Results for 'Vladimir Gelman'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  13
    Politicheskiye diffusii v usloviyakh prostranstvenno-gibridnogo rejhima: institutsional noe stroitel stvo i vybory merov v gorodakh Rossii.Vladimir Gelman & T. V. Lankina - 2007 - Polis 6:86-109.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. Artificial Intelligence and Artificial Sociality: Sociological Interpretation and Interdisciplinary Approach.Vladimir Menshikov, Vera Komarova, Ieva Bolakova & Andrejs Radionovs - 2024 - Filosofija. Sociologija 35 (2).
    The subject of this study is the participants in artificial sociality (humans and artificial intelligence (AI) tools) and communication between them. The first section analyses (using Luhmann’s methodology) communication as the basis of sociality. The second section shows how AI tools became social technologies in the framework of artificial sociality. The third section describes experimental communication between authors and AI tools (the case of ChatGPT). For the first time in the Baltic countries, the authors examined sociological, humanitarian, natural and technological (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  2
    Za okrainoĭ mira bytii︠a︡ i soznanii︠a︡.Vladimir Zorev - 1996 - Vladivostok: Dalʹnauka.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  99
    Early word-learning entails reference, not merely associations.Sandra R. Waxman & Susan A. Gelman - 2009 - Trends in Cognitive Sciences 13 (6):258-263.
  5.  63
    How biological is essentialism.Susan A. Gelman & Lawrence A. Hirschfeld - 1999 - In D. Medin & S. Atran (eds.), Folkbiology. MIT Press. pp. 403--446.
  6.  33
    Categories and induction in young children.Susan A. Gelman & Ellen M. Markman - 1986 - Cognition 23 (3):183-209.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   219 citations  
  7.  53
    Insides and Essences: Early Understandings of the Non- Obvious.Susan A. Gelman & Henry M. Wellman - 1991 - Cognition 38 (3):213-244.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   180 citations  
  8. Blame, not ability, impacts moral “ought” judgments for impossible actions: Toward an empirical refutation of “ought” implies “can”.Vladimir Chituc, Paul Henne, Walter Sinnott-Armstrong & Felipe De Brigard - 2016 - Cognition 150 (C):20-25.
    Recently, psychologists have explored moral concepts including obligation, blame, and ability. While little empirical work has studied the relationships among these concepts, philosophers have widely assumed such a relationship in the principle that “ought” implies “can,” which states that if someone ought to do something, then they must be able to do it. The cognitive underpinnings of these concepts are tested in the three experiments reported here. In Experiment 1, most participants judge that an agent ought to keep a promise (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  9. CR Gallistel Rochel Gelman.Rochel Gelman - 2005 - In K. Holyoak & B. Morrison (eds.), The Cambridge Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning. Cambridge University Press. pp. 559.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  62
    First Principles Organize Attention to and Learning About Relevant Data: Number and the Animate‐Inanimate Distinction as Examples.Rochel Gelman - 1990 - Cognitive Science 14 (1):79-106.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   137 citations  
  11.  54
    Differences in preschoolers’ and adults’ use of generics about novel animals and artifacts: A window onto a conceptual divide.Amanda C. Brandone & Susan A. Gelman - 2009 - Cognition 110 (1):1-22.
    Children and adults commonly produce more generic noun phrases (e.g., birds fly) about animals than artifacts. This may reflect differences in participants’ generic knowledge about specific animals/artifacts (e.g., dogs/chairs), or it may reflect a more general distinction. To test this, the current experiments asked adults and preschoolers to generate properties about novel animals and artifacts (Experiment 1: real animals/artifacts; Experiments 2 and 3: matched pairs of maximally similar, novel animals/artifacts). Data demonstrate that even without prior knowledge about these items, the (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  12. Ty i Vy.Vladimir I︠A︡kovlevich Kantorovich - 1974
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13. The generative basis of natural number concepts.Alan M. Leslie, Rochel Gelman & C. R. Gallistel - 2008 - Trends in Cognitive Sciences 12 (6):213-218.
    Number concepts must support arithmetic inference. Using this principle, it can be argued that the integer concept of exactly ONE is a necessary part of the psychological foundations of number, as is the notion of the exact equality - that is, perfect substitutability. The inability to support reasoning involving exact equality is a shortcoming in current theories about the development of numerical reasoning. A simple innate basis for the natural number concepts can be proposed that embodies the arithmetic principle, supports (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  14.  12
    Materialism and empirio-criticism.Vladimir Ilʹich Lenin - 1952 - Moscow,: Progress Publishers. Edited by Fineberg, A. & [From Old Catalog].
  15.  23
    Structural Constraints on Cognitive Development: Introduction to a Special Issue of Cognitive Science.Rochel Gelman - 1990 - Cognitive Science 14 (1):3-9.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   64 citations  
  16.  39
    My Heart Made Me Do It: Children's Essentialist Beliefs About Heart Transplants.Meredith Meyer, Susan A. Gelman, Steven O. Roberts & Sarah-Jane Leslie - 2017 - Cognitive Science 41 (6):1694-1712.
    Psychological essentialism is a folk theory characterized by the belief that a causal internal essence or force gives rise to the common outward behaviors or attributes of a category's members. In two studies, we investigated whether 4- to 7-year-old children evidenced essentialist reasoning about heart transplants by asking them to predict whether trading hearts with an individual would cause them to take on the donor's attributes. Control conditions asked children to consider the effects of trading money with an individual. Results (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  17. First principles organize attention to relevant data and the acquisition of numerical and causal concepts.R. Gelman - 1990 - Cognitive Science 14:79-106.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  18.  21
    Preschoolers’ use of spatiotemporal history, appearance, and proper name in determining individual identity.Grant Gutheil, Susan A. Gelman, Eileen Klein, Katherine Michos & Kara Kelaita - 2008 - Cognition 107 (1):366-380.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  19.  65
    So It Is, So It Shall Be: Group Regularities License Children's Prescriptive Judgments.Steven O. Roberts, Susan A. Gelman & Arnold K. Ho - 2017 - Cognitive Science 41 (S3):576-600.
    When do descriptive regularities become prescriptive norms? We examined children's and adults' use of group regularities to make prescriptive judgments, employing novel groups that engaged in morally neutral behaviors. Participants were introduced to conforming or non-conforming individuals. Children negatively evaluated non-conformity, with negative evaluations declining with age. These effects were replicable across competitive and cooperative intergroup contexts and stemmed from reasoning about group regularities rather than reasoning about individual regularities. These data provide new insights into children's group concepts and have (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  20. Artifacts and Essentialism.Susan A. Gelman - 2013 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 4 (3):449-463.
    Psychological essentialism is an intuitive folk belief positing that certain categories have a non-obvious inner “essence” that gives rise to observable features. Although this belief most commonly characterizes natural kind categories, I argue that psychological essentialism can also be extended in important ways to artifact concepts. Specifically, concepts of individual artifacts include the non-obvious feature of object history, which is evident when making judgments regarding authenticity and ownership. Classic examples include famous works of art (e.g., the Mona Lisa is authentic (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  21. Philosophy and the practice of Bayesian statistics in the social sciences.Andrew Gelman & Cosma Rohilla Shalizi - 2012 - In Harold Kincaid (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Social Science. Oxford University Press.
  22.  25
    Bewitchment, Biology, or Both: The Co-Existence of Natural and Supernatural Explanatory Frameworks Across Development.Cristine H. Legare & Susan A. Gelman - 2008 - Cognitive Science 32 (4):607-642.
    Three studies examined the co-existence of natural and supernatural explanations for illness and disease transmission, from a developmental perspective. The participants (5-, 7-, 11-, and 15-year-olds and adults; N = 366) were drawn from 2 Sesotho-speaking South African communities, where Western biomedical and traditional healing frameworks were both available. Results indicated that, although biological explanations for illness were endorsed at high levels, witchcraft was also often endorsed. More important, bewitchment explanations were neither the result of ignorance nor replaced by biological (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  23.  82
    Quantified Statements are Recalled as Generics: Evidence from Preschool Children and Adults.Sarah-Jane Leslie & Susan Gelman - 2012 - Cognitive Psychology 64 (186):214.
  24. Role of learning in cognitive development.Rochel Gelman & Joan Lucariello - 2002 - In J. Wixted & H. Pashler (eds.), Stevens' Handbook of Experimental Psychology. Wiley.
  25.  19
    The theory of space, time and gravitation.Vladimir Aleksandrovich Fok - 1959 - New York,: Macmillan.
  26.  22
    Shape and representational status in children's early naming.Susan A. Gelman & Karen S. Ebeling - 1998 - Cognition 66 (2):B35-B47.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  27.  54
    Children's Developing Intuitions About the Truth Conditions and Implications of Novel Generics Versus Quantified Statements.Amanda C. Brandone, Susan A. Gelman & Jenna Hedglen - 2015 - Cognitive Science 39 (4):711-738.
    Generic statements express generalizations about categories and present a unique semantic profile that is distinct from quantified statements. This paper reports two studies examining the development of children's intuitions about the semantics of generics and how they differ from statements quantified by all, most, and some. Results reveal that, like adults, preschoolers recognize that generics have flexible truth conditions and are capable of representing a wide range of prevalence levels; and interpret novel generics as having near-universal prevalence implications. Results further (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  28.  37
    Causal status effect in children's categorization.Woo-Kyoung Ahn, Susan A. Gelman, Jennifer A. Amsterlaw, Jill Hohenstein & Charles W. Kalish - 2000 - Cognition 76 (2):B35-B43.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  29.  28
    Questions for future research.Rochel Gelman & Brian Butterworth - 2005 - Trends in Cognitive Sciences 9 (1):6-10.
  30.  20
    Different kinds of concepts and different kinds of words: What words do for human cognition.Sandra Waxman & Susan Gelman - 2010 - In Denis Mareschal, Paul Quinn & Stephen E. G. Lea (eds.), The Making of Human Concepts. Oxford University Press. pp. 101--130.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  31.  85
    Who am I? The role of moral beliefs in children's and adults' understanding of identity.Larisa Heiphetz, Nina Strohminger, Susan Gelman & Liane L. Young - 2018 - Journal of Experimental Social Psychology:210-219.
    Adults report that moral characteristics—particularly widely shared moral beliefs—are central to identity. This perception appears driven by the view that changes to widely shared moral beliefs would alter friendships and that this change in social relationships would, in turn, alter an individual's personal identity. Because reasoning about identity changes substantially during adolescence, the current work tested pre- and post-adolescents to reveal the role that such changes could play in moral cognition. Experiment 1 showed that 8- to 10-year-olds, like adults, judged (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  32.  44
    A cross-linguistic comparison of generic noun phrases in English and Mandarin.Susan A. Gelman & Twila Tardif - 1998 - Cognition 66 (3):215-248.
    Generic noun phrases (e.g. 'bats live in caves') provide a window onto human concepts. They refer to categories as 'kinds rather than as sets of individuals. Although kind concepts are often assumed to be universal, generic expression varies considerably across languages. For example, marking of generics is less obligatory and overt in Mandarin than in English. How do universal conceptual biases interact with language-specific differences in how generics are conveyed? In three studies, we examined adults' generics in English and Mandarin (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  33.  38
    Preschoolers' counting: Principles before skill.Rochel Gelman & Elizabeth Meck - 1983 - Cognition 13 (3):343-359.
  34. Scientific and Folk Theories of Viral Transmission: A Comparison of COVID-19 and the Common Cold.Danielle Labotka & Susan A. Gelman - 2022 - Frontiers in Psychology 13.
    Disease transmission is a fruitful domain in which to examine how scientific and folk theories interrelate, given laypeople’s access to multiple sources of information to explain events of personal significance. The current paper reports an in-depth survey of U.S. adults’ causal reasoning about two viral illnesses: a novel, deadly disease that has massively disrupted everyone’s lives, and a familiar, innocuous disease that has essentially no serious consequences. Participants received a series of closed-ended and open-ended questions probing their reasoning about disease (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35. Can You Lie Without Intending to Deceive?Vladimir Krstić - 2019 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 100 (2):642–660.
    This article defends the view that liars need not intend to deceive. I present common objections to this view in detail and then propose a case of a liar who can lie but who cannot deceive in any relevant sense. I then modify this case to get a situation in which this person lies intending to tell his hearer the truth and he does this by way of getting the hearer to recognize his intention to tell the truth by lying. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  36. Differences in the Evaluation of Generic Statements About Human and Non‐Human Categories.Arber Tasimi, Susan Gelman, Andrei Cimpian & Joshua Knobe - 2017 - Cognitive Science 41 (7):1934-1957.
    Generic statements express generalizations about categories. Current theories suggest that people should be especially inclined to accept generics that involve threatening information. However, previous tests of this claim have focused on generics about non-human categories, which raises the question of whether this effect applies as readily to human categories. In Experiment 1, adults were more likely to accept generics involving a threatening property for artifacts, but this negativity bias did not also apply to human categories. Experiment 2 examined an alternative (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  37.  24
    A cross-linguistic comparison of generic noun phrases in English and Mandarin.S. A. Gelman & T. Z. Tardif - 1998 - Cognition 66 (3):215-248.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  38.  26
    Die ersten Fichteaner über die Schwierigkeiten des Verständnisses der Wissenschaftslehre.Vladimir Alekseevic Abaschnik - 2006 - Fichte-Studien 30:105-113.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  61
    On non-wellfounded iterations of the perfect set forcing.Vladimir Kanovei - 1999 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 64 (2):551-574.
    We prove that if I is a partially ordered set in a countable transitive model M of ZFC then M can be extended by a generic sequence of reals a i , i ∈ I, such that ℵ M 1 is preserved and every a i is Sacks generic over $\mathfrak{M}[\langle \mathbf{a}_j: j . The structure of the degrees of M-constructibility of reals in the extension is investigated. As applications of the methods involved, we define a cardinal invariant to distinguish (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  40. Bald-Faced Lies, Blushing, and Noses that Grow: An Experimental Analysis.Vladimir Krstić & Alexander Wiegmann - 2022 - Erkenntnis 89 (2):479-502.
    We conducted two experiments to determine whether common folk think that so-called _tell-tale sign_ bald-faced lies are intended to deceive—since they have not been tested before. These lies involve tell-tale signs (e.g. blushing) that show that the speaker is lying. Our study was designed to avoid problems earlier studies raise (these studies focus on a kind of bald-faced lie in which supposedly everyone knows that what the speaker says is false). Our main hypothesis was that the participants will think that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  41. Lying: revisiting the ‘intending to deceive’ condition.Vladimir Krstić - 2023 - Analysis.
    This paper refines the received analysis of deceptive lies. This is done by assessing some cases of lies that are supposedly not intended to deceive and by arguing that they actually involve sophisticated strategies of intentional deception. These lies, that is, merely seem not to be intended to deceive and this is because our received analysis of deceptive lies is insufficiently sophisticated. We need to add these strategies to our analysis of deceptive lying. The argument ends by presenting this refined (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  42. Beyond syntax: The influence of conversational constraints on speech modifications.Marilyn Shatz & Rochelle Gelman - 1977 - In Catherine E. Snow & Charles A. Ferguson (eds.), Talking to Children. Cambridge University Press. pp. 189--198.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  24
    The Importance of Clarifying Evolutionary Terminology Across Disciplines and in the Classroom: A Reply to Kampourakis.Elizabeth A. Ware & Susan A. Gelman - 2015 - Cognitive Science 39 (4):838-841.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  13
    Don't characterize replications as successes or failures.Andrew Gelman - 2018 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 41.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  45.  7
    Mismatch between scientific theories and statistical models.Andrew Gelman - 2022 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 45.
    Yarkoni recommends that psychology researchers should take care to align their statistical models to the verbal theories they are studying and testing. This principle applies not just to qualitative theories in psychology but also to more quantitative sciences: there, too, mismatch between open-ended theories and specific statistical models have led to confusion.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46.  61
    Moral conformity and its philosophical lessons.Vladimir Chituc & Walter Sinnott-Armstrong - 2020 - Philosophical Psychology 33 (2):262-282.
    ABSTRACTThe psychological and philosophical literature exploring the role of social influence in moral judgments suggests that conformity in moral judgments is common and, in many cases, seems to b...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47. On the nature of indifferent lies, a reply to Rutschmann and Wiegmann.Vladimir Krstić - 2020 - Philosophical Psychology 33 (5):757-771.
    In their paper published in 2017 in Philosophical Psychology, Ronja Rutschmann and Alex Wiegmann introduce a novel kind of lies, the indifferent lies. According to them, these lies are not intended to deceive simply because the liars do not care whether their audience is going to believe them or not. It seems as if indifferent lies avoid the objections raised against other kinds of lies supposedly not intended to deceive. I argue that this is not correct. Indifferent lies, too, are (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  48.  61
    Tracking the Actions and Possessions of Agents.Susan A. Gelman, Nicholaus S. Noles & Sarah Stilwell - 2014 - Topics in Cognitive Science 6 (4):599-614.
    We propose that there is a powerful human disposition to track the actions and possessions of agents. In two experiments, 3-year-olds and adults viewed sets of objects, learned a new fact about one of the objects in each set , and were queried about either the taught fact or an unrelated dimension immediately after a spatiotemporal transformation, and after a delay. Adults uniformly tracked object identity under all conditions, whereas children tracked identity more when taught ownership versus labeling information, and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  49. A Functional Analysis of Human Deception.Vladimir Krstić - forthcoming - Journal of the American Philosophical Association:1-19.
    A satisfactory analysis of human deception must rule out cases where it is a mistake or an accident that person B was misled by person A's behavior. Therefore, most scholars think that deceivers must intend to deceive. This article argues that there is a better solution: rather than appealing to the deceiver's intentions, we should appeal to the function of their behavior. After all, animals and plants engage in deception, and most of them are not capable of forming intentions. Accordingly, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50.  28
    Young children’s preference for unique owned objects.Susan A. Gelman & Natalie S. Davidson - 2016 - Cognition 155 (C):146-154.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000