefer the term “skeptheism” in order to clearly distinguish between two distinct epistemic attitudes with respect to the existence of God, namely, agnosticism and skepticism. For the skeptheist, we cannot know (or have good reasons to believe) that God exists, since there can be (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46. An epistemically distant God? A critique of John Hick's response to the problem of divine hiddenness.Nick Trakakis - 2007 - Heythrop Journal 48 (2):214–226.
    God is thought of as hidden in at least two ways. Firstly, God's reasons for permitting evil, particularly instances of horrendous evil, are often thought to be inscrutable or beyond our ken. Secondly, and perhaps more problematically, God's very existence and love or concern for us is often thought to be hidden from us (or, at least, from many of us on many occasions). But if we assume, as seems most plausible, that God's reasons for permitting evil will (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  47. Epistemic instrumentalism and the reason to believe in accord with the evidence.Nathaniel Sharadin - 2018 - Synthese 195 (9):3791-3809.
    Epistemic instrumentalists face a puzzle. In brief, the puzzle is that if the reason there is to believe in accord with the evidence depends, as the instrumentalist says it does, on agents’ idiosyncratic interests, then there is no reason to expect that this reason is universal. Here, I identify and explain two strategies instrumentalists have used to try and solve this puzzle. I then argue that we should find these strategies wanting. Faced with the failure of these strategies, I (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  48.  9
    Can we be good without God?: biology, behavior, and the need to believe.Rob Buckman - 2002 - Amherst, N.Y.: Prometheus Books.
    In this provocative study of the connection between belief and behavior, Buckman reviews the history of religious belief, and explains data from neuroscience experiments that show a physical cause for religious thoughts.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49.  23
    Reason and Religion [review of Erik J. Wielenberg, God and the Reach of Reason: C. S. Lewis, David Hume, and Bertrand Russell ]. [REVIEW]Stefan Andersson - 2013 - Russell: The Journal of Bertrand Russell Studies 33 (1):75-83.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviews 75 REASON AND RELIGION Stefan Andersson [email protected] Erik J.Wielenberg. God and the Reach of Reason: C. S. Lewis, David Hume, and Bertrand Russell. Cambridge and NewYork: Cambridge U. P., 2008. Pp. x, 243.£50.13 (hb); us$30.99 (pb). rik J.Wielenberg is Johnson Family University Professor, Associate Professor of Philosophy and Chair of the Philosophy Department at DePauw University. His interest in and affinity for Bertrand Russell’s views on religion came (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  6
    Why I believe in a personal God: the credibility of faith in a doubting culture.George Carey - 1991 - Wheaton, Ill.: H. Shaw Publishers.
    Is the Universe on our side? "My own investigations over a period of many years have given me a quiet assurance that there is a God who has given us sufficient clues in life, nature, human thought, beauty and art to satisfy the genuine inquirer that he exists, and that he has expressed himself most meaningfully in Jesus Christ. However, you may come to a different conclusion at the end of this book and that is your right as a thinking (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 999