Results for 'procreative rights'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  7
    Procreative Rights and Population Policy.Arthur J. Dyck - 1973 - The Hastings Center Studies 1 (1):74.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2. Against procreative moral rights.Jake Earl - 2021 - Bioethics 36 (5):569-575.
    Many contemporary ethical debates turn on claims about the nature and extent of our alleged procreative moral rights: moral rights to procreate or not to procreate as we choose. In this article, I argue that there are no procreative moral rights, in that generally we do not have a distinctive moral right to procreate or not to procreate as we choose. However, interference with our procreative choices usually violates our nonprocreative moral rights, such (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  3.  43
    Editorial: Rights and Procreative Liberty.Doris Schroeder - 2007 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 16 (3):325-325.
    edited by Doris Schroeder, welcomes contributions on all areas outlined below. Submitted papers are peer-reviewed. To submit a paper or to discuss suitable topics, please e-mail Doris Schroeder at [email protected].
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Procreative Justice Reconceived: Shifting the Moral Gaze.Emmalon Davis - 2024 - Journal of the American Philosophical Association (First View):1-23.
    This paper reconsiders Tommie Shelby's (2016) analysis of procreation in poor black communities. I identify three conceptual frames within which Shelby situates his analysis—feminization, choice-as-control, and moralization. I argue that these frames should be rejected on conceptual, empirical, and moral grounds. As I show, this framing engenders a flawed understanding of poor black women's procreative lives. I propose an alternative framework for reconceiving the relationship between poverty and procreative justice, one oriented around reproductive flourishing instead of reproductive responsibility. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5.  11
    Procreative loss without pregnancy loss: the limitations of fetal-centric conceptions of pregnancy.Hannah Carpenter, Georgia Loutrianakis, Peyton Baker, Tiffany Bystra & Lisa Campo-Engelstein - 2024 - Journal of Medical Ethics 50 (5):310-311.
    In their article, Romanis and Adkins delineate pregnancy loss and procreative loss to show that the former is possible without the latter, as in the case of artificial amnion and placenta technology.1 Here, we are interested in examining the reverse—procreative loss without pregnancy loss—to further tease apart these two types of loss. We discuss two cases: being forced to continue a pregnancy despite fetal demise due to abortion restrictions and choosing to selectively reduce a multifetal pregnancy. Our analysis (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6.  87
    Procreative Liberty, Enhancement and Commodification in the Human Cloning Debate.Sandra Shapshay - 2012 - Health Care Analysis 20 (4):356-366.
    The aim of this paper is to scrutinize a contemporary standoff in the American debate over the moral permissibility of human reproductive cloning in its prospective use as a eugenic enhancement technology. I shall argue that there is some significant and under-appreciated common ground between the defenders and opponents of human cloning. Champions of the moral and legal permissibility of cloning support the technology based on the right to procreative liberty provided it were to become as safe as in (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Procreative reasons-relevance: On the moral significance of why we have children.Mianna Lotz - 2008 - Bioethics 23 (5):291-299.
    Advances in reproductive technologies – in particular in genetic screening and selection – have occasioned renewed interest in the moral justifiability of the reasons that motivate the decision to have a child. The capacity to select for desired blood and tissue compatibilities has led to the much discussed 'saviour sibling' cases in which parents seek to 'have one child to save another'. Heightened interest in procreative reasons is to be welcomed, since it prompts a more general philosophical interrogation of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  8.  97
    Individual procreative responsibility and the non-identity problem.Eduardo Rivera-lópez - 2009 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 90 (3):336-363.
    The question I address in this paper is whether and under what conditions it is morally right to bring a person into existence. I defend the commonsensical thesis that, other things being equal, it is morally wrong to create a person who will be below some threshold of quality of life, even if the life of this potential person, once created, will nevertheless be worth living. However commonsensical this view might seem, it has shown to be problematic because of the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  9.  39
    Procreative liberty, biological connections, and motherhood.Margaret Olivia Little - 1996 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 6 (4):392-396.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Procreative Liberty, Biological Connections, and MotherhoodMargaret Olivia Little (bio)Given the complex and dramatic array of issues currently facing us in reproductive ethics, bioethicists working on the topic might be forgiven feelings of trepidation when they cast their minds toward the next century. Currently, technologies such as artificial insemination by donor (AID), once the source of intense controversy, are used on a routine basis; mainstream newspapers carry advertisements offering (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10. A Critical Take on Procreative Justice.Joona Räsänen, Andreas Bengtson, Hugo Cossette-Lefebvre & Kasper Lippert-Rasmussen - 2024 - Bioethics 38 (4):367-374.
    Herjeet Kaur Marway recently proposed the Principle of Procreative Justice, which says that reproducers have a strong moral obligation to avoid completing race and colour injustices through their selection choices. In this article, we analyze this principle and argue, appealing to a series of counterexamples, that some of the implications of Marway's Principle of Procreative Justice are difficult to accept. This casts doubt on whether the principle should be adopted. Also, we show that there are some more principled (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Procreative Justice: A Contractualist Approach.Rivka M. Weinberg - 2001 - Dissertation, University of Michigan
    My dissertation investigates the requirements of procreative justice. The procreative justice problem is that parents' interest in procreation conflicts with children's interest in optimal birth conditions. Intergenerational reciprocity is the principle that adjudicates this conflict: reciprocity dictates that children demand no more of their parents' procreative practices than they themselves are willing to abide by as adults and dig parents only procreate in accordance with principles dig they would have wanted their own parents to have followed. I (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. Genetic Affinity and the Right to ‘Three-parent IVF’.G. Owen Schaefer & Markus Labude - 2017 - Journal of Assisted Reproduction and Genetics 34 (12):1577-1580.
    With the recent report of a live birth after use of Mitochondrial replacement therapy, sometimes called ‘Three-parent IVF’, the clinical application of the technique is fast becoming a reality. While the United Kingdom allows the procedure under regulatory scrutiny, it remains effectively outlawed in many other countries. We argue that such prohibitions may violate individuals’ procreative rights, grounded in individuals’ interest in genetic affinity. The interest in genetic affinity was recently endorsed by Singapore’s highest court, reflecting an emphasis (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  13.  19
    Rule‐consequentialism, procreative freedom, and future generations.Julia Mosquera - 2022 - Ratio 35 (4):333-343.
    In this paper I analyse how procreative freedom poses a challenge for rule-consequentialism. First, I reconstruct the rule-consequentialist case for procreative freedom. Second, I argue that population scenarios resulting from very low fertility pose a problem for rule-consequentialism since such scenarios cannot secure population growth or even avoid human extinction in the long run. Third, I argue that population scenarios resulting from excessive procreation also pose a problem for rule-consequentialism since they are incompatible with the promotion of optimific (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  32
    “You Got Me Into This…”: Procreative Responsibility and Its Implications for Suicide and Euthanasia.Rivka Weinberg - 2015 - In Michael Cholbi & Jukka Varelius (eds.), New Directions in the Ethics of Assisted Suicide and Euthanasia. Cham: Springer Verlag. pp. 167-180.
    This paper investigates connections between procreative ethics and the ethics of suicide and euthanasia. While there are good reasons for distinguishing between lives worth starting and lives worth continuing, I argue that those reasons provide no reason for denying that there is a relationship between procreative and end of life ethics. Regarding euthanasia/assisted suicide, we might think it too demanding to ask parents to help euthanize their terminally ill, suffering child, but had the parents not procreated, thereby exposing (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  30
    Exploiting infertility vs. Natural procreative medicine.Kimberley Pfeiffer - 2012 - Bioethics Research Notes 24 (2):28.
    Pfeiffer, Kimberley We've heard it happening more than once. A couple uses IVF to fall pregnant then later down the track they conceive naturally. Confusing, right? Aren't they supposed to be infertile? Isn't that why people request this invasive and expensive procedure in the first place? Well, a recent study shows that more than 40% of women aged between 28 and 36 years that report having a history of infertility achieved subsequent births without using any form of reproductive assistance1. Which (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  33
    Reproductive Rights without Resources or Recourse.Kimberly Mutcherson - 2017 - Hastings Center Report 47 (s3):S12-S18.
    The U.S. Supreme Court declared procreation to be a fundamental right in the early twentieth century in a case involving Oklahoma's Habitual Criminal Sterilization Act, an act that permitted unconsented sterilization of individuals convicted of certain crimes. The right that the Court articulated in that case is a negative right: it requires that the government not place unjustified roadblocks in the way of people seeking to procreate, but it does not require the government to take positive steps to help people (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  17. Sex selection and the procreative liberty framework.I. Melo-Martín - 2013 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 23 (1):1-18.
  18.  23
    Which “New Eugenics”? Expanding Access to Art, Respecting Procreative Liberty, and Protecting the Moral Equality of All Persons in an Era of Neoliberal Choice.Karey Harwood - 2020 - International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics 13 (2):148-173.
    In The New Eugenics: Selective Breeding in an Era of Reproductive Technologies, Judith Daar advocates for increased access to assisted reproductive technologies and minimizes concerns about the potential “eugenic logic” of some procreative choices. Although Daar’s goal of expanded access is laudable, her argument suggests an unresolved tension between the moral equality of persons and individual reproductive freedom. Exploring that tension, this paper argues that efforts to expand access to ART must still grapple with the “eugenic mentality” of quality (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19.  70
    Rights, Equality and Procreation.Paula Casal & Andrew Williams - 1995 - Analyse & Kritik 17 (1):93-116.
    Individual decisions about how to exercise the legal right to procreative liberty may generate either positive or negative externalities. From within a resource egalitarian perspective, such as that of Ronald Dworkin, it can be argued that procreative justice is asymmetric in the following respect. Justice need not require that parents be subsidised if they produce a public good, yet its ideal achievement may require their activities be taxed if they threaten to produce a public bad.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  20. Procreation, Parenthood, and Educational Rights: Ethical and Philosophical Issues.Jaime Ahlberg & Michael Cholbi (eds.) - 2016 - Routledge.
    _Procreation, Parenthood, and Educational Rights_ explores important issues at the nexus of two burgeoning areas within moral and social philosophy: procreative ethics and parental rights. Surprisingly, there has been comparatively little scholarly engagement across these subdisciplinary boundaries, despite the fact that parental rights are paradigmatically ascribed to individuals responsible for procreating particular children. This collection thus aims to bring expert practitioners from these literatures into fruitful and innovative dialogue around questions at the intersection of procreation and parenthood. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  49
    Response to Orr and Siegler--collective intentionality and procreative desires: the permissible view on consent to posthumous conception.M. Parker - 2004 - Journal of Medical Ethics 30 (4):389-392.
    Orr and Siegler have recently defended a restrictive view concerning posthumous sperm retrieval and conception, which would limit insemination to those cases where the deceased man has provided explicit consent for such a procedure. The restrictive view dominates current law and practice. A permissible view, in contrast, would allow insemination and conception in all but those cases where the posthumous procedure has been explicitly refused, or where there is no reasonable evidence that the deceased person desired children. I describe a (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  22.  13
    Universal Procreation Rights and Future Generations.Tim Campbell, Martin Kolk & Julia Mosquera - forthcoming - Journal of Applied Philosophy.
    It is often acknowledged that public policies can constrain people's procreative opportunities, in some cases even infringing their procreative rights. However, a topic that is not often discussed is how the procreative choices of one generation can affect the procreative opportunities of later generations. In this article, we argue that the demographic fact that childbearing above the replacement fertility level is eventually unsustainable supports two constraints on universal procreation rights: a compossibility constraint and an (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23.  42
    Our right to in vitro fertilisation--its scope and limits.T. Tannsjo - 2008 - Journal of Medical Ethics 34 (11):802-806.
    There exists a derived negative right to procreative freedom, including a right to in vitro fertilisation (IVF) and to the exercise of selective techniques such as preimplantation genetic diagnosis. This is an extensive freedom, including not only the right to the exercise of a responsible parenthood, but also, in rare cases, to wrong decisions. It includes also a right for less than perfect parents to the use of IVF, and for IVF doctors to assist them, if they want and (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  24. How Procreation Generates Parental Rights and Obligations.Michael Cholbi - 2017 - In Michael Cholbi & Jaime Ahlberg (eds.), Procreation, Parenthood, and Educational Rights: Ethical and Philosophical Issues. Routledge.
    Philosophical defenses of parents’ rights typically appeal to the interests of parents, the interests of children, or some combination of these. Here I propose that at least in the case of biological, non-adoptive parents, these rights have a different normative basis: namely, these rights should be accorded to biological parents because of the compensatory duties such parents owe their children by virtue of having brought them into existence. Inspried by Seana Shiffrin, I argue that procreation inevitably encumbers (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  25.  19
    A child’s right to a father.C. L. Ten - 2000 - Monash Bioethics Review 19 (4):33-37.
    Recently a child’s right to a father was invoked to justify the prevention of single women from obtaining access to IVF. This article explores the conceptual and normative issues about the nature of the right and its conflict with a woman’s right to procreative autonomy. The discussion relates the conceptual issues to those raised in the context of ‘wrongful life’ tort cases. It concludes that the right to be born with a father, although conceptually sound, does not justify the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26.  67
    Storks, cabbage patches, and the right to procreate.Yvette E. Pearson - 2007 - Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 4 (2):105-115.
    In this paper I examine the prevailing assumption that there is a right to procreate and question whether there exists a coherent notion of such a right. I argue that we should question any and all procreative activities, not just alternative procreative means and contexts. I suggest that clinging to the assumption of a right to procreate prevents serious scrutiny of reproductive behavior and that, instead of continuing to embrace this assumption, attempts should be made to provide a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  27.  10
    A Defense of Dignity: Creating Life, Destroying Life, and Protecting the Rights of Conscience.Christopher Robert Kaczor - 2013 - Notre Dame, Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press.
    Questions about the dignity of the human person give rise to many of the most central and hotly disputed topics in bioethics. In _A Defense of Dignity: Creating Life, Destroying Life, and Protecting the Rights of Conscience_, Christopher Kaczor investigates whether each human being has intrinsic dignity and whether the very concept of "dignity" has a useful place in contemporary ethical debates. Kaczor explores a broad range of issues addressed in contemporary bioethics, including whether there is a duty of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28. Philippa R. Smith.Cicero Get it Right - 1995 - In Jonathan Powell (ed.), Cicero the philosopher: twelve papers. New York: Clarendon Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  83
    Five Reasons why Margaret Somerville is Wrong about Same-Sex Marriage and the Rights of Children.Scott Woodcock - 2009 - Dialogue 48 (4):867.
    ABSTRACT: In written work and a lecture at the 2008 Congress of the Humanities and Social Sciences that was co-sponsored by the Canadian Philosophical Association, Margaret Somerville has claimed that allowing same-sex marriage is unethical because doing so violates the inherently procreative function of marriage and thereby undermines the rights and duties that exist between children and their biological parents. In my paper, I offer five reasons for thinking that Somerville’s argument for this conclusion is unpersuasive. In each (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30. Declaration on anthropology and human rights (1999).Committe for Human Rights & American Anthropological Association - 2009 - In Mark Goodale (ed.), Human rights: an anthropological reader. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31. Roland N. Mckean.Some Changing Property Rights - forthcoming - Contemporary Issues in Business Ethics.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. The Liberal Paradox.Some Interpretations When Rights - 1996 - Analyse & Kritik 18:38-53.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. One Child: Do We Have a Right to Have More? by Sarah Conly. [REVIEW]Trevor Hedberg - 2017 - Philosophy East and West 67 (3):934-938.
    Sarah Conly's One Child is a substantive treatment of the extent to which procreative freedom is curtailed by rising global population and the environmental problems to which it contributes. This review provides an overview of the book's content and closes with a few critical remarks. The book is highly recommended for those interested in the intersection between environmental ethics and the ethics of procreation.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. Animal liberation or animal rights?, Peter Singer.Moral Rights - 1987 - The Monist 70 (1).
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Timothy F. Murphy.A. Patient'S. Right To Know - 1994 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 19 (4-6):553-569.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  24
    Agent-Relativity, Reason, and Value, ROBERT M. STEWART.Eric Rights - 1993 - The Monist 76 (2).
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Carlos S. Nino.Liberal Rights - 1989 - Law and Philosophy 8:37-52.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  12
    From Conflict to Confluence of Interest.Intellectual Property Rights - 2010 - In Thomas H. Murray & Josephine Johnston (eds.), Trust and integrity in biomedical research: the case of financial conflicts of interest. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39. John Baden and Richard Stroup.Property Rights - forthcoming - Contemporary Issues in Business Ethics.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. Public ai= I= airs quarterly.Private Property Rights - 2002 - Public Affairs Quarterly 16:231.
  41. Raymond plant.Welfare Rights - 1988 - In J. Donald Moon (ed.), Responsibility, Rights, and Welfare: The Theory of the Welfare State. Westview Press. pp. 55.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  11
    James gs Wilson.Taxonomy of Rights Hohfeld’S. - 2007 - In Richard E. Ashcroft (ed.), Principles of Health Care Ethics. Wiley.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. The nature and value of the.Moral Right To Privacy - 2002 - Public Affairs Quarterly 16 (4):329.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. Katharina Nieswandt, Concordia University. Authority & Interest in the Theory Of Right - 2019 - In Toh Kevin, Plunkett David & Shapiro Scott (eds.), Dimensions of Normativity: New Essays on Metaethics and Jurisprudence. New York: Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  26
    Right to Private Property.Welfare Rights as Compensation - 2012 - In T. Williamson (ed.), Property-Owning Democracy: Rawls and Beyond. Wiley-Blackwell.
  46.  9
    Just Interpretations: Law Between Ethics and Politics.Michel Rosenfeld & Professor of Human Rights and Director Program on Global and Comparative Constitutional Theory Michel Rosenfeld - 1998 - Univ of California Press.
    "An important contribution to contemporary jurisprudential debate and to legal thought more generally, Just Interpretations is far ahead of currently available work."--Peter Goodrich, author of Oedipus Lex "I was struck repeatedly by the clarity of expression throughout the book. Rosenfeld's description and criticism of the recent work of leading thinkers distinguishes his work within the legal theory genre. Furthermore, his own theory is quite original and provocative."--Aviam Soifer, author of Law and the Company We Keep.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  47. Index to Volume Fifty-Six.Wim De Reu & Right Words Seem Wrong - 2006 - Philosophy East and West 56 (4):709-714.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Index to Volume Fifty-SixArticlesBernier, Bernard, National Communion: Watsuji Tetsurō's Conception of Ethics, Power, and the Japanese Imperial State, 1 : 84-105Between Principle and Situation: Contrasting Styles in the Japanese and Korean Traditions of Moral Culture, Chai-sik Chung, 2 : 253-280Buxton, Nicholas, The Crow and the Coconut: Accident, Coincidence, and Causation in the Yogavāiṣṭha, 3 : 392-408Chan, Sin Yee, The Confucian Notion of Jing (Respect), Sin Yee Chan, 2 : (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. Ville paivansalo.Hobbesian Laws, Lockean Rights & Rawlsian Ideas - 2010 - In Virpi Mäkinen (ed.), The nature of rights: moral and political aspects of rights in late medieval and early modern philosophy. Helsinki: The Philosophical Society of Finland. pp. 225.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. Remedies'.P. Birks & Wrongs Rights - 2000 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 1.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  50. On moral arguments against.A. Legal Right To Unilateral - 2006 - Public Affairs Quarterly 20 (2):115.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 1000