Results for 'Rigorism'

984 found
Order:
  1.  38
    Rigor and Structure.John P. Burgess - 2015 - Oxford, England: Oxford University Press UK.
    While we are commonly told that the distinctive method of mathematics is rigorous proof, and that the special topic of mathematics is abstract structure, there has been no agreement among mathematicians, logicians, or philosophers as to just what either of these assertions means. John P. Burgess clarifies the nature of mathematical rigor and of mathematical structure, and above all of the relation between the two, taking into account some of the latest developments in mathematics, including the rise of experimental mathematics (...)
  2.  69
    Mathematical rigor and proof.Yacin Hamami - 2022 - Review of Symbolic Logic 15 (2):409-449.
    Mathematical proof is the primary form of justification for mathematical knowledge, but in order to count as a proper justification for a piece of mathematical knowl- edge, a mathematical proof must be rigorous. What does it mean then for a mathematical proof to be rigorous? According to what I shall call the standard view, a mathematical proof is rigorous if and only if it can be routinely translated into a formal proof. The standard view is almost an orthodoxy among contemporary (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  3. Reconciling Rigor and Intuition.Silvia De Toffoli - 2020 - Erkenntnis 86 (6):1783-1802.
    Criteria of acceptability for mathematical proofs are field-dependent. In topology, though not in most other domains, it is sometimes acceptable to appeal to visual intuition to support inferential steps. In previous work :829–842, 2014; Lolli, Panza, Venturi From logic to practice, Springer, Berlin, 2015; Larvor Mathematical cultures, Springer, Berlin, 2016) my co-author and I aimed at spelling out how topological proofs work on their own terms, without appealing to formal proofs which might be associated with them. In this article, I (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  4. Mathematical rigor--who needs it?Philip Kitcher - 1981 - Noûs 15 (4):469-493.
  5. What is Mathematical Rigor?John Burgess & Silvia De Toffoli - 2022 - Aphex 25:1-17.
    Rigorous proof is supposed to guarantee that the premises invoked imply the conclusion reached, and the problem of rigor may be described as that of bringing together the perspectives of formal logic and mathematical practice on how this is to be achieved. This problem has recently raised a lot of discussion among philosophers of mathematics. We survey some possible solutions and argue that failure to understand its terms properly has led to misunderstandings in the literature.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  6. A rigorous proof of determinism derived from the special theory of relativity.C. W. Rietdijk - 1966 - Philosophy of Science 33 (4):341-344.
    A proof is given that there does not exist an event, that is not already in the past for some possible distant observer at the (our) moment that the latter is "now" for us. Such event is as "legally" past for that distant observer as is the moment five minutes ago on the sun for us (irrespective of the circumstance that the light of the sun cannot reach us in a period of five minutes). Only an extreme positivism: "that which (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   90 citations  
  7. On rigorous definitions.Nuel Belnap - 1993 - Philosophical Studies 72 (2-3):115 - 146.
  8. A rigorous analytic solution of nonlinear differential equation of the poisson-bolitzmann type.S. N. Bagchi & G. P. Das - 1965 - In Karl W. Linsenmann (ed.), Proceedings. St. Louis, Lutheran Academy for Scholarship. pp. 29--28.
  9.  51
    Rigor; or, stupid uselessness.Geoffrey Bennington - 2012 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 50 (s1):20-38.
    In his seminars on the death penalty, Derrida consistently describes Kant's arguments in favor of capital punishment as “rigorous” and explicitly relates that rigor to the mechanisms of execution and the subsequent rigor mortis of the corpse. ‘Rigor’ has also often been a contested term in descriptions of deconstruction: different commentators have either deplored or celebrated the presence or the absence of rigor in Derrida's work. Derrida himself uses the term a good deal throughout his career, usually in a positive (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  10.  69
    Mathematical rigor, proof gap and the validity of mathematical inference.Yacin Hamami - 2014 - Philosophia Scientiae 18 (1):7-26.
    Mathematical rigor is commonly formulated by mathematicians and philosophers using the notion of proof gap: a mathematical proof is rig­orous when there is no gaps in the mathematical reasoning of the proof. Any philosophical approach to mathematical rigor along this line requires then an account of what a proof gap is. However, the notion of proof gap makes sense only relatively to a given conception of valid mathematical reasoning, i.e., to a given conception of the validity of mathematical inference. A (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11.  9
    Rigor mortis: how sloppy science creates worthless cures, crushes hope, and wastes billions.Richard F. Harris - 2017 - New York: Basic Books.
    American taxpayers spend $30 billion annually funding biomedical research. By some estimates, half of the results from these studies can't be replicated elsewhere-the science is simply wrong. Often, research institutes and academia emphasize publishing results over getting the right answers, incentivizing poor experimental design, improper methods, and sloppy statistics. Bad science doesn't just hold back medical progress, it can sign the equivalent of a death sentence. How are those with breast cancer helped when the cell on which 900 papers are (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  12.  11
    Rigorism of Truth: "Moses the Egyptian" and Other Writings on Freud and Arendt.Hans Blumenberg - 2017 - Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Edited by Ahlrich Meyer & Joe Paul Kroll.
    In "Moses the Egyptian"--the centerpiece of Rigorism of Truth, the German philosopher Hans Blumenberg addresses two defining figures in the intellectual history of the twentieth century: Sigmund Freud and Hannah Arendt. Unpublished during his lifetime, this essay analyzes Freud's Moses and Monotheism and Arendt's Eichmann in Jerusalem, and discovers in both a principled rigidity that turns into recklessness because it is blind to the politics of the unknown. Offering striking insights into the importance of myth in politics and the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13.  18
    O rigor científico: princípios elementares extraídos de Aristóteles no interesse da teologia.Clodovis Boff - 2015 - Horizonte 13 (39):1559-1579.
    Against the modern tendency to considerate just the formal-empirical knowledge as Science, and this one mathematized as much as possible, here many declarations of Aristotle are raised in order to show that the scientific rigour is not univocal but analogic: it is determined according to the nature of the object to be known. This is a so elementary epistemological rule that not knowing it is understood by that philosopher as apaideusia, i.e., lack of basic education in the knowledge sphere in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. Rigorous results, cross-model justification, and the transfer of empirical warrant: the case of many-body models in physics.Axel Gelfert - 2009 - Synthese 169 (3):497-519.
    This paper argues that a successful philosophical analysis of models and simulations must accommodate an account of mathematically rigorous results. Such rigorous results may be thought of as genuinely model-specific contributions, which can neither be deduced from fundamental theory nor inferred from empirical data. Rigorous results provide new indirect ways of assessing the success of models and simulations and are crucial to understanding the connections between different models. This is most obvious in cases where rigorous results map different models on (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  15.  11
    Rigor and the Context-Dependence of Diagrams: The Case of Euler Diagrams.David Waszek - 2018 - In Peter Chapman, Gem Stapleton, Amirouche Moktefi, Sarah Perez-Kriz & Francesco Bellucci (eds.), Diagrammatic Representation and Inference. Cham: Springer. pp. 382-389.
    Euler famously used diagrams to illustrate syllogisms in his Lettres à une princesse d’Allemagne [1]. His diagrams are usually seen as suffering from a fatal “ambiguity problem” [11]: as soon as they involve intersecting circles, which are required for the representation of existential statements, it becomes unclear what exactly may be read off from them, and as Hammer & Shin conclusively showed, any set of reading conventions can lead to erroneous conclusions. I claim that Euler diagrams can, however, be used (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. Rigorous information-theoretic derivation of quantum-statistical thermodynamics. II.William Band & James L. Park - 1977 - Foundations of Physics 7 (9-10):705-721.
    Part I of the present work outlined the rigorous application of information theory to a quantum mechanical system in a thermodynamic equilibrium state. The general formula developed there for the best-guess density operator $\hat \rho$ was indeterminate because it involved in an essential way an unspecified prior probability distribution over the continuumD H of strong equilibrium density operators. In Part II mathematical evaluation of $\hat \rho$ is completed after an epistemological analysis which leads first to the discretization ofD H and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  8
    Rigorous Purposes of Analysis in Greek Geometry.Viktor Blåsjö - 2021 - Philosophia Scientiae 25:55-80.
    Analyses in Greek geometry are traditionally seen as heuristic devices. However, many occurrences of analysis in formal treatises are difficult to justify in such terms. I show that Greek analysies of geometrics can also serve formal mathematical purposes, which are arguably incomplete without which their associated syntheses are arguably incomplete. Firstly, when the solution of a problem is preceded by an analysis, the analysis latter proves rigorously that there are no other solutions to the problem than those offered in the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  49
    Rigor mortis: A response to Nilsson's 'logic and artificial intelligence'.Lawrence Birnbaum - 1991 - Artificial Intelligence 47 (1-3):57-78.
  19. Kantian rigorism and mitigating circumstances.Tamar Schapiro - 2006 - Ethics 117 (1):32–57.
    A task of any moral theory is to account for both the rigidity and the flexibility of moral rules. Utilitarianism faces the problem of building rigidity into a framework that tends towards objectionable flexibility. Kantianism faces the problem of building flexibility into a framework that tends towards objectionable rigidity. I offer an argument on this front on behalf of Kantians. I show how Kantians can maintain that actions are right and wrong "in themselves," while still maintaining that such actions can (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  20.  27
    Rigor and Clarity: Foundations of Mathematics in France and England, 1800–1840.Joan L. Richards - 1991 - Science in Context 4 (2):297-319.
    The ArgumentIt has long been apparent that in the nineteenth century, mathematics in France and England developed along different lines. The differences, which might well be labelled stylistic, are most easy to see on the foundational level. At first this may seem surprising because it is such a fundamental area, but, upon reflection, it is to be expected. Ultimately discussions about the foundations of mathematics turn on views about what mathematics is, and this is a question which is answered by (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  21. All science as rigorous science: the principle of constructive mathematizability of any theory.Vasil Penchev - 2020 - Logic and Philosophy of Mathematics eJournal 12 (12):1-15.
    A principle, according to which any scientific theory can be mathematized, is investigated. Social science, liberal arts, history, and philosophy are meant first of all. That kind of theory is presupposed to be a consistent text, which can be exhaustedly represented by a certain mathematical structure constructively. In thus used, the term “theory” includes all hypotheses as yet unconfirmed as already rejected. The investigation of the sketch of a possible proof of the principle demonstrates that it should be accepted rather (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  28
    Rigorous Reasoning.Peter Cave - 1994 - Philosophy Now 9:14-17.
  23.  8
    Rigor and formalization.Pawel Pawlowski & Karim Zahidi - 2024 - Synthese 203 (3):1-18.
    This paper critically examines and evaluates Yacin Hamami’s reconstruction of the standard view of mathematical rigor. We will argue that the reconstruction offered by Hamami is premised on a strong and controversial epistemological thesis and a strong and controversial thesis in the philosophy of mind. Secondly, we will argue that Hamami’s reconstruction of the standard view robs it of its original philosophical rationale, i.e. making sense of the notion of rigor in mathematical practice.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  25
    A rigorous approach for testing the constructionist hypotheses of brain function.Gopikrishna Deshpande, K. Sathian, Xiaoping Hu & Joseph A. Buckhalt - 2012 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 35 (3):148-149.
    Although the target article provides strong evidence against the locationist view, evidence for the constructionist view is inconclusive, because co-activation of brain regions does not necessarily imply connectivity between them. We propose a rigorous approach wherein connectivity between co-activated regions is first modeled using exploratory Granger causality, and then confirmed using dynamic causal modeling or Bayesian modeling.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. Mathematical Rigor in Physics: Putting Exact Results in Their Place.Axel Gelfert - 2005 - Philosophy of Science 72 (5):723-738.
    The present paper examines the role of exact results in the theory of many‐body physics, and specifically the example of the Mermin‐Wagner theorem, a rigorous result concerning the absence of phase transitions in low‐dimensional systems. While the theorem has been shown to hold for a wide range of many‐body models, it is frequently ‘violated’ by results derived from the same models using numerical techniques. This raises the question of how scientists regulate their theoretical commitments in such cases, given that the (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  26.  12
    The Rigor of a Certain Inhumanity: Toward a Wider Suffrage.John Llewelyn - 2012 - Indiana University Press.
    The Rigor of a Certain Inhumanity is a rich and passionate, playful and perceptive work of philosophical analysis.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27. Objectivity and Rigor in Classical Italian Algebraic Geometry.Silvia De Toffoli & Claudio Fontanari - 2022 - Noesis 38:195-212.
    The classification of algebraic surfaces by the Italian School of algebraic geometry is universally recognized as a breakthrough in 20th-century mathematics. The methods by which it was achieved do not, however, meet the modern standard of rigor and therefore appear dubious from a contemporary viewpoint. In this article, we offer a glimpse into the mathematical practice of the three leading exponents of the Italian School of algebraic geometry: Castelnuovo, Enriques, and Severi. We then bring into focus their distinctive conception of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28.  93
    Is mathematical rigor necessary in physics?Kevin Davey - 2003 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 54 (3):439-463.
    Many arguments found in the physics literature involve concepts that are not well-defined by the usual standards of mathematics. I argue that physicists are entitled to employ such concepts without rigorously defining them so long as they restrict the sorts of mathematical arguments in which these concepts are involved. Restrictions of this sort allow the physicist to ignore calculations involving these concepts that might lead to contradictory results. I argue that such restrictions need not be ad hoc, but can sometimes (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  29.  62
    Rigorous proof and the history of mathematics: Comments on Crowe.Douglas Jesseph - 1990 - Synthese 83 (3):449 - 453.
    Duhem's portrayal of the history of mathematics as manifesting calm and regular development is traced to his conception of mathematical rigor as an essentially static concept. This account is undermined by citing controversies over rigorous demonstration from the eighteenth and twentieth centuries.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30. Rigorism and perfection, notes on the ethics of thomassin, Louis.D. Bosco - 1988 - Rivista di Filosofia Neo-Scolastica 80 (1):22-62.
  31. A Rigorous Analysis of the Clauser–Horne–Shimony–Holt Inequality Experiment When Trials Need Not be Independent.Peter Bierhorst - 2014 - Foundations of Physics 44 (7):736-761.
    The Clauser–Horne–Shimony–Holt (CHSH) inequality is a constraint that local hidden variable theories must obey. Quantum Mechanics predicts a violation of this inequality in certain experimental settings. Treatments of this subject frequently make simplifying assumptions about the probability spaces available to a local hidden variable theory, such as assuming the state of the system is a discrete or absolutely continuous random variable, or assuming that repeated experimental trials are independent and identically distributed. In this paper, we do two things: first, show (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. Rigor in Research, Honesty and Values.M. Hohl - 2016 - Constructivist Foundations 11 (3):585-586.
    Open peer commentary on the article “Design Research as a Variety of Second-Order Cybernetic Practice” by Ben Sweeting. Upshot: I reflect on the theme of honesty in research and discuss the adjoining requirements of rigor from an academic perspective. Central to my discussion is Glanville’s assertion that what researchers - from either science or design - presented was not what they actually thought and did.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  28
    Are rigorous evolutionary histories of human mating possible?Harmon R. Holcomb - 2000 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 23 (4):606-607.
    Critics of evolutionary psychology object that it is not rigorous science compared to other evolutionary science. Advocates reply that it is rigorous science, and that the critics are uninformed. Still, informed people having opposing preconceptions of what counts as rigor may reach opposing evaluative conclusions. I shall clarify the very idea of rigorous evolutionary histories in relation to the basic objection that “evolution without history” is not rigorous.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34.  16
    The rigor of angels: Borges, Heisenberg, Kant, and the ultimate nature of reality.William Egginton - 2023 - New York: Pantheon Books.
    A monumental and riveting account of how a poet, a physicist, and a philosopher pursued truth to the very limits of human apprehension and revealed the fundamental nature of our place in the universe Spiraling in the wreckage of a failed love affair, Argentine poet Jorge Luis Borges channeled his devastation into his work, reassessing the slippery nature of our own identities and the way we perceive reality, ultimately securing his place in the literary pantheon. Doggedly fighting against the scientific (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  27
    Republican Rigorism: Hegelian Views of Emancipation in 1848.Douglas Moggach - 2003 - The European Legacy 8 (4):441-457.
    This paper examines whether Bruno Bauer's critical assessment of Jewish emancipation in Prussia is consistent with his other republican writings in the 1840s. It argues that Bauer's political position is a form of republican rigorism, according to which human emancipation requires identification with universal interests, and not the defence of particular identities. Rigorism involves the elimination of internal as well as external heteronomous influences, and implies shifting the boundaries between the juridical and the moral realms as defined by (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  13
    A Rigorous Set Theoretical Foundation of the Structuralist Approach.H. Peter - 1996 - In Wolfgang Balzer & Carles Ulises Moulines (eds.), Structuralist theory of science: focal issues, new results. New York: Walter de Gruyter. pp. 6--233.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Mathematical rigor in physics.Mark Steiner - 1992 - In Michael Detlefsen (ed.), Proof and Knowledge in Mathematics. Routledge. pp. 158.
  38.  4
    Rigorism and the 'New Kant'.Robert B. Pippin - 2001 - In Volker Gerhardt, Rolf-Peter Horstmann & Ralph Schumacher (eds.), Kant Und Die Berliner Aufklärung: Akten des Ix Internationalen Kant-Kongresses. Walter de Gruyter. pp. 313-326.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  39.  20
    Imitation of Rigor: An Alternative History of Analytic Philosophy.Mark Wilson - 2021 - New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
    "Mark Wilson aims to reconnect analytic philosophy with the evolving practicalities within science from which many of its grander concerns originally sprang. He offers an alternative history of how the subject might have developed had the insights of its philosopher/scientist forebears not been cast aside in the vain pursuit of 'ersatz rigor'"--.
    No categories
  40. Rigor, Reproof and Bolzano's Critical Program.Michael Detlefsen - 2010 - In Pierre Edouard Bour, Manuel Rebuschi & Laurent Rollet (eds.), Construction: A Festschrift for Gerhard Heinzmann. Cambridge: King's College Publications. pp. 171-184.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  17
    Rigorism and the 'New Kant'.Robert B. Pippin - 2001 - In Ralph Schumacher, Rolf-Peter Horstmann & Volker Gerhardt (eds.), Kant Und Die Berliner Aufklärung: Akten des Ix. Internationalen Kant-Kongresses. Bd. I: Hauptvorträge. Bd. Ii: Sektionen I-V. Bd. Iii: Sektionen Vi-X: Bd. Iv: Sektionen Xi-Xiv. Bd. V: Sektionen Xv-Xviii. New York: De Gruyter. pp. 313-326.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  42.  72
    Open texture, rigor, and proof.Benjamin Zayton - 2022 - Synthese 200 (4):1-20.
    Open texture is a kind of semantic indeterminacy first systematically studied by Waismann. In this paper, extant definitions of open texture will be compared and contrasted, with a view towards the consequences of open-textured concepts in mathematics. It has been suggested that these would threaten the traditional virtues of proof, primarily the certainty bestowed by proof-possession, and this suggestion will be critically investigated using recent work on informal proof. It will be argued that informal proofs have virtues that mitigate the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43. Rigor e Aquisição de Conhecimento Moral em Aristóteles.Mariane Oliveira & J. Alexandre Durry Guerzoni - 2015 - Prometheus 8 (18):149-161.
    No livro I da Ethica Eudemia, Aristóteles dedica um capítulo a considerações acerca de seu método. No entanto, analisando passagens de outros tratados do autor, é possível concluir que há algo comum que perpassa as diversas considerações acerca de seu método, a saber: que o ponto de partida de toda investigação é dado pelo que é mais cognoscível a nós, e todo o procedimento de investigação visa chegar ao que é mais cognoscível em si mesmo – o conhecimento estrito do (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. Rigorous information-theoretic derivation of quantum-statistical thermodynamics. I.James L. Park & William Band - 1977 - Foundations of Physics 7 (3-4):233-244.
    In previous publications we have criticized the usual application of information theory to quantal situations and proposed a new version of information-theoretic quantum statistics. This paper is the first in a two-part series in which our new approach is applied to the fundamental problem of thermodynamic equilibrium. Part I deals in particular with informational definitions of equilibrium and the identification of thermodynamic analogs in our modified quantum statistics formalism.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  45. Philosophy as Rigorous Science.Edmund Husserl - 2002 - New Yearbook for Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy 2:249-295.
  46.  61
    Frege and the rigorization of analysis.William Demopoulos - 1994 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 23 (3):225 - 245.
    This paper has three goals: (i) to show that the foundational program begun in the Begriffsschroft, and carried forward in the Grundlagen, represented Frege's attempt to establish the autonomy of arithmetic from geometry and kinematics; the cogency and coherence of 'intuitive' reasoning were not in question. (ii) To place Frege's logicism in the context of the nineteenth century tradition in mathematical analysis, and, in particular, to show how the modern concept of a function made it possible for Frege to pursue (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  47.  10
    Mathematical Rigor and the Origin of the Exhaustion Method.Theokritos Kouremenos - 1997 - Centaurus 39 (3):230-252.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48.  6
    The psychology of rigorous humanism.Joseph Frank Rychlak - 1987 - New York: New York University Press.
    In this second edition, Joseph Rychlak has retained his analysis of the philosophical antecedents of psychology and, at the same time, has considerably revised more complicated material illustration rigorous humanism to make the book more accessible for students. Rychlak here offers an analysis of the philosophical traditions underlying the social sciences and shows how functionalism came to dominate the modern science of psychology in America.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  49.  16
    Rigorous disease management evaluation.Melinda Beeuwkes Buntin - 2006 - Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 12 (2):121-123.
  50.  10
    Rigor or rhetoric: philosopher and public in dialogue.Deven Burks - 2018 - Perspectives 8 (1):4-13.
    Leiter (2016) charges public philosophy with being “neoliberal”. To understand that charge better, I define, in §1, three versions of public philosophy which might be concerned and two pictures of its practice targeted by Leiter. I also compare two deliberative sites wherein those pictures may play out. In §2, I sketch how Leiter’s two paradoxes for “neoliberal” public philosophy lead to a revised public philosophy. §3 questions the paradoxes’ empirical grounding and scope. Lastly, in §4, I assume Leiter’s picture and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 984