Results for 'axiomatization of plane geometry'

999 found
Order:
  1.  23
    Constructive Axiomatizations of Plane Absolute, Euclidean and Hyperbolic Geometry.Victor Pambuccian - 2001 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 47 (1):129-136.
    In this paper we provide quantifier-free, constructive axiomatizations for 2-dimensional absolute, Euclidean, and hyperbolic geometry. The main novelty consists in the first-order languages in which the axiom systems are formulated.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  2.  26
    Constructive Axiomatization of Plane Hyperbolic Geometry.Victor Pambuccian - 2001 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 47 (4):475-488.
    We provide a universal axiom system for plane hyperbolic geometry in a firstorder language with two sorts of individual variables, ‘points’ and ‘lines’ , containing three individual constants, A0, A1, A2, standing for three non-collinear points, two binary operation symbols, φ and ι, with φ = l to be interpreted as ‘[MATHEMATICAL SCRIPT SMALL L] is the line joining A and B’ , and ι = P to be interpreted as [MATHEMATICAL SCRIPT SMALL L]P is the point of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  3.  24
    Another Constructive Axiomatization of Euclidean Planes.Victor Pambuccian - 2000 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 46 (1):45-48.
    H. Tietze has proved algebraically that the geometry of uniquely determined ruler and compass constructions coincides with the geometry of ruler and set square constructions. We provide a new proof of this result via new universal axiom systems for Euclidean planes of characteristic ≠ 2 in languages containing only operation symbols.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  35
    Royden H. L.. Remarks on primitive notions for elementary Euclidean and non-Euclidean plane geometry. The axiomatic method with special reference to geometry and physics, Proceedings of an International Symposium held at the University of California, Berkeley, December 26,1957-January 4, 1958, Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics, North-Holland Publishing Company, Amsterdam 1959, pp. 86–96. [REVIEW]Lesław W. Szczerba - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (3):473-474.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  16
    Ternary operations as primitive notions for constructive plane geometry III.Victor Pambuccian - 1993 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 39 (1):393-402.
    This paper continues the investigations begun in [6] and continued in [7] about quantifier-free axiomatizations of plane Euclidean geometry using ternary operations. We show that plane Euclidean geometry over Archimedean ordered Euclidean fields can be axiomatized using only two ternary operations if one allows axioms that are not first-order but universal Lw1,w sentences. The operations are: the transport of a segment on a halfline that starts at one of the endpoints of the given segment, and the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6.  29
    Ternary operations as primitive notions for plane geometry II.Victor Pambuccian - 1992 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 38 (1):345-348.
    We proved in the first part [1] that plane geometry over Pythagorean fields is axiomatizable by quantifier-free axioms in a language with three individual constants, one binary and three ternary operation symbols. In this paper we prove that two of these operation symbols are superfluous.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7.  22
    Ternary Operations as Primitive Notions for Constructive Plane Geometry VI.Victor Pambuccian - 1995 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 41 (3):384-394.
    In this paper we provide quantifier-free, constructive axiomatizations for several fragments of plane Euclidean geometry over Euclidean fields, such that each axiom contains at most 4 variables. The languages in which they are expressed contain only at most ternary operations. In some precisely defined sense these axiomatizations are the simplest possible.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  8.  9
    Ternary Operations as Primitive Notions for Constructive Plane Geometry V.Victor Pambuccian - 1994 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 40 (4):455-477.
    In this paper we provide a quantifier-free, constructive axiomatization of metric-Euclidean and of rectangular planes . The languages in which the axiom systems are expressed contain three individual constants and two ternary operations. We also provide an axiom system in algorithmic logic for finite Euclidean planes, and for several minimal metric-Euclidean planes. The axiom systems proposed will be used in a sequel to this paper to provide ‘the simplest possible’ axiom systems for several fragments of plane Euclidean (...). (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  9.  21
    Ternary Operations as Primitive Notions for Constructive Plane Geometry IV.Victor Pambuccian - 1994 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 40 (1):76-86.
    In this paper we provide a quantifier-free constructive axiomatization for Euclidean planes in a first-order language with only ternary operation symbols and three constant symbols . We also determine the algorithmic theories of some ‘naturally occurring’ plane geometries.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10.  33
    The axioms of constructive geometry.Jan von Plato - 1995 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 76 (2):169-200.
    Elementary geometry can be axiomatized constructively by taking as primitive the concepts of the apartness of a point from a line and the convergence of two lines, instead of incidence and parallelism as in the classical axiomatizations. I first give the axioms of a general plane geometry of apartness and convergence. Constructive projective geometry is obtained by adding the principle that any two distinct lines converge, and affine geometry by adding a parallel line construction, etc. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  11.  8
    David Hilbert and the foundations of the theory of plane area.Eduardo N. Giovannini - 2021 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 75 (6):649-698.
    This paper provides a detailed study of David Hilbert’s axiomatization of the theory of plane area, in the classical monograph Foundation of Geometry. On the one hand, we offer a precise contextualization of this theory by considering it against its nineteenth-century geometrical background. Specifically, we examine some crucial steps in the emergence of the modern theory of geometrical equivalence. On the other hand, we analyze from a more conceptual perspective the significance of Hilbert’s theory of area for (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12.  25
    Axiomatizations of Hyperbolic Geometry: A Comparison Based on Language and Quantifier Type Complexity.Victor Pambuccian - 2002 - Synthese 133 (3):331-341.
    Hyperbolic geometry can be axiomatized using the notions of order andcongruence (as in Euclidean geometry) or using the notion of incidencealone (as in projective geometry). Although the incidence-based axiomatizationmay be considered simpler because it uses the single binary point-linerelation of incidence as a primitive notion, we show that it issyntactically more complex. The incidence-based formulation requires some axioms of the quantifier-type \forall\exists\forall, while the axiom system based on congruence and order can beformulated using only \forall\exists-axioms.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  13.  59
    Axiomatizations of hyperbolic geometry: A comparison based on language and quantifier type complexity.Victor Pambuccian - 2002 - Synthese 133 (3):331 - 341.
    Hyperbolic geometry can be axiomatized using the notions of order andcongruence (as in Euclidean geometry) or using the notion of incidencealone (as in projective geometry). Although the incidence-based axiomatizationmay be considered simpler because it uses the single binary point-linerelation of incidence as a primitive notion, we show that it issyntactically more complex. The incidence-based formulation requires some axioms of the quantifier-type forallexistsforall, while the axiom system based on congruence and order can beformulated using only forallexists-axioms.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  14.  51
    Correction to “Axiomatizations of Hyperbolic Geometry”.Victor Pambuccian - 2005 - Synthese 145 (3):497-497.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  71
    Optical axiomatization of Minkowski space-time geometry.Brent Mundy - 1986 - Philosophy of Science 53 (1):1-30.
    Minkowski geometry is axiomatized in terms of the asymmetric binary relation of optical connectibility, using ten first-order axioms and the second-order continuity axiom. An axiom system in terms of the symmetric binary optical connection relation is also presented. The present development is much simpler than the corresponding work of Robb, upon which it is modeled.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  16. The twofold role of diagrams in Euclid’s plane geometry.Marco Panza - 2012 - Synthese 186 (1):55-102.
    Proposition I.1 is, by far, the most popular example used to justify the thesis that many of Euclid’s geometric arguments are diagram-based. Many scholars have recently articulated this thesis in different ways and argued for it. My purpose is to reformulate it in a quite general way, by describing what I take to be the twofold role that diagrams play in Euclid’s plane geometry (EPG). Euclid’s arguments are object-dependent. They are about geometric objects. Hence, they cannot be diagram-based (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  17.  18
    The complexity of plane hyperbolic incidence geometry is∀∃∀∃.Victor Pambuccian - 2005 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 51 (3):277-281.
    We show that plane hyperbolic geometry, expressed in terms of points and the ternary relation of collinearity alone, cannot be expressed by means of axioms of complexity at most ∀∃∀, but that there is an axiom system, all of whose axioms are ∀∃∀∃ sentences. This remains true for Klingenberg's generalized hyperbolic planes, with arbitrary ordered fields as coordinate fields.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  18.  23
    Die Eindeutigkeit der konstruktiven Geometrie.Karl-Heinrich Katthage - 1987 - Zeitschrift Für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 18 (1-2):285-295.
    Inquiries of Wellstein, Grünbaum and others have proved that there are indefinitely many different spatial models of Euklidian geometry. The points, lines and planes of these models are related to each other as the points, straight lines and planes of Euklidian geometry, but they are obviously totally different from them. That means that the axiomatic Euklidian geometry does not clearly determine the spatial forms of their planes and straight lines. The constructive geometry basing on approaches of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  7
    On the arithmetization of school geometry in the setting of modern axiomatics.Tasos Patronis & Yannis Thomaidis - 1997 - Science & Education 6 (3):273-290.
  20.  14
    Simplifying von Plato's axiomatization of Constructive Apartness Geometry.Dafa Li, Peifa Jia & Xinxin Li - 2000 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 102 (1-2):1-26.
    In the 1920s Heyting attempted at axiomatizing constructive geometry. Recently, von Plato used different concepts to axiomatize it. He used 14 axioms to formulate constructive apartness geometry, seven of which have occurrences of negation. In this paper we show with the help of ANDP, a theorem prover based on natural deduction, that four new axioms without negation, shorter and more intuitive, can replace seven of von Plato's 14 ones. Thus we obtained a near negation-free new system consisting of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21.  21
    Corrigendum to “The complexity of plane hyperbolic incidence geometry is ∀∃∀∃”.Victor Pambuccian - 2008 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 54 (6):668-668.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  29
    A Proposition of Elementary Plane Geometry that Implies the Continuum Hypothesis.Frederick Bagemihl - 1961 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 7 (1-5):77-79.
  23.  26
    Groups and Plane Geometry.Victor Pambuccian - 2005 - Studia Logica 81 (3):387-398.
    We show that the first-order theory of a large class of plane geometries and the first-order theory of their groups of motions, understood both as groups with a unary predicate singling out line-reflections, and as groups acting on sets, are mutually inter-pretable.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  24.  44
    Abstraction and Intuition in Peano's Axiomatizations of Geometry.Davide Rizza - 2009 - History and Philosophy of Logic 30 (4):349-368.
    Peano's axiomatizations of geometry are abstract and non-intuitive in character, whereas Peano stresses his appeal to concrete spatial intuition in the choice of the axioms. This poses the problem of understanding the interrelationship between abstraction and intuition in his geometrical works. In this article I argue that axiomatization is, for Peano, a methodology to restructure geometry and isolate its organizing principles. The restructuring produces a more abstract presentation of geometry, which does not contradict its intuitive content (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  25.  20
    Equivalence to the Continuum Hypothesis of a Certain Proposition of Elementary Plane Geometry.Roy O. Davies - 1962 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 8 (2):109-111.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  24
    Equivalence to the Continuum Hypothesis of a Certain Proposition of Elementary Plane Geometry.Roy O. Davies - 1962 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 8 (2):109-111.
  27.  14
    A structural and foundational analysis of euclid’s plane geometry: The case study of continuity.Pierluigi Graziani - 2014 - In Vincenzo Fano, Francesco Orilia & Giovanni Macchia (eds.), Space and Time: A Priori and a Posteriori Studies. Boston: De Gruyter. pp. 63-106.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  12
    Enthymemathical proofs and canonical proofs in Euclid's plane geometry.Abel Lassalle & Marco Panza - 2018 - In Claudio Bartocci (ed.), The Philosophers and Mathematics. Springer Verlag. pp. 127-144.
    Since the application of Postulate I.2 in Euclid's Elements is not uniform, one could wonder in what way should it be applied in Euclid's plane geometry. Besides legitimizing questions like this from the perspective of a philosophy of mathematical practice, we sketch a general perspective of conceptual analysis of mathematical texts, which involves an extended notion of mathematical theory as system of authorizations, and an audience-dependent notion of proof.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  26
    A common axiom set for classical and intuitionistic plane geometry.Melinda Lombard & Richard Vesley - 1998 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 95 (1-3):229-255.
    We describe a first order axiom set which yields the classical first order Euclidean geometry of Tarski when used with classical logic, and yields an intuitionistic Euclidean geometry when used with intuitionistic logic. The first order language has a single six place atomic predicate and no function symbols. The intuitionistic system has a computational interpretation in recursive function theory, that is, a realizability interpretation analogous to those given by Kleene for intuitionistic arithmetic and analysis. This interpretation shows the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  30.  8
    Enthymemathical Proofs and Canonical Proofs in Euclid’s Plane Geometry.Marco Panza & Abel Lassalle-Casanave - 2018 - In Hassan Tahiri (ed.), The Philosophers and Mathematics: Festschrift for Roshdi Rashed. Cham: Springer Verlag. pp. 127-144.
    Since the application of Postulate I.2 in Euclid’s Elements is not uniform, one could wonder in what way should it be applied in Euclid’s plane geometry. Besides legitimizing questions like this from the perspective of a philosophy of mathematical practice, we sketch a general perspective of conceptual analysis of mathematical texts, which involves an extended notion of mathematical theory as system of authorizations, and an audience-dependent notion of proof.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. Quantifier-free axioms for constructive affine plane geometry.Patrick Suppes - 2000 - Synthese 125 (1-2):263-281.
  32. Axiomatics, empiricism, and Anschauung in Hilbert's conception of geometry: Between arithmetic and general relativity.Leo Corry - 2006 - In José Ferreirós Domínguez & Jeremy Gray (eds.), The Architecture of Modern Mathematics: Essays in History and Philosophy. Oxford University Press. pp. 133--156.
  33.  34
    Analysis of contrasts and identifications of Burgers vectors for basal-plane dislocations and threading edge dislocations in 4H-SiC crystals observed by monochromatic synchrotron X-ray topography in grazing-incidence Bragg-case geometry.Hirofumi Matsuhata, Hirotaka Yamaguchi & Toshiyuki Ohno - 2012 - Philosophical Magazine 92 (36):4599-4617.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  34. The Physical Content of Minkowski Geometry.Brent Mundy - 1986 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 37 (1):25-54.
    The standard coordinate-based formulation of the space-time theory of special relativity (Minkowski geometry) is philosophically unsatisfactory for various reasons. We here present an explicit axiomatic formulation of that theory in terms of primitives with a definitive physical interpretation, prove its equivalence to the standard coordinate formulation, and draw various philosophical conclusions concerning the physical content and assumptions of the space-time theory. The prevalent causal interpretation of physical Minkowski geometry deriving from Reichenbach is criticised on the basis of the (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  35.  5
    The axiomatic geometry of Space-Time: An assessment of the work of A. A. Robb.A. J. Briginshaw - 1979 - Centaurus 22 (4):315-323.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  13
    Mario Pieri’s View of the Symbiotic Relationship between the Foundations and the Teaching of Elementary Geometry in the Context of the Early Twentieth Century Proposals for Pedagogical Reform.Elena Anne Corie Marchisotto & Ana Millán Gasca - 2021 - Philosophia Scientiae 25:157-183.
    In this paper, we discuss a proposal for reform in the teaching of Euclidean geometry that reveals the symbiotic relationship between axiomatics and pedagogy. We examine the role of intuition in this kind of reform, as expressed by Mario Pieri, a prominent member of the Schools of Peano and Segre at the University of Turin. We are well aware of the centuries of attention paid to the notion of intuition by mathematicians, mathematics educators, philosophers, psychologists, historians, and others. To (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37.  39
    Beltrami's model and the independence of the parallel postulate.J. Scanlan Michael - 1988 - History and Philosophy of Logic 9 (1):13-34.
    E. Beltrami in 1868 did not intend to prove the consistency of non-euclidean plane geometry nor the independence of the euclidean parallel postulate. His approach would have been unsuccessful if so intended. J. Hoüel in 1870 described the relevance of Beltrami's work to the issue of the independence of the euclidean parallel postulate. Hoüel's method is different from the independence proofs using reinterpretation of terms deployed by Peano about 1890, chiefly in using a fixed interpretation for non-logical terms. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  38.  8
    Review: H. L. Royden, Remarks on Primitive Notions for Elementary Euclidean and Non-Euclidean Plane Geometry[REVIEW]Leslaw W. Szczerba - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (3):473-474.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  89
    Nathaniel Miller. Euclid and his twentieth century rivals: Diagrams in the logic of euclidean geometry. Csli studies in the theory and applications of diagrams.John Mumma - 2008 - Philosophia Mathematica 16 (2):256-264.
    It is commonplace to view the rigor of the mathematics in Euclid's Elements in the way an experienced teacher views the work of an earnest beginner: respectable relative to an early stage of development, but ultimately flawed. Given the close connection in content between Euclid's Elements and high-school geometry classes, this is understandable. Euclid, it seems, never realized what everyone who moves beyond elementary geometry into more advanced mathematics is now customarily taught: a fully rigorous proof cannot rely (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  40.  34
    Max Beberman and Herbert E. Vaughan. High school mathematics. Course 2. Plane geometry with appendices on logic and solid geometry. D. C. Heath and Company, Boston, Englewood, Chicago, San Francisco, Atlanta, Dallas, London, and Toronto, 1965, xi + 584 pp. - Max Beberman and Herbert E. Vaughan. High school mathematics. Course 2. Plane geometry with appendices on logic and solid geometry. Teacher's edition. D. C. Heath and Company, Boston, Englewood, Chicago, San Francisco, Atlanta, Dallas, London, and Toronto, 1965, 608 pp. [REVIEW]Theodore Hailperin - 1966 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 31 (4):672-673.
  41. On the relationship between plane and solid geometry.Andrew Arana & Paolo Mancosu - 2012 - Review of Symbolic Logic 5 (2):294-353.
    Traditional geometry concerns itself with planimetric and stereometric considerations, which are at the root of the division between plane and solid geometry. To raise the issue of the relation between these two areas brings with it a host of different problems that pertain to mathematical practice, epistemology, semantics, ontology, methodology, and logic. In addition, issues of psychology and pedagogy are also important here. To our knowledge there is no single contribution that studies in detail even one of (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  42.  13
    The Axiomatic Method: With Special Reference to Geometry and Physics: Proceedings of an International Symposium Held at the University of California, Berkeley, December 26, 1957 - January 4, 1958.Leon Henkin, Patrick Suppes & Alfred Tarski (eds.) - 1959 - Amsterdam, Netherlands: North-Holland.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  96
    Edmund Husserl on the Applicability of Formal Geometry.René Jagnow - 2006 - In Emily Carson & Renate Huber (eds.), Intuition and the Axiomatic Method. Springer. pp. 67-85.
    In this paper, I reconstruct Edmund Husserl's view on the relationship between formal inquiry and the life-world, using the example of formal geometry. I first outline Husserl's account of geometry and then argue that he believed that the applicability of formal geometry to intuitive space (the space of everyday-experience) guarantees the conceptual continuity between different notions of space.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  13
    Thermodynamics of multicaloric effects in multiferroics.A. Planes, T. Castán & A. Saxena - 2014 - Philosophical Magazine 94 (17):1893-1908.
  45.  81
    Axiomatizing Changing Conceptions of the Geometric Continuum I: Euclid-Hilbert†.John T. Baldwin - 2018 - Philosophia Mathematica 26 (3):346-374.
    We give a general account of the goals of axiomatization, introducing a variant on Detlefsen’s notion of ‘complete descriptive axiomatization’. We describe how distinctions between the Greek and modern view of number, magnitude, and proportion impact the interpretation of Hilbert’s axiomatization of geometry. We argue, as did Hilbert, that Euclid’s propositions concerning polygons, area, and similar triangles are derivable from Hilbert’s first-order axioms. We argue that Hilbert’s axioms including continuity show much more than the geometrical propositions (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  46.  78
    Bridging the gap between analytic and synthetic geometry: Hilbert’s axiomatic approach.Eduardo N. Giovannini - 2016 - Synthese 193 (1):31-70.
    The paper outlines an interpretation of one of the most important and original contributions of David Hilbert’s monograph Foundations of Geometry , namely his internal arithmetization of geometry. It is claimed that Hilbert’s profound interest in the problem of the introduction of numbers into geometry responded to certain epistemological aims and methodological concerns that were fundamental to his early axiomatic investigations into the foundations of elementary geometry. In particular, it is shown that a central concern that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  47. Leo Corry. David Hilbert and the axiomatization of physics (1898–1918).Katherine Brading - 2008 - Philosophia Mathematica 16 (1):113-129.
    This book is a wonderful resource for historians and philosophers of mathematics and physics alike, not just for Hilbert's own work in physics, but also because Corry sets Hilbert in context, bringing out the people with whom Hilbert had contact, describing their work and possible links with Hilbert's work, and describing the activities going on around Hilbert. The historical thesis of this book is that Hilbert worked on a wide range of issues in physics for a period lasting more than (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  16
    Completeness of Pledger’s modal logics of one-sorted projective and elliptic planes.Rob Goldblatt - 2021 - Australasian Journal of Logic 18 (4).
    Ken Pledger devised a one-sorted approach to the incidence relation of plane geometries, using structures that also support models of propositional modal logic. He introduced a modal system 12g that is valid in one-sorted projective planes, proved that it has finitely many non-equivalent modalities, and identified all possible modality patterns of its extensions. One of these extensions 8f is valid in elliptic planes. These results were presented in his 1980 doctoral dissertation, which is reprinted in this issue of the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  23
    Kinetics of the phase separation in Cu–Al–Mn alloys and the influence on martensitic transformations.Jordi Marcos, Lluís Mañosa, Antoni Planes, Ricardo Romero & María Luján Castro - 2004 - Philosophical Magazine 84 (1):45-90.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  14
    Geometry of the astrolabe in the tenth century.Abgrall Philippe - 2000 - Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 10 (1):7-77.
    Many studies on the astrolabe were written during the period from the ninth to the eleventh century, but very few of them related to projection, i.e., to the geometrical transformation underlying the design of the instrument. Among those that did, the treatise entitled The Art of the Astrolabe, written in the tenth century by Abū Sahl al-Qūhī, represents a particulary important phase in the history of geometry. This work recently appeared in a critical edition with translation and commentary by (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 999