Results for 'Leslie Henderson'

991 found
Order:
  1.  6
    On the nature of the facilitation of visual comparisons by lexical membership.Leslie Henderson & Jackie Chard - 1976 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 7 (5):432-434.
  2.  24
    Oral reading: Duel but not rout.Leslie Henderson - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):713-714.
  3. Bayesianism and Inference to the Best Explanation.Leah Henderson - 2014 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 65 (4):687-715.
    Two of the most influential theories about scientific inference are inference to the best explanation and Bayesianism. How are they related? Bas van Fraassen has claimed that IBE and Bayesianism are incompatible rival theories, as any probabilistic version of IBE would violate Bayesian conditionalization. In response, several authors have defended the view that IBE is compatible with Bayesian updating. They claim that the explanatory considerations in IBE are taken into account by the Bayesian because the Bayesian either does or should (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  4.  6
    Constructing Low-Order Discriminant Neural Networks Using Statistical Feature Selection.E. K. Henderson & T. R. Martinez - 2007 - Journal of Intelligent Systems 16 (1):27-56.
  5.  86
    Are Epistemic Norms Fundamentally Social Norms?David Henderson - 2020 - Episteme 17 (3):281-300.
    People develop and deploy epistemic norms – normative sensibilities in light of which they regulate both their individual and community epistemic practice. There is a similarity to folk's epistemic normative sensibilities – and it is by virtue of this that folk commonly can rely on each other, and even work jointly to produce systems of true beliefs – a kind of epistemic common good. Agents not only regulate their belief forming practices in light of these sensitivities, but they make clear (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  6.  49
    Was Jesus God?Leslie Houlden - 2010 - Religious Studies 46 (2):265-269.
    The orderliness of the universe and the existence of human beings already provides some reason for believing that there is a God - as argued in Richard Swinburne's earlier book Is There a God? Swinburne now claims that it is probable that the main Christian doctrines about the nature of God and his actions in the world are true. In virtue of his omnipotence and perfect goodness, God must be a Trinity, live a human life in order to share our (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  7.  5
    Arc and path consistency revisited.Roger Mohr & Thomas C. Henderson - 1986 - Artificial Intelligence 28 (2):225-233.
  8.  56
    A Refined Account of the "Epistemic Game": Epistemic Norms, Temptations, and Epistemic Coorperation.David Henderson & Peter Graham - 2017 - American Philosophical Quarterly 54 (4):383-396.
    In "Epistemic Norms and the 'Epistemic Game' They Regulate", we advance a general case for the idea that epistemic norms regulating the production of beliefs might usefully be understood as social norms. There, we drew on the influential account of social norms developed by Cristina Bicchieri, and we managed to give a crude recognizable picture of important elements of what are recognizable as central epistemic norms. Here, we consider much needed elaboration, suggesting models that help one think about epistemic communities (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  9.  20
    What’s the Point of Knowledge?David Henderson - 2021 - Analysis 81 (1):87-100.
    Michael Hannon advocates an epistemological methodology – tracing its roots, articulating refinements, distinguishing it from alternative methodologies and giving reasons for preferring it to the alternatives. He also advances an account of knowledge as a compelling application of this methodology. As reflected in his title, both projects are pivotal to the work and intimately related. In its general outlines, I judge that that case for the method should be taken to heart – although details could stand for further attention – (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10. Winch and the Constraints on Interpretation: Versions of the Principle of Charity.David K. Henderson - 2010 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 25 (2):153-173.
  11. Nonconciliation in Peer Disagreement: Its Phenomenology and Its Rationality.David Henderson, Terry Horgan, Matjaz Potrc & Hannah Tierney - 2017 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 94 (1-2):194-225.
    The authors argue in favor of the “nonconciliation” (or “steadfast”) position concerning the problem of peer disagreement. Throughout the paper they place heavy emphasis on matters of phenomenology—on how things seem epistemically with respect to the net import of one’s available evidence vis-à-vis the disputed claim p, and on how such phenomenology is affected by the awareness that an interlocutor whom one initially regards as an epistemic peer disagrees with oneself about p. Central to the argument is a nested goal/sub-goal (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  12.  8
    Is There Only One Correct System of Modal Logic?E. J. Lemmon & G. P. Henderson - 1959 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 33 (1):23-56.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  13. What Is a Priori and What Is It Good For?David Henderson - 2000 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 38 (S1):51-86.
    The doctrine is familiar. In a sentence, a priori truths are those that are knowable on the basis of reflection alone (independent of experience) by anyone who has acquired the relevant concepts. This expresses the classical conception of the a priori. Of course, there are those who despair of finding any truths that fully meet these demands. Some of the doubters are convinced, however, that the demands, are somewhat inflated by an epistemological tradition that was nevertheless on to something of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  14.  26
    Valuing the Stars.David Henderson - 2010 - Environmental Philosophy 7 (1):17-26.
    The night sky has been radically altered by light pollution, artificially produced light that obscures the stars. The effects and costs of this are diverse and poorly appreciated. A survey of the economically quantifiable aspects of this problem demonstrates that the value of the starry sky is immense, and yet it remains stubbornly beyond the ken of the market. The attempts to quantify this value and the ultimate impossibility of the task give lie to the economic pretense that the dollar (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  15.  28
    Valuing the Stars.David Henderson - 2010 - Environmental Philosophy 7 (1):17-26.
    The night sky has been radically altered by light pollution, artificially produced light that obscures the stars. The effects and costs of this are diverse and poorly appreciated. A survey of the economically quantifiable aspects of this problem demonstrates that the value of the starry sky is immense, and yet it remains stubbornly beyond the ken of the market. The attempts to quantify this value and the ultimate impossibility of the task give lie to the economic pretense that the dollar (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  16.  87
    Norms, normative principles, and explanation: On not getting is from ought.David Henderson - 2002 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 32 (3):329-364.
    It seems that hope springs eternal for the cherished idea that norms (or normativeprinciples) explain actions or regularities in actions. But it also seems thatthere are many ways of going wrong when taking norms and normative principlesas explanatory. The author argues that neither norms nor normative principles—insofar as they are the sort of things with normative force—is explanatoryof what is done. He considers the matter using both erotetic and ontic models ofexplanation. He further considers various understandings of norms. Key Words: (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  17.  25
    When Does Stress Help or Harm? The Effects of Stress Controllability and Subjective Stress Response on Stroop Performance.Roselinde K. Henderson, Hannah R. Snyder, Tina Gupta & Marie T. Banich - 2012 - Frontiers in Psychology 3.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  18.  43
    What Research Ethics Should Learn from Genomics and Society Research: Lessons from the ELSI Congress of 2011.Gail E. Henderson, Eric T. Juengst, Nancy M. P. King, Kristine Kuczynski & Marsha Michie - 2012 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 40 (4):1008-1024.
    In much the same way that genomic technologies are changing the complexion of biomedical research, the issues they generate are changing the agenda of IRBs and research ethics. Many of the biggest challenges facing traditional research ethics today — privacy and confidentiality of research subjects; ownership, control, and sharing of research data; return of results and incidental findings; the relevance of group interests and harms; the scope of informed consent; and the relative importance of the therapeutic misconception — have become (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  19.  32
    Abductive Inference, Explicable and Anomalous Disagreement, and Epistemic Resources.David Henderson & Terry Horgan - 2016 - Res Philosophica 93 (3):567-584.
    Disagreement affords humans as members of epistemic communities important opportunities for refining or improving their epistemic situations with respect to many of their beliefs. To get such epistemic gains, one needs to explore and gauge one’s own epistemic situation and the epistemic situations of others. Accordingly, a fitting response to disagreement regarding some matter, p, typically will turn on the resolution of two strongly interrelated questions: (1) whether p, and (2) why one’s interlocutor disagrees with oneself about p. When one (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  20.  12
    "Raising the Cultural Level" at the Hangzhou Children's Palace.Leslie M. Swartz - 1989 - The Journal of Aesthetic Education 23 (1):125.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  43
    Norms, invariance, and explanatory relevance.David Henderson - 2005 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 35 (3):324-338.
    Descriptions of social norms can be explanatory. The erotetic approach to explanation provides a useful framework. I describe one very broad kind of explanation-seeking why-question, a genus that is common to the special sciences, and argue that descriptions of norms can serve as an answer to such why-questions. I draw upon Woodward’s recent discussion of the explanatory role of generalizations with a significant degree of invariance. Descriptions of norms provide what is, in effect, a generalization regarding the kind of historically (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  22.  19
    ‘“Ought” Implies “CAN”’1: PHILOSOPHY.G. P. Henderson - 1966 - Philosophy 41 (156):101-112.
    The dictum ‘“ought” implies “can”’ has a status in moral philosophy in some respects like that of ‘a good player needs good co-ordination’ in talk about ball-games. Clearly, you say something important but not conclusive about proficiency in playing a ball-game when you say that it requires good co-ordination: similarly, you say something important but not conclusive about obligation when you say that it implies a certain possibility or power or ability. Each dictum is a reminder: the one about such (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  23. Deflating the Determination Argument.Jared Henderson - 2017 - Thought: A Journal of Philosophy 6 (2):167-177.
    This article argues for the compatibility of deflationism and truth-conditional semantic theories. I begin by focusing on an argument due to Dorit Bar-On, Claire Horisk, and William Lycan for incompatibility, arguing that their argument relies on an ambiguity between two senses of the expression ‘is at least.’ I go on to show how the disambiguated arguments have different consequences for the deflationist, and argue that no conclusions are established that the deflationist cannot accommodate. I then respond to some objections and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  15
    Within-subjects partial-reinforcement effects in acquisition and in later discrimination learning.Kent Henderson - 1966 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 72 (5):704.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  25.  11
    New developments in transnational education and the challenges for higher education professional staff.Michelle Henderson, Rebecca Barnett & Heather Barrett - 2017 - Perspectives: Policy and Practice in Higher Education 21 (1):11-19.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26.  88
    What Plato Knew About Enron.Michele C. Henderson, M. Gregory Oakes & Marilyn Smith - 2009 - Journal of Business Ethics 86 (4):463-471.
    This paper applies Plato's cave allegory to Enron's success and downfall. Plato's famous tale of cave dwellers illustrates the different levels of truth and understanding. These levels include images, the sources of images, and the ultimate reality behind both. The paper first describes these levels of perception as they apply to Plato's cave dwellers and then provides a brief history of the rise of Enron. Then we apply Plato's levels of understanding to Enron, showing how the company created its image (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  27.  19
    What Plato Knew About Enron.Michele Henderson, M. Gregory Oakes & Marilyn Smith - 2009 - Journal of Business Ethics 86 (4):463-471.
    This paper applies Plato’s cave allegory to Enron’s success and downfall. Plato’s famous tale of cave dwellers illustrates the different levels of truth and understanding. These levels include images, the sources of images, and the ultimate reality behind both. The paper first describes these levels of perception as they apply to Plato’s cave dwellers and then provides a brief history of the rise of Enron. Then we apply Plato’s levels of understanding to Enron, showing how the company created its image (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  28.  18
    Symposium: Is There Only One Correct System of Modal Logic?E. J. Lemmon & G. P. Henderson - 1959 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 33 (2):23 - 56.
  29.  11
    Leveraging Community Context, Data, and Resources to Inform Suicide Prevention Strategies.Leslie M. Barnard, Talia L. Spark, Colton Leavitt, Jacob Leary, Lee J. Lehmkuhl, Nicole Johnston & Erik A. Wallace - 2023 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 51 (1):83-92.
    Colorado has consistently had one of the highest rates of suicide in the United States, and El Paso County has the highest number of suicide and firearm-related suicide deaths within the state. Community-based solutions like those of the Suicide Prevention Collaborative of El Paso County may be more effective in preventing suicide as they are specific to local issues, sensitive to local culture, and informed by local data, community members, and stakeholders.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  58
    An empirical basis for charity in interpretation.David K. Henderson - 1990 - Erkenntnis 32 (1):83 - 103.
    In codifying the methods of translation, several writers have formulated maxims that would constrain interpreters to construe their subjects as (more or less) rational speakers of the truth. Such maxims have come to be known as versions of the principle of charity. W. V. O. Quine suggests an empirical, not purely methodological, basis for his version of that principle. Recently, Stephen Stich has criticized Quine's attempt to found the principle of charity in translation on information about the probabilities of various (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  31.  26
    A solution to Davidson's paradox of irrationality.DavidK Henderson - 1987 - Erkenntnis 27 (3):359 - 369.
  32.  9
    Wittgenstein's Descriptivist Approach to Understanding: Is There a Place for Explanation in Interpretive Accounts?David Henderson - 1988 - Dialectica 42 (2):105-115.
    SummaryIn his Remarks on Frazer's Golden Bough, Wittgenstein holds that in studying or interpreting a language and associated activities we should not attempt to explain what goes on, just describe, for description is able to give us everything we could ask for. He seems to presents two arguments for this descriptivist approach. I criticize both. Generally, I argue that Wittgenstein's position seems to presuppose a radical distinction between description and explanation that cannot be supported.Specifically, I show that Wittgenstein's first objection (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  33.  7
    Victorian Equations.Andrea Kelly Henderson - 2024 - Critical Inquiry 50 (2):252-276.
    As familiar as the form of the mathematical equation is to us, the ostensibly simple act of equating unlike things was an achievement many centuries in the making, and one that would ultimately redefine European mathematical enquiry such that its bias toward geometry and the concrete would be displaced by a bias toward algebraic abstraction. The moment of that displacement was the nineteenth century, and its broader significance is on particularly striking display in the British context, where the implications of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  21
    World Yearbook of Education, 1995: Youth Education and Work.Leslie Bash & Andy Green - 1996 - British Journal of Educational Studies 44 (1):105-107.
  35.  7
    Crack-branching in heavily drawn chromium.F. P. Bullen, F. Henderson & H. L. Wain - 1970 - Philosophical Magazine 21 (172):689-699.
  36. Jews in the Gentile World.Isacque Graeber, Steuart Henderson Britt, Donald S. Strong, Jacob R. Marcus, Raphael Mahler & Bernard Dov Weinryb - 1942 - Science and Society 6 (4):388-394.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Epistemic Evaluation: Point and Purpose in Epistemology.John Greco & David Henderson (eds.) - 2015 - Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  1
    Apophasis and Psychoanalysis.David Henderson - 2018 - In Thomas Cattoi & David M. Odorisio (eds.), Depth Psychology and Mysticism. Cham: Springer Verlag. pp. 199-212.
    The problem of unknowing is central to the theory and practice of psychoanalysis. This paper argues that psychoanalysis is a contemporary site of apophatic discourse. Pseudo-Dionysius observed that: “If one considers these texts with a reverent eye one will see something that brings about unity and manifests a single empathy.” By casting a “reverent eye” on psychoanalysis, we can see that psychoanalytic theory and practice are saturated with apophatic maneuvers. The intuition of apophasis at work in each of the traditions (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  15
    A Critique of Religious Reductionism.Edward Henderson - 1982 - Philosophy Research Archives 8:429-456.
    Accounts of theistic faith according to which it does not involve referring to or believing in God as existing independently of the life of faith are instances of theistic reductionism. Theistic reductionism, in holding that ‘God’ does not refer to reality outside the life of believers, holds thereby that theism is not rightly to be regarded as true or false. Such accounts may be proposed or used as defenses of theistic faith. They ‘defend’ faith insofar as they describe the form (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  35
    A Critique of Religious Reductionism.Edward Henderson - 1982 - Philosophy Research Archives 8:429-456.
    Accounts of theistic faith according to which it does not involve referring to or believing in God as existing independently of the life of faith are instances of theistic reductionism. Theistic reductionism, in holding that ‘God’ does not refer to reality outside the life of believers, holds thereby that theism is not rightly to be regarded as true or false. Such accounts may be proposed or used as defenses of theistic faith. They ‘defend’ faith insofar as they describe the form (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  28
    A critical perspective on a critical perspective on social science.David K. Henderson - 2015 - Metascience 24 (3):457-461.
    Yoshida considers two broad understandings of how social scientists can and should “describe and explain other cultures or their aspects under concepts of rationality” . In the one corner is a family of approaches that Yoshida finds deeply flawed: cultural interpretivist approaches. Five authors representative of this family are given fine chapter length examinations: Winch, Taylor, Geertz, Sahlins, and Obeyesekere. In the other corner is Yoshida’s favored approach: critical rationalism. This approach is associated with the intellectual descendants of Karl Popper—notably (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  18
    A Doo-Dah-Doo-Dah-Dey at the Races: Ovid Amores 3.2 and the Personal Politics of the Circus Maximus.John Henderson - 2002 - Classical Antiquity 21 (1):41-65.
    Ovid's two versions of his encounter with a woman at the races in the Circus Maximus are re-read together as celebrations of the spectacle of the spectators in the arena. The analytical approaches of "Everyday Life" collage and "Foucauldian panopticism" structure are shown to "over-achieve." Ovid dramatizes personal politics at the Circus in a sustained display of the self-reflexive poetics of erotic metaphor. When elegiac amor is acted out as a race, victory and favor are eroticized, steering between crude explicitness (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  9
    An Introduction to the Study of the Dependent, Defective, and Delinquent Classes.Charles Richmond Henderson - 1894 - Philosophical Review 3 (1):125-126.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  14
    Aristophanes, Lysistrate 264.Jeffrey Henderson - 1979 - Classical Quarterly 29 (01):53-.
    Aristophanes, Lysistrate 256–65 271–80 runs as follows. I print the muchdiscussed and frequently emended2 lines 260–65 275–80 as they appear in the manuscripts and testimonia, and shall argue that they are sound with the exception of 264, for which I suggest an emendation.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  15
    A Little Digital Help: Advancing Social Support for Transplant Patients With Technology.Macey L. Henderson & Margot Kelly-Hedrick - 2019 - American Journal of Bioethics 19 (11):42-44.
    Volume 19, Issue 11, November 2019, Page 42-44.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  30
    Account of the Toronto Conference.Larry Henderson - 1995 - The Chesterton Review 21 (1/2):172-173.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  10
    An “Orthodox” Use of the Term “Beautiful”.G. P. Henderson - 1960 - Philosophy 35 (133):114-121.
    The word “beautiful” plays a surprisingly unimportant part in the language of sophisticated artistic appreciation; I mean in the informed criticism and comparison of specific works of art. Though in ordinary conversation it can be used naturally and easily, it does not serve readily as a technical term in expert writing or discussion. To become a technical term of this kind it would have to be definable, and definable in terms which commanded sufficient agreement: but attempts to define “beauty” and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  40
    A Reminder on Recognizing Ethical Problems are Practical.Bernard Henderson - 2002 - Teaching Ethics 2 (2):1-18.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  24
    A substantial theory of value.T. Y. Henderson - 1973 - Journal of Value Inquiry 7 (3):188-197.
  50. And They Cried for Justice.Stewart Henderson - 1989 - Transformation: An International Journal of Holistic Mission Studies 6 (4):17-17.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 991