Results for 'noumena'

139 found
Order:
  1.  28
    Fanged Noumena: collected writings 1987-2007.Nick Land - 2012 - New York, NY: Sequence Press. Edited by Robin Mackay & Ray Brassier.
    A dizzying trip through the mind(s) of the provocative and influential thinker Nick Land. During the 1990s British philosopher Nick Land's unique work, variously described as “rabid nihilism,” “mad black deleuzianism,” and “cybergothic,” developed perhaps the only rigorous and culturally-engaged escape route out of the malaise of “continental philosophy” —a route that was implacably blocked by the academy. However, Land's work has continued to exert an influence, both through the British “speculative realist” philosophers who studied with him, and through the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  2.  57
    Noumena and microphysics.Gaston Bachelard & David Reggio - 2005 - Angelaki 10 (2):73 – 78.
    (2005). Noumena and Microphysics1. Angelaki: Vol. 10, continental philosophy and the sciences the french tradition issue editor: andrew aitken, pp. 73-78.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  3.  31
    Phaenomena/Noumena und die Amphibolie der Reflexionsbegriffe.Marcus Willaschek - 1998 - In Phaenomena/Noumena und die Amphibolie der Reflexionsbegriffe. pp. 325-351.
  4.  47
    Noumena’ versus ‘Things in Themselves'.Marialena Karampatsou - 2018 - In Violetta L. Waibel, Margit Ruffing & David Wagner (eds.), Natur und Freiheit. Akten des XII. Internationalen Kant-Kongresses. De Gruyter. pp. 1065-1072.
    I argue against an identification of the terms ‘thing in itself’ and ‘noumenon’ within the context of the Phenomena/Noumena Section in Kant's Critique of Pure Reason: the agnosticism which Kant undeniably expresses with regard to noumena is not to be extended to his attitude towards things in themselves. My reading is neutral with regard to the debate between one-world and two-world interpretations of transcendental idealism.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5.  9
    Kantian Noumena and Peirceian Noumena.Lynn Stephens - 1989 - Proceedings of the Sixth International Kant Congress 2 (2):595-602.
  6.  24
    Everyday Noumena – The Fact and Significance of Ordinary Intelligible Objects.Jennifer Uleman - 2013 - In Stefano Bacin, Alfredo Ferrarin, Claudio La Rocca & Margit Ruffing (eds.), Kant und die Philosophie in weltbürgerlicher Absicht. Akten des XI. Internationalen Kant-Kongresses. Boston: de Gruyter. pp. 799-808.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  59
    Noumena, phenomena, and God.Robert A. Oakes - 1973 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 4 (1):30 - 38.
  8. Things in Themselves, Noumena, and the Transcendental Object.Henri E. Allison - 1978 - Dialectica 32 (1):41-76.
    SummaryThis paper is divided into two parts. The first sketches an interpretation of the thing in itself, the noumenon and the transcendental object which clarifies the connection between these conceptions and shows that each has a “critical” function. This is accomplished by linking them with transcendental reflection. It is shown that such reflection requires the distinction between two ways of considering an object and that “noumenon” and “transcendental object” characterize alternative descriptions of an object considered as it is in itself. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  9.  15
    Kant’s Negative Noumena as Abstracta.Chong-Fuk Lau - 2022 - In Gregory S. Moss (ed.), The Being of Negation in Post-Kantian Philosophy. Springer Verlag. pp. 33-55.
    This paper takes a fresh look at Kant’s transcendental idealism with a new reading of negative noumena as abstract entities. It shows that the three criteria for abstractness, i.e., non-spatiotemporality, causal inefficacy, and non-indiscernibility, are true of Kant’s negative noumena. Phenomena, by contrast, are concrete entities in space and time, which can be understood as spatiotemporally instantiated noumena. Kant’s distinction between noumena in the positive and negative sense will be reinterpreted as a distinction between non-spatiotemporally instantiated (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. "On the Noumena of History": On the Status of Nomads in Deleuze's Thought.Daniel W. Smith - manuscript
    The “Treatise on Nomadology: The War Machine" is one of the most important and innovative chapters in Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari's book, A Thousand Plateaus. It is a highly original text in political philosophy whose implications have yet to be fully mined—or even partially mined, for that matter. This short text analyzes the "noumenal" status that Deleuze assigns to the nomadic war machine, and analyzes the fundamental role that the nomadology plays in Deleuze and Guattari's political philosophy.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  98
    Saving the Noumena.Lawrence Sklar - 1982 - Philosophical Topics 13 (1):89-110.
  12.  39
    Saving the Noumena.Lawrence Sklar - 1982 - Philosophical Topics 13 (1):89-110.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  13. Never Mind the Intuitive Intellect: Applying Kant’s Categories to Noumena.Colin Marshall - 2018 - Kantian Review 23 (1):27-40.
    According to strong metaphysical readings of Kant, Kant believes there are noumenal substances and causes. Proponents of these readings have shown that these readings can be reconciled with Kant’s claims about the limitations of human cognition. An important new challenge to such readings, however, has been proposed by Markus Kohl, focusing on Kant’s occasional statements about the divine or intuitive intellect. According to Kohl, how an intuitive intellect represents is a decisive measure for how noumena are for Kant, but (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  14.  24
    Things in Themselves, Noumena, and the Transcendental Object.Henri E. Allison - 1978 - Dialectica 32 (1):41-76.
    SummaryThis paper is divided into two parts. The first sketches an interpretation of the thing in itself, the noumenon and the transcendental object which clarifies the connection between these conceptions and shows that each has a “critical” function. This is accomplished by linking them with transcendental reflection. It is shown that such reflection requires the distinction between two ways of considering an object and that “noumenon” and “transcendental object” characterize alternative descriptions of an object considered as it is in itself. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  15.  19
    Kant’s Amodalism about Noumena and Freedom.Uygar Abaci - 2021 - In Camilla Serck-Hanssen & Beatrix Himmelmann (eds.), The Court of Reason: Proceedings of the 13th International Kant Congress. De Gruyter. pp. 413-422.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  2
    13 Phaenomena/Noumena und die Amphibolie der Reflexionsbegriffe.Marcus Willaschek - 2024 - In Georg Mohr & Marcus Willaschek (eds.), Immanuel Kant: Kritik der reinen Vernunft. De Gruyter. pp. 259-280.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  8
    Chronicling the Erosion of Noumena.Fabio Gironi - 2010 - Cosmos and History 6 (1):169-175.
  18.  59
    To save the noumena.Clark Glymour - 1976 - Journal of Philosophy 73 (18):635-637.
  19. To save the noumena L nu ®.Clark Glymour - unknown
    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of J STOR’s Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. J STOR’s Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non—commercial use.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  22
    Kant and Heidegger: The Place of Truth and the Shrinking Back of the Noumena.Eben Hensby - 2021 - Philosophia 49 (4):1507-1524.
    There is much debate on how to understand Kant’s transcendental idealism in the context of the Critique of Pure Reason. Heidegger’s Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics offers an innovative reading of Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, but is often overlooked due to the violence it allegedly does in its interpretation. This paper offers a Heideggerian-inspired phenomenological or ontological interpretation of transcendental idealism by drawing on Heidegger’s interpretation of the Critique. First, I draw a connection between the two uses of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21. The Content of Kant's Pure Category of Substance and Its Use on Phenomena and Noumena.James Messina - 2021 - Philosophers' Imprint 21 (29).
    I begin by arguing that, for Kant, the pure category of substance has both a general content that is in play whenever we think of any entity as a substance as well as a more specific content that arises in conjunction with the thought of what Kant calls a positive noumenon. Drawing on this new “Dual Content” account of the pure category of substance, I offer new answers to two contested questions: What is the relation of the pure category to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  22. Robots en Noumena.J. J. M. Sleutels - 2000 - Algemeen Nederlands Tijdschrift voor Wijsbegeerte 92 (1):110-112.
  23.  35
    Bodies in Prolegomena §13: Noumena or Phenomena?Edward Kanterian - unknown
    This article discusses Kant's transcendental idealism in relation to his perplexing use of ‘body’ and related terms in Prolegomena §13. Here Kant admits the existence of bodies external to us, although unknown as what they might be in themselves. It is argued that we need to distinguish between a phenomenal and a noumenal use of ‘body’ to make sense of Kant's argument. The most important recent discussions of this passage, i.e., Prauss, Langton and Bird, are presented and shown to suffer (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  9
    Kant's Conception of the Self: Applying the Dual-Aspect Reading of the Phenomena/Noumena Distinction to the Self.Theodore Di Maria - 1999 - Dissertation, Marquette University
    In his critical philosophy, Kant considers the 'subject' to be the source and ground of the a priori conditions of experience, but says exasperatingly little to elucidate this crucial notion. Kant's express view in the first Critique is that the self, like other objects of experience, can be considered either through the conditions of experience as a phenomenon, or as it is independently of these conditions as a noumenon. According to this view, the 'subject' that serves as the ground of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. Freedom and the Distinction Between Phenomena and Noumena: Is Allison’s View Methodological, Metaphysical, or Equivocal?Kenneth Westphal - 2001 - Journal of Philosophical Research 26:593-622.
    Henry Allison criticizes and rejects naturalism because the idea of freedom is constitutive of rational spontaneity, which alone enables and entitles us to judge or to act rationally, and only transcendental idealism can justify our acting under the idea of freedom. Allison’s critique of naturalism is unclear because his reasons for claiming that free rational spontaneity requires transcendental idealism are inadequate and because his characterization of Kant’s idealism is ambiguous. Recognizing this reinforces the importance of the question of whether only (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  26. Neurological Embodiments of Belief and the Gaps in the Fit of Phenomena to Noumena in Naturalistic Epistemology: A Symposium of Two Decades.Dt Campbell - 1987 - Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 100:165-192.
  27. The refutation of idealism and the distinction between phenomena and noumena.Dina Edmundts - 2010 - In Paul Guyer (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Kant's Critique of Pure Reason. Cambridge University Press.
  28.  21
    A Fregean Reading of Kant’s Distinction between Phenomena and Noumena.Martha I. Gibson - 2009 - History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 12 (1):289-309.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  81
    I. Kant's doctrine of the "things in themselves" and noumena.T. I. Oizerman - 1981 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 41 (3):333-350.
  30.  66
    On Transcending the Limits of Language.Graham Priest - 2023 - In Jens Pier (ed.), Limits of Intelligibility: Issues from Kant and Wittgenstein. Routledge.
    The first half of this article is critical: it develops an interpretation of Kant as trying, and failing, to limit our judgments to phenomena and abstain from making claims about noumena, and an interpretation of Wittgenstein as trying, and failing, to develop a theory of meaning that abstains from attempting to say the unsayable. On the reading offered, both Kant and Wittgenstein find themselves saying things that by their own lights cannot be said: in Kant’s case, claims about (...), and in Wittgenstein’s case, structural claims. While Kant attempts a solution of the problem which also fails, Wittgenstein bites the bullet and leaves his Tractatus, for the most part, void and meaningless. The suggested response is a dialetheic approach—either as an alternative or, potentially, as an amendment to a Kantian or Wittgensteinian theory. According to this approach, certain problems in philosophy arise from true contradictions and thus require a theory that makes sense of contradiction. A subgroup of these problems (among them the noumenal and structural issues in Kant and Wittgenstein) are about things that both are and are not ineffable. The second half of the paper develops a dialetheic account of ineffability and a concise formal theory to ensure that contradiction at the limits of language does not spread to other areas. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  31. Can we interpret Kant as a compatibilist about determinism and moral responsibility?Ben Vilhauer - 2004 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 12 (4):719 – 730.
    In this paper, I discuss Hud Hudson's compatibilistic interpretation of Kant's theory of free will, which is based on Davidson's anomalous monism. I sketch an alternative interpretation of my own, an incompatibilistic interpretation according to which agents qua noumena are responsible for the particular causal laws which determine the actions of agents qua phenomena. Hudson's interpretation should be attractive to philosophers who value Kant's epistemology and ethics, but insist on a deflationary reading of things in themselves. It is in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  32. Incompatibilism and Ontological Priority in Kant's Theory of Free Will.Benjamin Vilhauer - 2008 - In Pablo Muchnik (ed.), Incompatibilism and Ontological Priority in Kant's Theory of Free Will.
    This paper concerns the role of the transcendental distinction between agents qua phenomena and qua noumena in Kant's theory of free will. It argues (1) that Kant's incompatibilism can be accommodated if one accepts the "ontological" interpretation of this distinction (i.e. the view that agents qua noumena are ontologically prior to agents qua phenomena), and (2) that Kant's incompatibilism cannot be accommodated by the "two-aspect" interpretation, whose defining feature is the rejection of the ontological priority of agents qua (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  12
    Phänomenotechnik und Noumenologie: Gaston Bachelard über die Erweiterung der Wirklichkeit durch Gedankengegenstände.Sebastian Kawanami-Breu - 2022 - Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 70 (6):886-903.
    My paper examines the potential of Gaston Bachelard’s concept of phenomenotechnique through a critique of its historical reception and an analysis of its epistemological implications. Vis-a-vis constructivist and pragmatist interpretations, I argue that the core issue at stake in this concept is not just to regard scientific knowledge as ‘fabricated’ through technical means, but also to understand the radical difference that lies between the experience of a world given to and measured by scientists, and one that is ontologically expanded by (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. Noumenal Causality Reconsidered: Affection, Agency, and Meaning in Kant.Kenneth R. Westphal - 1997 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 27 (2):209 - 245.
    The idea that noumena or things in themselves causally affect our sensibility, and thus provide us with sensations, has been rejected on two basic grounds: It is unintelligible because distinguishes between appearance and reality in such a way that things cannot in principle appear as they really are, and it requires applying the concept of causality trans-phenomenally, contra Kant’s Schematism. I argue that noumenal causality is intelligible and is required out of fidelity to Kant’s texts and doctrines. Kant’s theory (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  35. Problems From Kant.James Van Cleve - 1999 - New York: Oup Usa.
    James Van Cleve examines the main topics from Kant's Critique of Pure Reason, such as transcendental idealism, necessity and analyticity, space and time, substance and cause, noumena and things-in-themselves, problems of the self, and rational theology. He also discusses the relationship between Kant's thought and that of modern anti-realists, such as Putnam and Dummett. Because Van Cleve focuses upon specific problems rather than upon entire passages or sections of the Critique, he makes Kant's work more accessible to the serious (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  36. Things in themselves.Robert Merrihew Adams - 1997 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57 (4):801-825.
    The paper is an interpretation and defense of Kant's conception of things in themselves as noumena, along the following lines. Noumena are transempirical realities. As such they have several important roles in Kant's critical philosophy (Section 1). Our theoretical faculties cannot obtain enough content for a conception of noumena that would assure their real possibility as objects, but can establish their merely formal logical possibility (Sections 2-3). Our practical reason, however, grounds belief in the real possibility of (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  37. A brief history of continental realism.Lee Braver - 2012 - Continental Philosophy Review 45 (2):261-289.
    This paper explains the nature and origin of what I am calling Transgressive Realism, a middle path between realism and anti-realism which tries to combine their strengths while avoiding their weaknesses. Kierkegaard created the position by merging Hegel’s insistence that we must have some kind of contact with anything we can call real (thus rejecting noumena), with Kant’s belief that reality fundamentally exceeds our understanding; human reason should not be the criterion of the real. The result is the idea (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  38. Science Meets Philosophy: Metaphysical Gap & Bilateral Brain.Hermann G. W. Burchard - 2020 - Philosophy Study 10 (10):599-614.
    The essay brings a summation of human efforts seeking to understand our existence. Plato and Kant & cognitive science complete reduction of philosophy to a neural mechanism, evolved along elementary Darwinian principles. Plato in his famous Cave Allegory explains that between reality and our experience of it there exists a great chasm, a metaphysical gap, fully confirmed through particle-wave duality of quantum physics. Kant found that we have two kinds of perception, two senses: By the spatial outer sense we perceive (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  39.  15
    Things in Themselves.Robert Merrihew Adams - 1997 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57 (4):801-825.
    The paper is an interpretation and defense of Kant’s conception of things in themselves as noumena, along the following lines. Noumena are transempirical realities. As such they have several important roles in Kant’s critical philosophy (Section 1). Our theoretical faculties cannot obtain enough content for a conception of noumena that would assure their real possibility as objects, but can establish their merely formal logical possibility (Sections 2-3). Our practical reason, however, grounds belief in the real possibility of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  40. Transcendental Idealism, Noumenal Metaphysical Monism and Epistemological Phenomenalism.Roberto Horácio de Sá Pereira - 2019 - Analytica. Revista de Filosofia 22 (1):81-104.
    In this paper, I present a new reading of transcendental idealism. For a start, I endorse Allison’s rejection of the traditional so-called two-world view and, hence, of Guyer and Van Cleve’s ontological phenomenalism. But following Allais, I also reject Allison’s metaphysical deflacionism: transcendental idealism is metaphysically committed to the existence of things in themselves, noumena in the negative sense. Nevertheless, in opposition to Allais, I take Kant’s claim that appearances are “mere representations” inside our minds seriously. In the empirical (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  19
    A Relational Theory of the Visible.A. H. Louie - 2022 - Axiomathes 32 (5):793-816.
    On the basis of previous studies in relational biology and the phenomenological calculus, in my contribution I outline the mathematical foundations of biological perception generally, and visual perception specifically. In this approach, the premise is that objects in nature are not directly accessible, and that real manifestations are projections of these invariant objects. The morphology of observables is mathematically entailed by the duality of projections and projectors in a bilinear algebra that is the phenomenological calculus. The relationships between what is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42. Practical Cognition and Knowledge of Things-in-Themselves.Karl Schafer - forthcoming - In Evan Tiffany & Dai Heide (eds.), The Idea of Freedom: New Essays on the Kantian Theory of Freedom. Oxford University Press.
    Famously, in the second Critique, Kant claims that our consciousness of the moral law provides us with sufficient grounds for the attribution of freedom to ourselves as noumena or things-in-themselves. In this way, while Kant insists that we have no rational basis to make substantive assertions about things-in-themselves from a theoretical point of view, it is rational for us to assert that we are noumenally free from a practical one. This much is uncontroversial. What is controversial is the cognitive (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  43. Convergence and Consensus in Public Reason.Kevin Vallier - 2011 - Public Affairs Quarterly 25 (4):261-280.
    Reasonable individuals often share a rationale for a decision but, in other cases, they make the same decision based on disparate and often incompatible rationales. The social contract tradition has been divided between these two methods of solving the problem of social cooperation: must social cooperation occur in terms of common reasoning, or can individuals with different doctrines simply converge on shared institutions for their own reasons? For Hobbes, it is rational for all persons, regardless of their theological beliefs, to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  44.  12
    An outline of the idealistic construction of experience.J. B. Baillie - 1906 - New York: Garland.
    Introduction.--Dualism and the new problem.--Truth and experience.--Plan and stages of the argument.--The interpretation of sense-experience: and of perceptual experience.--Understanding and the world of noumena and phenomena.--Self-conscious experience.--The sphere of reason, scientific experience.--The sphere of finite spirit, moral experience.--The sphere of absolute spirit, religious experience, contemplation.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  97
    Kant’s View of the Self In the First Critique. Maria - 2002 - Idealistic Studies 32 (3):191-202.
    In Kant’s Transcendental Idealism, Henry Allison argues that Kant’s theoretical treatment of the self presents both an incoherent “official view” and a coherent “alternative view.” In this paper, I argue that Kant’s genuine position on the self can be reconstructed as a coherent unity by examining the flaws in Allison’s analysis. It is shown that Allison’s objections to Kant’s official view are based on unwarranted metaphysical assumptions and unjustified conceptual identifications. Allison’s own dual-aspect view of the transcendental distinction between phenomena (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  15
    Romanticism, Existentialism and Religion.T. A. Burkill - 1955 - Philosophy 30 (115):318 - 332.
    Thus Pascal sets forth the romanticist thesis that reason has nothing to do with the deep intimations of the worshipping soul. Religion is an affair of the heart, and the productive Source of all things cannot be comprehended by the exercise of the finite intellect. This doctrine foreshadows the Kantian dichotomy between phenomena and noumena: the understanding can legitimately operate only within the sphere of space, time and natural causality, as it knows nothing of the transcendental postulates of the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. The Relation between Reality and Negation in Kant, Maimon, and Fichte.Chiu Yui Plato Tse - forthcoming - In The Significance of Negation in Classical German Philosophy. Dordrecht, Netherlands:
    The aim of this paper is to show that the binary notions of reality and negation play an important role in the philosophical agenda of Kant, Maimon and Fichte. The paper has three sections. The first section illustrates the metaphysical significance of Kant’s introduction of the quantitative opposition between reality and negation, which informs the phenomena-noumena distinction and the attribution of intensive magnitude. The second section argues that Maimon’s speculative appropriation of differentials took up Kant’s conception of real opposition (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  95
    Theoretical philosophy, 1755-1770.Immanuel Kant - 1992 - New York: Cambridge University Press. Edited by David Walford & Ralf Meerbote.
    This is the first volume of the first ever comprehensive edition of the works of Immanuel Kant in English translation. The eleven essays in this volume constitute Kant's theoretical, pre-critical philosophical writings from 1755 to 1770. Several of these pieces have never been translated into English before; others have long been unavailable in English. We can trace in these works the development of Kant's thought to the eventual emergence in 1770 of the two chief tenets of his mature philosophy: the (...)
  49.  44
    Noumenal Freedom and Kant’s Modal Antinomy.Uygar Abaci - 2022 - Kantian Review 27 (2):175-194.
    Kant states in §76 of the third Critique that the divine intuitive intellect would not represent modal distinctions. Kohl and Stang claim that this statement entails that noumena lack modal properties, which, in turn, conflicts with Kant’s attribution of contingency to human noumenal wills. They both propose resolutions to this conflict based on conjectures regarding how God might non-modally represent what our discursive intellects represent as modally determined. I argue that these proposals fail; the viable resolution consists in recognizing (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  50.  33
    Symbolic Languages and Natural Structures a Mathematician’s Account of Empiricism.Hermann G. W. Burchard - 2005 - Foundations of Science 10 (2):153-245.
    The ancient dualism of a sensible and an intelligible world important in Neoplatonic and medieval philosophy, down to Descartes and Kant, would seem to be supplanted today by a scientific view of mind-in-nature. Here, we revive the old dualism in a modified form, and describe mind as a symbolic language, founded in linguistic recursive computation according to the Church-Turing thesis, constituting a world L that serves the human organism as a map of the Universe U. This methodological distinction of L (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
1 — 50 / 139