Results for 'doctrine of restraint'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  66
    Religion, pacifism, and the doctrine of restraint.Christopher J. Eberle - 2006 - Journal of Religious Ethics 34 (2):203-224.
    The doctrine of restraint is the claim that citizens and legislators ought to restrain themselves from making political decisions solely on religious grounds. That doctrine is normally construed as a general constraint on religious arguments: an exclusively religious rationale "as such" is an inappropriate basis for a political decision, particularly a coercive political decision. However, the most common arguments for the doctrine of restraint fail to show that citizens and legislators ought to obey the (...) of restraint, as we can see by reflecting on those arguments as they bear on the Agapic Pacifist's rationale for denying that even legitimate political authorities may use lethal military force. (shrink)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  2.  20
    In Defense of Restraint: Democratic Respect, Public Justification, and Religious Conviction in Liberal Politics.Vic McCracken - 2012 - Journal of the Society of Christian Ethics 32 (1):133-149.
    WHAT DOES RESPECT REQUIRE OF RELIGIOUSLY MOTIVATED CITIZENS AS they support coercive public policies? In his recent work, Christopher Eberle argues against the doctrine of restraint, a norm that requires citizens to refrain from supporting laws for which public reasons are unavailable. Against Eberle, I defend the doctrine of restraint as a necessary corollary to liberal democratic respect. For this defense, I draw from one imaginary case, Robert Audi's example of "sacred dandelions" and laws banning lawn (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. Kant's Non-Absolutist Conception of Political Legitimacy – How Public Right ‘Concludes’ Private Right in the “Doctrine of Right”.Helga Varden - 2010 - Kant Studien 101 (3):331-351.
    Contrary to the received view, I argue that Kant, in the “Doctrine of Right”, outlines a third, republican alternative to absolutist and voluntarist conceptions of political legitimacy. According to this republican alternative, a state must meet certain institutional requirements before political obligations arise. An important result of this interpretation is not only that there are institutional restraints on a legitimate state's use of coercion, but also that the rights of the state (‘public right’) are not in principle reducible to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  4.  11
    Figures of Antichrist: The Apocalypse and Its Restraints in Contemporary Political Thought.Giuseppe Fornari - 2010 - Contagion: Journal of Violence, Mimesis, and Culture 17:53-85.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Figures of Antichrist:The Apocalypse and Its Restraints in Contemporary Political ThoughtGiuseppe Fornari (bio)1. The Antichrist and the Katéchon in Early ChristianityThe history of the Antichrist follows the history of Christ like a shadow.1 This statement is far from banal, not only because of its consequences but also because Christianity as currently presented typically denies that a figure like the Antichrist could be a cause for concern. When confronted with (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  29
    Basic human worth and religious restraint.Christopher J. Eberle - 2009 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 35 (1-2):151-181.
    The Doctrine of Religious Restraint is the claim that citizens and officials in a liberal democracy should not support coercive laws that they know to require a religious rationale. The most prominent argument for the Doctine of Religious Restraint appeals to the claim that we ought to treat each person as having basic worth: citizens and officials ought to obey the Doctrine of Religious Restraint because doing so is required in order for them to respect (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  6. Hurting or Helping? A Catholic Ethical Analysis of the Practice of Physical and Mechanical Restraints by Human Services.Marc Tumeinski - 2019 - Fellowship of Catholic Scholars Quarterly 4 (41):435-448.
    Jesus embodies for the Christian the model of true service, which should be discernibly distinct from secular service. Even for non-Christian services, the Church offers relevant models and teaching. Contemporary service structures often lose sight of the dignity of served and server, and have grown dependent upon technology and technique, straying outside the realm of relationality. An example of this within certain service fields is reliance on physical and mechanical restraints to restrict movement, causing harm to recipients and to the (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  18
    Of Wild Beasts and Bloodhounds: John Locke and Frederick Douglass on the Forfeiture of Humanity.Jennifer A. Herdt - 2021 - Journal of the Society of Christian Ethics 41 (2):207-224.
    The doctrine of the image of God is often regarded as grounding human dignity in something permanent and unchanging that transcends our attitudes and behaviors. Yet we persistently encounter the argument that particular human individuals or groups have acted so as to forfeit their moral standing as fellow humans. They are bestialized, categorized as non-human animals, lifting ordinary restraints on punishment. I examine the logic of this argument in John Locke, Thomas Aquinas, and contemporary felony disenfranchisement, showing how it (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  28
    Overcoming Temptations to Violate Human Dignity in Times of Crisis: On the Possibilities for Meaningful Self-Restraint.Steven R. Ratner - 2004 - Theoretical Inquiries in Law 5 (1):81-109.
    The codification of international human rights law and international humanitarian law, and the accession to those treaties by a large majority of states, does not at first glance seem to have any significant effect upon states' behavior in situations of crisis. Any understanding of the prospects for such law in these situations requires an appraisal of both the motivations of states in concluding these treaties and the pressures on them to ignore them. This paper analyzes those motivations and temptations through (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9. On the Presence of Educated Religious Beliefs in the Public Sphere.Gheorghe-Ilie Farte - 2015 - Argumentum. Journal of the Seminar of Discursive Logic, Argumentation Theory and Rhetoric 13 (2):146-178.
    Discursive liberal democracy might not be the best of all possible forms of government, yet in Europe it is largely accepted as such. The attractors of liberal democracy (majority rule, political equality, reasonable self-determination and an ideological framework built in a tentative manner) as well as an adequate dose of secularization (according to the doctrine of religious restraint) provide both secularist and educated religious people with the most convenient ideological framework. Unfortunately, many promoters of ideological secularization take too (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10.  2
    The Effect of EU Law.Anthony Arnull - 2015 - In Dennis Patterson (ed.), A Companion to European Union Law and International Law. Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 62–79.
    This chapter considers the effect of European Union (EU) law in the national courts of the member states and its status vis‐a‐vis overlapping rules of national law. The basic doctrines crafted by the Court of Justice of the European Union (CJEU) marked a significant departure from the standard model of international law and made a major contribution to the early development of the common market. The CJEU added, in many national legal systems the essentials of the legal rules governing State (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  37
    Religion, respect and Eberle’s agapic pacifist.Robert B. Talisse - 2012 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 38 (3):313-325.
    Christopher Eberle has developed a powerful critique of justificatory liberalism. According to Eberle, justificatory liberalism’s doctrine of restraint , which requires religious citizens to refrain from publicly advocating for policies that can be supported only by their religious reasons, is illiberal. In this article, I defend justificatory liberalism against Eberle’s critique.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  12.  64
    The katechon in the age of biopolitical nihilism.Sergei Prozorov - 2012 - Continental Philosophy Review 45 (4):483-503.
    The article addresses the ‘messianic turn’ in contemporary continental philosophy, focusing on the concept of the katechon as the restraining force that delays the advent of the Antichrist in the Second Letter to the Thessalonians. While Carl Schmitt held the passage on the katechon to ground the Christian doctrine of state power, Giorgio Agamben’s reading of Pauline messianism rather posits the ‘removal’ of the katechon as the pathway for messianic redemption. In our argument, the significance of this text goes (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  13.  33
    Documentation.Sacred Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith - 1992 - Review of Metaphysics 46 (1):239-239.
  14.  23
    Fichte e Schelling em confronto – filosofia da reflexão ou não?Francisco Prata Gaspar - 2015 - Doispontos 12 (2).
    O objetivo do artigo é apresentar a discussão entre Fichte e Schelling em torno do conflito entre o idealismo transcendental da doutrina-da-ciência e a filosofia-da-natureza do Identitätssystem. Buscamos compreender, de um ponto de vista fichteano, se e em que medida é possível afirmar que a doutrina-da-ciência é uma filosofia da reflexão, tal como entendida por Schelling. Para tanto, em um primeiro momento, serão expostas as críticas de Schelling a Fichte, como ele progressivamente se afasta em relação à filosofia transcendental e (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  15.  30
    Religious conviction in the profession of arms.Christopher J. Eberle & Rick Rubel - 2012 - Journal of Military Ethics 11 (3):171-185.
    Abstract Many political theorists have argued that religious reasons should play a rather limited role in public or political settings. So, for example, according to the Doctrine of Religious Restraint, citizens and legislators ought not allow religious reasons to play a decisive role in justifying public policies. Many military professionals seem to believe that some version of that doctrine applies in military settings, that is, that military professionals should not allow their religious convictions to determine how they (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  44
    Democratic Erosion, Populist Constitutionalism, and the Unconstitutional Constitutional Amendments Doctrine.Tamar Hostovsky Brandes & Yaniv Roznai - 2020 - Law and Ethics of Human Rights 14 (1):19-48.
    The world is experiencing a crisis of constitutional democracies. Populist leaders are abusing constitutional mechanisms, such as formal procedures of constitutional change, in order to erode the democratic order. The changes are, very often, gradual, incremental, and subtle. Each constitutional change, on its own, may not necessarily amount to a serious violation of essential democratic values. Yet, when examined in the context of an ongoing process, such constitutional changes may prove to be part of the incremental, gradual process of democratic (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  12
    Sacred Doctrine, Secular Practice: Theology and Philosophy in the Faculty of Arts at Paris, 1325–1400.Jack Zupko - 1997 - In Jan Aertsen & Andreas Speer (eds.), Was ist Philosophie im Mittelalter? Qu'est-ce que la philosophie au moyen âge? What is Philosophy in the Middle Ages?: Akten des X. Internationalen Kongresses für Mittelalterliche Philosophie der Société Internationale pour l'Etude de la Philosophie Médié. Erfurt: De Gruyter. pp. 656-666.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  19
    The ethos of sovereignty: A critical appraisal. [REVIEW]Panu Minkkinen - 2007 - Human Rights Review 8 (2):33-51.
    Taking as its starting point the commonly held claim about the obscurity of the concept of sovereignty, the article first identifies a fundamental paradox between the classical Westphalian notion of state sovereignty and human rights. In the rhetoric of international politics, attempts to establish the responsibility of states to respect human rights and fundamental freedoms within their jurisdictions are often countered with claims referring to the “sovereign equality” of all states and the subsequent principle of non-intervention. The article suggests that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19. Why The Doctrine Of Right Does Not Belong In The Metaphysics Of Morals.Marcus Willaschek - 1997 - Jahrbuch für Recht Und Ethik 5.
    Der Aufsatz behandelt den Zusammenhang zwischen Recht, Ethik und Moral in der MdS. Ausgangspunkt ist der Befund, daß Kants System der Pflichten in der MdS weder konsistent noch vollständig ist, weil Rechts- und Tugendpflichten, entgegen Kants Annahme, den Bereich der moralischen Pflichten nicht erschöpfen . Kants System der Pflichten beruht auf den Unterscheidungen zwischen Recht und Ethik und zwischen Legalität und Moralität. Letztere konzipiert Kant in der MdS anders als in früheren Werken, indem er sie nun auf die beiden Arten (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  20.  67
    Putnam's doctrine of natural kind words and Frege's doctrines of sense, reference, and extension: Can they cohere?David Wiggins - 1994 - In Peter Clark & Bob Hale (eds.), Reading Putnam. Blackwell. pp. 59--74.
  21.  60
    On the Platonist Doctrine of the ἀσύμβλητοι ἀριθμοί.J. Cook Wilson - 1904 - The Classical Review 18 (05):247-260.
  22. The significance of the doctrine of sympathy in Hume and Adam Smith.Glenn R. Morrow - 1923 - Philosophical Review 32 (1):60-78.
  23.  37
    God, War, and Conscience.Christopher J. Eberle - 2007 - Journal of Religious Ethics 35 (3):479-507.
    Many military officers believe that they morally ought to obey legal orders to fight even in unjust wars: they have a moral obligation to exercise indiscriminate obedience to legal orders to fight. I argue that officers should not be required to exercise indiscriminate obedience: certain theistic commitments to which many citizens and officers adhere prohibit indiscriminate obedience to legal orders to fight. This theistic argument constitutes adequate reason not to require officers to exercise indiscriminate obedience. However, this raises a further (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24.  95
    Recent Philosophical Work on the Doctrine of the Eucharist.James M. Arcadi - 2016 - Philosophy Compass 11 (7):402-412.
    The doctrine of the Eucharist has been one of the more fruitful locales of philosophical reflection within Christian theology. The central philosophical question has been, ‘what is the state of affairs such that it is apt to say of a piece of bread, “This is the body of Christ”?’ In this article, I offer a delineation of various families of answers to this question as they have been proffered in the history of the church. These families are distinguished by (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  25.  7
    Isvara-Pratyabhijna-Vimarsini of Abhinavagupta: Doctrine of Divine Recognition.K. A. Abhinavagupta, Kanti Chandra Subramania Iyer, R. C. Pandey & Dwivedi (eds.) - 1986 - Motilal Banarsidass Publ..
    that Buddhism is best understood as a philosophy of practice-or a.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  82
    Berkeley's doctrine of notions and theory of meaning.A. D. Woozley - 1976 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 14 (4):427-434.
  27.  11
    Towards the social doctrine of the Orthodox Church: The document ‘For the Life of the World’ of the Ecumenical Patriarchate.Iuliu-Marius Morariu - 2021 - HTS Theological Studies 77 (4):1-6.
    Amongst the recent documents released by the Greek Ecumenical Patriarchate of Constantinople, the one titled ‘For the Life of the World’, published before the beginning of the COVID-19 pandemic, touches upon an important section of the life of the Orthodox Church, namely, the social one. As a result of the fact that, so far, there is no official document of the aforementioned Church dedicated to this aspect, whilst the Reformed Churches and the Catholic one have already issued similar documents, I (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  28
    The body disciplined: Rewriting teaching competence and the doctrine of reflection.Peter Erlandson - 2005 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 39 (4):661–670.
    Shortly after the publication of The Reflective Practitioner (1983) and the sequel Educating the Reflective Practitioner (1987) ‘reflection-in-action’ became a major concept in teacher education. The concept has, however, been criticised on ontological/epistemological as well as practice oriented accounts (Van Manen, 1995; Newman, 1999; Erlandson, 1995). In this paper I argue that reflection-in-action is a theoretical construction that snatches the interacting, working, and producing bodies from their practices, and consequently, matters of politics, of discipline, of institutional interaction and of the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  29.  88
    Belief, Affirmation, and the Doctrine of Conatus in Spinoza.Diane Steinberg - 2005 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 43 (1):147-158.
  30.  15
    The Controversy of the Correctoria and the Limits of Metaphysics.Mark Jordan - 1982 - Speculum 57 (2):292-314.
    The first defenses of Aquinas's doctrine after his death, particularly those five polemical works known as the correctoria, are usually read as illustrations of the intellectual forces of the late thirteenth century. The correctoria are used to show the struggle between “Augustinianism” and “Aristotelianism,” between Franciscans and Dominicans, between anti-Thomists and Thomists. It is true that they are anti-Augustinian, after a fashion. They come from Dominican hands, and they defend Thomas. But it is important to see why they reject (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31.  11
    Metaphysical Foundations and Complementarity of Science and Theology.James A. Marcum - 2005 - Journal of Interdisciplinary Studies 17 (1-2):45-64.
    This essay examines the metaphysical foundations of the natural sciences and Christian theology in order to complement the epistemic claims from both disciplines. These foundations include Robin Collingwood's notion of presuppositions and Ernan McMullin's epistemic and non-epistemic values. Specifically, the essay investigates the presuppositions and values of science and theology used for guiding and constraining the formation and evaluation of scientific theories and theological doctrines. Practitioners in both disciplines need to keep these presuppositions and values in mind when complementing epistemic (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. Philippa Foot and the Doctrine of Double Effect.Roy Weatherford - 1979 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 60 (1):105.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  14
    ‘Three Subsistences … One Substance’: the Doctrine of the Trinity in the Second London Confession.Steve Weaver - 2022 - Perichoresis 20 (1):9-21.
    This article examines the doctrine of the Trinity taught in the Second London Confession of Faith of 1677. It begins by examining a trinitarian controversy among the Particular Baptists of England in the mid-seventeenth century. After outlining the doctrinal deviations of Thomas Collier, the article proceeds to describe some of the responses to Collier from the Particular Baptist community. In many ways the Second London Confession can be seen as a response to Collier. The article also explores the theology (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. The Reformed Doctrine of Adoption.Robert Alexander Webb - 1947
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  2
    Ficino’s Doctrine of Love and Beauty and its Plotinian Background.Sonja Weiss - 2022 - Filozofia 77 (1):20-35.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36. In This Name; The Doctrine of the Trinity in Contemporary Theology.Claude Welch - 1952
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  26
    Spinoza's doctrine of the relationship between mind and body.W. Hale White - 1896 - International Journal of Ethics 6 (4):515-518.
  38. The Biblical Doctrine of Initiation; A Theology of Baptism and Evangelism.R. E. O. WHITE - 1960
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39. The Biblical Doctrine of Initiation.R. E. O. White - 1960
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  51
    Paduan epistemology and the doctrine of the one mind.Harold Skulsky - 1968 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 6 (4):341-361.
  41.  1
    The Constitution of the Intellect and the Farabian Doctrine of First and Second Intention.Nicholas A. Oschman - 2018 - Phänomenologische Forschungen 2018 (2):46-60.
    This article examines Abu Nasr al-Farabı (c. 872–950/1) on the topic of intentionality, with particular focus on how intentionality is integral for the constitution of the intellect within his psychology. Unfortunately, targeted study of al-Farabı’s doctrine of intentionality has been largely neglected since Kwame Gyekye’s 1971 essay, The Terms ‘Prima Intentio’ and ‘Secunda Intentio’ in Arabic Logic. Gyekye showed that the Arabic (and thus the Latin) doctrine of first and second intention originated within the texts of al-Farabı,not the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42. A series of eleven lessons in karma yoga (the yogi philosophy of thought-use) and the yogin doctrine of work. Bhikshu - 1928 - Tinevelly, (S. India): The Latent light culture.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. Authorized Coercion in the Introduction to Kant's Doctrine of Right.Fdbio Frangois Mendonga da Fonseca - 2008 - In Valerio Hrsg V. Rohden, Ricardo Terra & Guido Almeida (eds.), Recht Und Frieden in der Philosophie Kants. pp. 323.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  4
    The principle of Mind Healing: Focused on Buddhist Doctrine of Karma and Retribution. 장진영 - 2017 - Journal of the Society of Philosophical Studies 116:193-219.
    본고에서는 인간이 겪는 고통을 개인적 고통과 사회적 고통으로 대별하고 불교의 업설을 통해 그 원리와 해법을 살펴보았다. 업설에 따르면 인간의 모든 의지적 행위가 곧 업이며, 그 업에는 반드시 과보가 따른다. 그러므로 우리가 고통에서 벗어나기 위해 업을 제거하도록 해야 한다. 불교의 업설에서 주목해야 할 것으로 첫째, 모든 행위에 있어서 그 결과보다는 ‘의지(의도)’를 중시한다는 점이다. 그러므로 어떤 행위를 함에 있어서 그 선택의 자율성을 어떻게 확보할 것인지가 자기치유에 있어서 매우 중요하다. 둘째, 업설은 사회적(자연적) 관계 속에서 이해되어야 한다는 점이다. 즉 우리에게 주어진 조건(인간관계, 주변 환경)은 (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  11
    A Study of the Doctrine of Metempsychosis in Greece: From Pythagoras to Plato.Edwin L. Minar & Herbert Strainge Long - 1950 - American Journal of Philology 71 (4):447.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  46.  71
    Mill's doctrine of natural kinds.W. H. S. Monck - 1887 - Mind 12 (48):637-640.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  47. Defending the Doctrine of the Mean Against Counterexamples: A General Strategy.Nicholas Colgrove - 2024 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly (Online First):1-24.
    Aristotle’s doctrine of the mean states that each moral virtue stands opposed to two types of vice: one of excess and one of deficiency, respectively. Critics claim that some virtues—like honesty, fair-mindedness, and patience—are counterexamples to Aristotle’s doctrine. Here, I develop a generalizable strategy to defend the doctrine of the mean against such counterexamples. I argue that not only is the doctrine of the mean defensible, but taking it seriously also allows us to gain substantial insight (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  14
    3. The Doctrine of the Relativity of Human Knowledge, as Held by Sir William Hamilton.John StuartHG Mill - 1979 - In An Examination of Sir William Hamilton's Philosophy: Volume 9. University of Toronto Press. pp. 13-33.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  2
    17. The Doctrine of Concepts, or General Notions.John StuartHG Mill - 1979 - In An Examination of Sir William Hamilton's Philosophy: Volume 9. University of Toronto Press. pp. 301-323.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  21
    Whether the Doctrine of Informed Consent is Rhetoric: Understanding Autonomy and Informed Consent in the Indian Context.Vibhav Mithal - 2014 - Asian Bioethics Review 6 (1):39-54.
1 — 50 / 1000