Results for ' KpV'

8 found
Order:
  1.  12
    Was versteht Kant unter einem „übersinnlichen Gebrauche der Kategorien“? Eine Interpretation von KpV, Ak. 5, S. 5.24–6.1. [REVIEW]Heiko Puls - 2016 - In Stephan Zimmermann (ed.), Die „Kategorien der Freiheit“ in Kants Praktischer Philosophie: Historisch-Systematische Beiträge. Boston: De Gruyter. pp. 77-90.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  9
    Zum Nachweis von Kants Fontenelle-Zitat: „Vor einem Vornehmen bücke ich mich […]“.Martin Walter & Jörg Hüttner - 2023 - Kant Studien 114 (2):383-384.
    It is shown that the famous quote from Fontenelle in Kant’s Critique of Practical Reason, “I bow before an eminent man, but my spirit does not bow,” comes from the book On Principles of Morality, written by Abbé Mably. The Fontenelle quote is found in a review of this very book in the Allgemeine Literaturzeitung (No. 21, 1785). This review should further be considered Kant’s source.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. Kant vs. eudaimonism.Allen W. Wood - manuscript
    Kant was among the first[i] to break decisively with the eudaimonistic tradition of classical ethics by declaring that the moral principle is entirely distinct and divergent from the principle of happiness (G 4:393, KpV 5:21-27).[ii] I am going to argue that what is at issue in Kant’s rejection of eudaimonism is not fundamentally any question of ethical value or the priority among values. On the contrary, on these matters Kant shares the views which led classical ethical theory from Socrates onward (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  4.  8
    Sinnvolle Theologie bei Rudolf Carnap.Niko Strobach - 2023 - In Martin Lemke, Konstantin Leschke, Friederike Peters & Matthias Wunsch (eds.), Der Wiener Kreis und sein philosophisches Spektrum: Beiträge zur Kulturphilosophie, Metaphysik, Philosophiegeschichte, Praktischen Philosophie und Ästhetik. Springer Berlin Heidelberg. pp. 107-126.
    In diesem Beitrag soll gezeigt werden, dass, inwiefern und wieso Rudolf Carnap die Möglichkeit sinnvoller Theologie anerkannt hat. Die These ist, kurz gesagt: Es gibt nach Carnap sinnvolle Theologie. Es lohnt sich, das zu zeigen, da oberflächliche Rezeption der Legende Vorschub leistet, nach Carnap sei alle Theologie Unsinn. Kant und Frege hielten sinnvolle Theologie klarerweise für möglich. Kant zweifelte nicht daran, mit dem Satz „Gott ist“ oder „Es ist ein Gott“ (KrV, B 627) sagen zu können, was er für nachweislich (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  8
    Nota sobre el libro Est Deus in nobis. Die Identität von Gott und reiner praktischer Vernunft in Immanuel Kants «Kritik der praktischen Vernunft» de Gerhard Schwarz.Ignacio Falgueras Salinas - 2012 - Contrastes: Revista Internacional de Filosofía 17.
    RESUMENEste trabajo describe y examina críticamente la obra mencionada, cuya tesis final es la infinitud del hombre y su divinización por el Kant maduro. Su mérito consiste en (i) realizar una minu- 1 «Existe Dios en nosotros. La identidad de Dios y la razón pura práctica en la Crítica de la razón práctica de Kant». En lo que sigue abrevio el nombre del autor con las siglas «GS», y el de esta obra con las siglas «TGS». ciosa lectura de los (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  26
    «Kant und die Kategorien der Freiheit». Recenti discussioni in germania.Francesca Fantasia - 2012 - Giornale di Metafisica 1.
    The chapter of Kant’s Critique of Practical Reason entitled “Table of the categories of liberty, in relation to the concepts of good and evil”, to which this year the Bonn conference “Kant und die ‘Kategorien der Freiheit’” was devoted, today still arouses many questions: is the table of the categories of liberty sufficient to cover the whole practical domain, including that of the empirically conditioned? And if this is the case, what is the meaning of the genitive “of liberty”, and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  76
    Self-Determination and the Categories of Freedom in Kant’s Moral Philosophy.Seung-Kee Lee - 2012 - Kant Studien 103 (3):337-350.
    : Kant speaks of our capacity to be “self-determining […] in certain […] laws holding firm a priori”. Here the “laws” refer to the categories of freedom introduced in KpV. The categories of freedom, then, are necessary for self-determination. I first explain how Kant employs the notion of determination in his theoretical philosophy. I then explain how the notion is utilized also in his practical philosophy, particularly in connection to the act of determining the forms of willing that make morality (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  23
    Self-perfection, self-knowledge, and the supererogatory.Katharina Naumann - 2017 - Etica E Politica (1):319-332.
    Supererogation seems to be an important concept of common sense morality. However, assuming the existence of such a category seems to pose a serious problem for Kantian Ethics, given the all-encompassing role of duty. In fact, Kant seems to deny the possibility of such acts when he states in the second critique that “[b]y exhortation to actions as noble, sublime, and magnanimous, minds are attuned to nothing but moral enthusiasm and exaggerated self-conceit; [...] they are led into the delusion that (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark