Results for 'James Aristotle'

988 found
Order:
  1. The worlds of Plato and Aristotle.James Benjamin Plato, Harold Joseph Wilbur, Allen & Aristotle - 1962 - Buffalo, N.Y.: Prometheus Books. Edited by Aristotle, James Benjamin Wilbur & Harold Joseph Allen.
  2.  14
    Aristotle Dictionary.Thomas P. Aristotle, Theodore E. Kiernan & James - 1962 - P. Owen.
    At long last a comprehensive tool in English for a better understanding of the most basic terms in Aristotle's philosophy. A careful comparison of the original Greek, medieval and renaissance Latin translations and a reappraisal of English usage make the work a definitive source for the precise grasp of what has been the historical Aristotle as far as the documents permit one to judge. -- provided by the publisher.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. A Synopsis of the Rhetoric of Aristotle.James E. Thorold Rogers & Aristotle - 1853 - Alexander Ambrose Masson.
  4. ADAMSON Peter and Richard C. Taylor (eds): The Cambridge Companion.James W. Allard, David Bradshaw, Aristotle East, Ronald Bruzina & Edmund Husserl - 2005 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 13 (2):415-419.
  5.  15
    Aristotle's philosophy of biology: studies in the origins of life science.James G. Lennox - 2000 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    In addition to being one of the world's most influential philosophers, Aristotle can also be credited with the creation of both the science of biology and the philosophy of biology. He was the first thinker to treat the investigations of the living world as a distinct inquiry with its own special concepts and principles. This book focuses on a seminal event in the history of biology - Aristotle's delineation of a special branch of theoretical knowledge devoted to the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  6.  12
    Aristotle on Inquiry: Erotetic Frameworks and Domain Specific Norms.James G. Lennox - 2020 - New York, NY, USA: Cambridge University Press.
    Aristotle is a rarity in the history of philosophy and science - he is a towering figure in the history of both disciplines. Moreover, he devoted a great deal of philosophical attention to the nature of scientific knowledge. How then do his philosophical reflections on scientific knowledge impact his actual scientific inquiries? In this book James Lennox sets out to answer this question. He argues that Aristotle has a richly normative view of scientific inquiry, and that those (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  7.  67
    Introduction to philosophy: classical and contemporary readings.Louis P. Pojman & James Fieser (eds.) - 2004 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Now in a third edition, Introduction to Philosophy: Classical and Contemporary Readings is a highly acclaimed, topically organized collection that covers five major areas of philosophy--theory of knowledge, philosophy of religion, philosophy of mind, freedom and determinism, and moral philosophy. Editor Louis P. Pojman enhances the text's topical organization by arranging the selections into a pro/con format to help students better understand opposing arguments. He also includes accessible introductions to each chapter, subsection, and individual reading, a unique feature for an (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  8.  6
    How Things Are: Studies in Predication and the History of Philosophy and Science.James Bogen & J. E. Mcguire - 1984 - Springer.
    One of the earliest and most influential treatises on the subject of this volume is Aristotle's Categories. Aristotle's title is a form of the Greek verb for speaking against or submitting an accusation in a legal proceeding. By the time of Aristotle, it also meant: to signify or to predicate. Surprisingly, the "predicates" Aristotle talks about include not only bits of language, but also such nonlinguistic items as the color white in a body and the knowledge (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  9.  6
    Sources of desire: essays on Aristotle's theoretical works.James Oldfield (ed.) - 2012 - Newcastle upon Tyne, UK: Cambridge Scholars Press.
    Though Aristotle is universally acknowledged as having a mighty influence on the history of philosophy, large parts of his writings are often thought to be interesting to nobody except the historian. This includes those treatises known as the theoretical works (preeminently the Metaphysics, Physics, De Anima, and Posterior Analytics). However, the contributions in this book show that these old treatises are still profound resources for philosophical inquiry. Not only do they inform us about the origins of our ideas, but (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  24
    Aquinas's philosophical commentary on the Ethics: a historical perspective.James Conroy Doig - 2001 - Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers, c.
    Is Aquinas's Sententia libri Ethicorum an interpretation of Aristotle based on `principles of Christian ethics'? Or do we have in that work a presentation of the foundation of Aquinas's moral philosophy? Professor Doig answers these questions through an examination of the historical context within which the Sententia was composed. In Chapters 1-2, the work's role as a corrective of earlier commentaries is established. Chapter 3, by examining philosophy at Paris between 1215 and 1283, reveals that the proposal by Aquinas (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  11.  26
    Aristotle: On the Parts of Animals.James G. Lennox (ed.) - 2002 - Clarendon Press.
    Aristotle is without question the founder of the science of biology. In his treatise On the Parts of Animals, he develops his systematic principles for biological investigation, and explanation, and applies those principles to explain why the different animal kinds have the different parts that they do. It is one of the greatest achievements in the history of science. This new translation from the Greek aims to reflect the subtlety and detail of Aristotle's reasoning. The commentary provides help (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  12.  56
    Theories of education: studies of significant innovation in western educational thought.James Bowen - 1987 - New York: J. Wiley. Edited by Peter R. Hobson.
    This book provides an analysis of the major educational theories of European culture. It covers the spectrum of educational thought from the traditional positions of Plato and Aristotle, through the opposed progressive positions of Rousseau and Dewey, to recent and contemporary variations and reactions to these viewpoints in the work of the Russian communist educator Makarenko, the behaviourist and social theorist B F Skinner, the apostle of freedom in education A S Neill, the British analytic philosopher R S Peters, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  13. The Commentary of St. Thomas on the De Caelo of Aristotle.James A. Weisheipl - 2002 - In Brian Davies (ed.), Thomas Aquinas: contemporary philosophical perspectives. New York: Oxford University Press.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. Epistemology after Protagoras: Responses to Relativism in Plato, Aristotle, and Democritus. Pp. xii + 291. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2005. Cased, £45. ISBN: 0-19-926222-5. [REVIEW]James Warren - 2006 - The Classical Review 56 (1):59-61.
  15.  30
    Exhortations to Philosophy: The Protreptics of Plato, Isocrates, and Aristotle.James Henderson Collins - 2015 - Oup Usa.
    The author argues that the fourth-century philosophers used protreptic discourses to market philosophical practices and to define and legitimize the school of higher learning.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  16.  9
    Boethius' Bearbeitung der Categoriae des Aristoteles.James C. Notker & King - 1972 - Tübingen,: M. Niemeyer. Edited by James Cecil King.
  17. Aristotle’s Ethics.James Urmson - 1988 - Malden, Mass.: Blackwell.
    Introduces Aristotle's writings on ethics, and discusses character, intelligence, pleasure, and friendship.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  18.  34
    Taking flight: trust, ethics and the comfort of strangers.Anne Pirrie, James MacAllister & Gale Macleod - 2012 - Ethics and Education 7 (1):33 - 44.
    This article explores the themes of trust and ethical conduct in social research, with particular attention to the trust that can develop between the members of a research team as well as between researchers and the researched. The authors draw upon a three-year empirical study of destinations and outcomes for young people excluded from alternative educational provision. They also make reference to a contemporary exposition of Aristotle's writing on friendship in order to explore two sets of relevant distinctions that (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  19. ‘Early Interest in Knowledge’.James Lesher - 1999 - In A. A. Long (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Early Greek Philosophy. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 225-249.
    Western philosophy begins with Thales, Anaximander, and Anaximenes. Or so we are told by Aristotle and many members of the later doxographical tradition. But a good case can be made that several centuries before the Milesian thinkers began their investigations, the poets of archaic Greece reflected on the limits of human intelligence and concluded that no mortal being could know the full and certain truth. Homer belittled the mental capacities of ‘creatures of a day’ and a series of poets (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  20. Aristotle’s Philosophy of Biology: Studies in the Origins of Life Science.James G. Lennox - 2001 - Journal of the History of Biology 36 (1):223-224.
  21. Getting Your Sources Right: What Aristotle Didn’t Say.James Mahon - 1999 - In Researching and Applying Metaphor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 69-80.
    In this chapter I argue that writers on metaphor have misunderstood Aristotle on metaphor. Aristotle is not an elitist about metaphor and does not consider metaphors to be merely ornamental. Rather, Aristotle believes that metaphors are ubiquitous and believes that people can express themselves in a clearer and more attractive way through the use of metaphors and that people learn and understand things better through metaphor. He also distinguishes between the use of metaphor and the coinage of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  21
    De caelo 2.2 and Its Debt to De incessu animalium.James G. Lennox - 2009 - In Alan Bowen & Christian Wildberg (eds.), New Perspectives on Aristotle’s De Caelo. Brill. pp. 1--187.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  23. The Development of Aristotle's Logic: Part of an Account in Outline.James Allen - 1995 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 11:177-205.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  24. Technology and Psychiatry.James Phillips - 2013 - In K. W. M. Fulford, Martin Davies, Richard Gipps, George Graham, John Sadler, Giovanni Stanghellini & Tim Thornton (eds.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy and psychiatry. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    This chapter evaluates the multiple roles of technology in psychiatry, drawing on philosophical resources and mindful of psychiatry's need to benefit from technology without reducing itself to nothing but a technology. It approaches the topic of technology and psychiatry from three perspectives. First, it addresses technology as a way of thinking-technical or instrumental reason-and how technical reason informs psychiatric theory and practice. For this analysis it invokes a philosophical tradition that stretches from Aristotle to Toulmin and Gadamer. Second, it (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. Getting Your Sources Right: What Aristotle Didn’t Say.James Mahon - 1999 - In Researching and Applying Metaphor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 69-80.
    In this chapter I argue that writers on metaphor have misunderstood Aristotle on metaphor. Aristotle is not an elitist about metaphor and does not consider metaphors to be merely ornamental. Rather, Aristotle believes that metaphors are ubiquitous and believes that people can express themselves in a clearer and more attractive way through the use of metaphors and that people learn and understand things better through metaphor. He also distinguishes between the use of metaphor and the coinage of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  16
    The Pleasures of Reason in Plato, Aristotle, and the Hellenistic Hedonists.James Warren - 2014 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Human lives are full of pleasures and pains. And humans are creatures that are able to think: to learn, understand, remember and recall, plan and anticipate. Ancient philosophers were interested in both of these facts and, what is more, were interested in how these two facts are related to one another. There appear to be, after all, pleasures and pains associated with learning and inquiring, recollecting and anticipating. We enjoy finding something out. We are pained to discover that a belief (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  27. Aristotle's forbidden sweets.James Bogen & J. M. E. Moravcsik - 1982 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 20 (2):111-127.
  28.  3
    Aristotle's Forbidden Sweets.James Bogen & J. M. E. Moravcsik - 1982 - University of California Press].
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  29.  14
    Philosophy and Political Economy.James Bonar - 2018 - Routledge.
    This volume is one of the most remarkable works in the history of economic thought. First published in 1893, its principal significance rests in its argument that economic theory, however technical or pragmatic, is necessarily formed by and derives its meaning from larger moral and philosophical systems and assumptions. Bonar traces the inexorable presence of this moral and philosophical element in a vast, though highly nuanced, survey of the economic aspect of major thinkers from Plato to Darwin and demonstrates how (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  30.  29
    Seeking the Common Good in Education Through a Positive Conception of Social Justice.James Arthur, Kristján Kristjánsson & Candace Vogler - 2021 - British Journal of Educational Studies 69 (1):101-117.
    Many Faculties of Education in the UK and elsewhere have ‘social justice’ written into their mission statements. But are they concerned by questions of social justice in education, or has the term become somewhat vacuous and devoid of substantive meaning? The present article subjects recent discourses about social justice in education to scrutiny and finds them wanting in various respects, in particular when juxtaposed with historical accounts of justice by philosophers such as Aristotle or Aquinas. Among the complaints made (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  31.  3
    Aristotle's History Oif Athenian Democray.James Day & Mortimer Chambers - 1967 - Hakkert.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. Aristotle on Form, Substance, and Universals: A Dilemma.James H. Lesher - 1971 - Phronesis 16 (1):169-178.
    In book Zeta of the Metaphysics and elsewhere Aristotle appears to commit himself to the following propositions: (1) No universal can be substance; (2) Form is a universal; and (3) Form is that which is most truly substance. These propositions appear to constitute an inconsistent triad lying at the heart of Aristotle’s ontology. A number of attempts have been made to rescue Aristotle from the charge of inconsistency. Some have claimed that Aristotle did not subscribe to (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  33. Art and Knowledge.James O. Young - 2001 - New York: Routledge.
    Almost all of us would agree that the experience of art is deeply rewarding. Why this is the case remains a puzzle; nor does it explain why many of us find works of art much more important than other sources of pleasure. Art and Knowledge argues that the experience of art is so rewarding because it can be an important source of knowledge about ourselves and our relation to each other and to the world. The view that art is a (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  34. Aristotle on Norms of Inquiry.James G. Lennox - 2011 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 1 (1):23-46.
    Where does Aristotle stand in the debate between rationalism and empiricism? The locus classicus on this question, Posterior Analytics II. 19, seems clearly empiricist. Yet many commentators have resisted this conclusion. Here, I review their arguments and conclude that they rest in part on expectations for this text that go unfulfilled. I argue that this is because his views about norms of empirical inquiry are in the rich methodological passages in his scientific treatises. In support of this claim, I (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  35.  53
    Change and Contrariety in Aristotle.James Bogen - 1992 - Phronesis 37 (1):1-21.
  36. Aristotle on the Emergence of Material Complexity: Meteorology IV and Aristotle’s Biology.James G. Lennox - 2014 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 4 (2):272-305.
    In this article I defend an account of Meteorology IV as providing a material-level causal account of the emergence of uniform materials with a wide range of dispositional properties not found at the level of the four elements—the emergence of material complexity. I then demonstrate that this causal account is used in the Generation of Animals and Parts of Animals as part of the explanation of the generation of the uniform parts (tissues) and of their role in providing nonuniform parts (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  37.  76
    Aristotle on genera, species, and?the more and the less?James G. Lennox - 1980 - Journal of the History of Biology 13 (2):321-346.
  38.  62
    Aristotle's Definition of Change.James Kostman - 1987 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 4 (1):3 - 16.
  39.  66
    Aristotle’s Great Clock.James Bogen & J. E. McGuire - 1986 - Philosophy Research Archives 12:387-448.
    This paper offers a detailed account of arguments in De Caelo I by which Aristotle tried to demonstrate the necessity of the perpetual existence and the perpetual rotation of the cosmos. On our interpretation, Aristotle’s arguments are naturalistic. Instead of being based (as many have thought) on rules of logic and language, they depend, we argue, on natural science theories about abilities (δυνάμεις), e.g., to move and to change, which things have by nature and about the conditions under (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  31
    Aristotle’s Great Clock.James Bogen & J. E. McGuire - 1986 - Philosophy Research Archives 12:387-448.
    This paper offers a detailed account of arguments in De Caelo I by which Aristotle tried to demonstrate the necessity of the perpetual existence and the perpetual rotation of the cosmos. On our interpretation, Aristotle’s arguments are naturalistic. Instead of being based (as many have thought) on rules of logic and language, they depend, we argue, on natural science theories about abilities (δυνάμεις), e.g., to move and to change, which things have by nature and about the conditions under (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  21
    Aristotle’s Great Clock.James Bogen & J. E. McGuire - 1986 - Philosophy Research Archives 12:387-448.
    This paper offers a detailed account of arguments in De Caelo I by which Aristotle tried to demonstrate the necessity of the perpetual existence and the perpetual rotation of the cosmos. On our interpretation, Aristotle’s arguments are naturalistic. Instead of being based (as many have thought) on rules of logic and language, they depend, we argue, on natural science theories about abilities (δυνάμεις), e.g., to move and to change, which things have by nature and about the conditions under (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  29
    Aristotle, Berkeley, and Proteus: Joyce's Use of Philosophy.James Cappio - 1981 - Philosophy and Literature 5 (1):21-32.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43. Syllogism, demonstration, and definition in Aristotle's Topics and Posterior Analytics.James Allen - 2011 - In Michael Frede, James V. Allen, Eyjólfur Kjalar Emilsson, Wolfgang-Rainer Mann & Benjamin Morison (eds.), Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy: Essays in Memory of Michael Frede. Summer 2011. Vol. 40. Oxford University Press. pp. 40--63.
  44. Texts to illustrate a course of elementary lectures on Greek philosophy after Aristotle.James Adam - 1902 - New York,: Macmillan & Co..
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. Texts to Illustrate a Course of Elementary Lectures on Greek Philosophy After Aristotle, Selected and Arranged by J. Adam.James Adam - 1902
  46. Syllogism, Demonstration, and Definition in Aristotle's Topics and Posterior Analytics.James Allen - 2011 - Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 40:63-90.
  47.  7
    Aristotle: On the Parts of Animals.James G. Lennox (ed.) - 2002 - Clarendon Press.
    Aristotle is without question the founder of the science of biology. In his treatise On the Parts of Animals, he develops his systematic principles for biological investigation, and explanation, and applies those principles to explain why the different animal kinds have the different parts that they do. It is one of the greatest achievements in the history of science. This new translation from the Greek aims to reflect the subtlety and detail of Aristotle's reasoning. The commentary provides help (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  48. Aristotle: On the Parts of Animals.James G. Lennox - 2003 - Philosophical Quarterly 53 (213):607-609.
    Aristotle is without question the founder of the science of biology. In his treatise On the Parts of Animals, he develops his systematic principles for biological investigation, and explanation, and applies those principles to explain why the different animal kinds have the different parts that they do. It is one of the greatest achievements in the history of science. This new translation from the Greek aims to reflect the subtlety and detail of Aristotle's reasoning. The commentary provides help (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  49.  41
    Teilhard’s Cosmological Kinship to Aristotle.James F. Anderson - 1971 - New Scholasticism 45 (4):584-589.
  50.  97
    Aristotle's politics and ptolemy of Lucca.James Blythe - 2002 - Vivarium 40 (1):103-136.
1 — 50 / 988