Results for 'Harmfulness of Death'

993 found
Order:
  1.  43
    Near–death experiences. A theological interpretation.Harm Goris - 2014 - International Journal of Philosophy and Theology 75 (1):74-85.
    Stories about near-death experiences draw much attention from the general public and are extensively discussed by medical doctors and neuroscientists. However, though eschatology belongs to their core business, only few theologians participate in the debate. This article proposes a theological interpretation of NDEs as ‘private revelations’. I first give a critical analysis of the development of the modern, allegedly ‘scientific’, concept of NDE. This concept changes concrete personal testimonies into statistical data that are used as scientific evidence for the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. Saving People from the Harm of Death.Espen Gamlund & Carl Tollef Solberg (eds.) - 2019 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Death is something we mourn or fear as the worst thing that could happen―whether the deaths of close ones, the deaths of strangers in reported accidents or tragedies, or our own. And yet, being dead is something that no one can experience and live to describe. This simple truth raises a host of difficult philosophical questions about the negativity surrounding our sense of death, and how and for whom exactly it is harmful. The question of whether death (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  3. The harm of death, time-relative interests, and abortion.David Degrazia - 2007 - Philosophical Forum 38 (1):57–80.
    Regarding the sinking lifeboat scenario involving several human beings and a dog, nearly everyone agrees that it is right to sacrifice the dog. I suggest that the best explanation for this considered judgment, an explanation that appears to time-relative interests, contains a key insight about prudential value. This insight, I argue, also provides perhaps the most promising reply to the future-like-ours argument, which is widely regarded as the strongest moral argument against abortion. Providing a solution to a longstanding puzzle in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  4. Accounting for the Harm of Death.Duncan Purves - 2014 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 97 (1):89-112.
    I defend a theory of the way in which death is a harm to the person who dies that fits into a larger, unified account of harm ; and includes an account of the time of death's harmfulness, one that avoids the implications that death is a timeless harm and that people have levels of welfare at times at which they do not exist.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  5. Epicurus and the harm of death.William Grey - 1999 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 77 (3):358 – 364.
    Epicurus notoriously argued that death at no time is a harm because before death there is no harm and after death there is no victim. The denial that death can be a harm to the one who dies has been challenged by various claims including (1) death is eternally bad for the victim (Feldman), (2) it is before death that it is bad for the victim (Feinberg and Pitcher), (3) death is bad for (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  6.  10
    Saving People From the Harm of Death. Edited by Gamlund Espen & Solberg Carl Tollef.Karl Ekendahl - 2020 - Philosophical Quarterly 70 (281):871-873.
    Saving People From the Harm of Death. Edited by Gamlund Espen, Solberg Carl Tollef.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7. Animals and the harm of death.Frederike Kaldewaij - 2003 - In Susan Jean Armstrong & Richard George Botzler (eds.), The animal ethics reader. New York: Routledge.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  8. Quantifying the harm of death.Erik Nord - 2019 - In Espen Gamlund & Carl Tollef Solberg (eds.), Saving People from the Harm of Death. New York: Oxford University Press.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  8
    Metaphysics of the Harm of Death.Ikuro Suzuki - 2011 - Journal of the Japan Association for Philosophy of Science 39 (1):13-24.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. Putting a number on the harm of death.Joseph Millum - 2019 - In Espen Gamlund & Carl Tollef Solberg (eds.), Saving People from the Harm of Death. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 61-75.
    Donors to global health programs and policymakers within national health systems have to make difficult decisions about how to allocate scarce health care resources. Principled ways to make these decisions all make some use of summary measures of health, which provide a common measure of the value (or disvalue) of morbidity and mortality. They thereby allow comparisons between health interventions with different effects on the patterns of death and ill health within a population. The construction of a summary measure (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11.  4
    Culture of death: the age of "do harm" medicine.Wesley J. Smith - 2016 - New York: Encounter Books.
    Harsh medicine -- Life unworthy of life -- The price of autonomy -- Creating a duty to die -- Organ donors or organ farms? -- Putting second things first -- Two legs good, four legs better.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12.  14
    SAVING PEOPLE FROM THE HARM OF DEATH. Espen Gamlund and Carl Tollef Solberg (Eds.) Oxford University Press: New York, NY, 2019. 284 pp., includes index. ISBN 9780190921415. $85 (Hardcover). [REVIEW]Molly Gardner - 2020 - Bioethics 34 (9):996-997.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  45
    The Harm of Premature Death, Immortality - The Transhumanist Challenge.James D. E. Watson - 2009 - Ethical Perspectives 16 (4):435-458.
    Although an age-old problem, the debate over immortality has become reanimated in light of recent advances in life extension technologies, accompanied by an ever-growing body of enthusiasts, both within academic circles as well as the public in general. For these people, death is no longer a natural process, but a disease, and one that might be prevented. It seems that the desire for immortality is a result, in part, of a profound sense of incompleteness and frustration that death (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  25
    The Culture of Death: The Age of “Do Harm” Medicine.Ralph A. Capone - 2018 - The National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly 18 (3):554-557.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. “Welfare and Harm After Death,”.Barbara Baum Levenbook - 2013 - In James Stacey Taylor (ed.), The Metaphysics and Ethics of Death: New Essays. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. pp. 188-209.
    I defend the claim that posthumous harm is possible against a simple but powerful and appealing argument for the impossibility of harm from posthumous events. I produce a counterargument against one of its assumptions. My conclusion is that the boundaries of welfare-affecting events may extend beyond the existence of the person whose welfare is in question. My case for rejecting the contrary claim avoids an objection to some familiar arguments for posthumous harm and is superior to another argument for posthumous (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  16. Mortal Harm and the Antemortem Experience of Death.Stephan Blatti - 2014 - Journal of Medical Ethics 40 (9):640-42.
    In his recent book, Death, Posthumous Harm, and Bioethics (Routeledge 2012), James Stacey Taylor challenges two ideas whose provenance may be traced all the way back to Aristotle. The first of these is the thought that death (typically) harms the one who dies (mortal harm thesis). The second is the idea that one can be harmed (and wronged) by events that occur after one’s death (posthumous harm thesis). Taylor devotes two-thirds of the book to arguing against both (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17. Dissolving Death’s Time-of-Harm Problem.Travis Timmerman - 2022 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 100 (2):405-418.
    Most philosophers in the death literature believe that death can be bad for the person who dies. The most popular view of death’s badness—namely, deprivationism—holds that death is bad for the person who dies because, and to the extent that, it deprives them of the net good that they would have accrued, had their actual death not occurred. Deprivationists thus face the challenge of locating the time that death is bad for a person. This (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  18. The Power of Death: Retroactivity, Narrative, and Interest.Patrick Stokes - 2006 - In Robert L. Perkins (ed.), International Kierkegaard Commentary: Prefaces/Writing Sampler and Three Discourses on Imagined Occasions. Mercer University Press.
    This paper contrasts Kierkegaard's response to Epicurean indifference to death in "At a Graveside" with attempts in contemporary analytic philosophy to overcome Epicurus ' challenge to the rationality of fearing death. I argue that attempts by Nagel, Pitcher, Feinberg etc. to show why death is a harm rely on a narrative understanding of life that, according to Kierkegaard, is unavailable with respect to one's own death. Kierkegaard's approach, by contrast, involves becoming phenomenally co-present with one's own (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  19. Do Embryos Have Interests?: Why Embryos Are Identical to Future Persons but Not Harmed by Death.Aaron Simmons - 2012 - Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 9 (1):57-66.
    Are embryos deserving of moral consideration in our actions? A standard view suggests that embryos are considerable only if they have interests. One argument for embryonic interests contends that embryos are harmed by death because they are deprived of valuable future lives as adult persons. Some have challenged this argument on the grounds that embryos aren’t identical to adults: either due to the potential for embryos to twin or because we do not exist until the fetus develops consciousness. These (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20.  70
    The Metaphysics of death.John Martin Fischer (ed.) - 1993 - Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press.
    Introduction : death, metaphysics, and morality / John Martin Fischer Death knocks / Woody Allen Rationality and the fear of death / Jeffrie G. Murphy Death / Thomas Nagel The Makropulos case : reflections on the tedium of immortality / Bernard Williams The evil of death / Harry S. Silverstein How to be dead and not care : a defense of Epicurus / Stephen E. Rosenbaum The dead / Palle Yourgrau The misfortunes of the dead (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  21. The Severity of Death.Jens Johansson - 2016 - In John K. Davis (ed.), Ethics at the End of Life: New Issues and Arguments. New York: Routledge. pp. 61-73.
    Just as some illnesses and injuries are worse than others, so some deaths appear to be worse than others. This is so not only for the fairly trivial reason that those deaths that are bad are worse than those deaths that are not bad: less trivially, some bad deaths seem to be worse than other bad deaths. For instance, whereas it may well be bad for an eighty-year-old to die, it is likely to be even worse for a forty-year-old, and (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. Sentient Nonpersons and the Disvalue of Death.David DeGrazia - 2016 - Bioethics 30 (7):511-519.
    Implicit in our everyday attitudes and practices is the assumption that death ordinarily harms a person who dies. A far more contested matter is whether death harms sentient individuals who are not persons, a category that includes many animals and some human beings. On the basis of the deprivation account of the harm of death, I argue that death harms sentient nonpersons. I next consider possible bases for the commonsense judgment that death ordinarily harms persons (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  23. Against "the badness of death".Hilary Greaves - 2019 - In Espen Gamlund & Carl Tollef Solberg (eds.), Saving People from the Harm of Death. New York: Oxford University Press.
    I argue that excessive reliance on the notion of “the badness of death” tends to lead theorists astray when thinking about healthcare prioritisation. I survey two examples: the confusion surrounding the “time-relative interests account” of the badness of death, and a confusion in the recent literature on cost-benefit analyses for family planning interventions. In both cases, the confusions in question would have been avoided if (instead of attempting to theorise in terms of the badness of death) theorists (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  24.  7
    The Harms of a Penal Colony.Justin Strong - 2019 - Hastings Center Report 49 (4):44-45.
    More than just a jail, Rikers has become a site of shifting discourse on punishment and justice in the United States. In the book Life and Death in Rikers Island, Homer Venters argues that the systematic failures of jails to provide appropriate safety and care constitute human rights violations and public health risks. The former chief medical officer and commissioner of correctional health services for the NYC Health and Hospitals system, Venters offers critical insight on the Rikers jail system. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. Rationality and the Fear of Death in Epicurean Philosophy.Voula Tsouna - 2006 - Rhizai. A Journal for Ancient Philosophy and Science 1:79-117.
    This paper outlines the Epicurean conception of rationality and then tries to assess the merits of the notorious contention of the Epicurean philosophers that it is irrationalto fear death. At the outset, I talk about the nature of harmful emotions or passions, of which the fear of death is an outstanding example: their dependence on one‘s disposition, their cognitive and non-cognitive components, the ways in which these elements may be related to each other, and the healthy counterparts of (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  26.  36
    The disvalue of death in the global burden of disease.Carl Tollef Solberg, Ole Frithjof Norheim & Mathias Barra - 2018 - Journal of Medical Ethics 44 (3):192-198.
    In the Global Burden of Disease study, disease burden is measured as disability-adjusted life years (DALYs). The paramount assumption of the DALY is that it makes sense to aggregate years lived with disability (YLDs) and years of life lost (YLLs). However, this is not smooth sailing. Whereas morbidity (YLD) is something thathappens toan individual, loss of life itself (YLL) occurs when that individual’s life has ended. YLLs quantify something that involves no experience and does not take place among living individuals. (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  27. Editorial Afterword.Death Of Hinck - 1998 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 76 (1):138-139.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28.  29
    Epicurus and the Singularity of Death: Defending Radical Epicureanism.David B. Suits - 2020 - New York: Bloomsbury Academic.
    Epicurus's claim that "death is nothing to us" is defended. The usual concepts of harm, loss and suffering do not apply in the case of death. Immortality need not be bad. Epicurean prudence does not recommend suicide. Some issues in applied ethics are also discussed: the right to life, egoistic friendship, wills, and life insurance.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. Death's Distinctive Harm.Stephan Blatti - 2012 - American Philosophical Quarterly 49 (4):317-30.
    Despite widespread support for the claim that death can harm the one who dies, debate continues over how to rescue this harm thesis (HT) from Epicurus’s challenge. Disagreements focus on two of the three issues that any defense of HT must resolve: the subject of death’s harm and the timing of its injury. About the nature of death’s harm, however, a consensus has emerged around the view that death harms a subject (when it does) by depriving (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  30.  98
    Harming someone after his death.Barbara Baum Levenbook - 1984 - Ethics 94 (3):407-419.
    I argue for the possibility of posthumous harm based on an account of the harm of murder. I start with the deep-seated intuition that when someone is murdered he (or she) is harmed (over and above the pain of injury or dying), and argue that Feinberg's account that assumes that harm is an invasion of an interest cannot plausibly accommodate this intuition. I propose a new account of the harm of murder: it is an irreversible loss of functions necessary for (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  31.  86
    The Benefits and Harms of Existence and Non-existence: Guest Editor’s Introduction.Jens Johansson - 2013 - The Journal of Ethics 17 (1-2):1-4.
    According to the “deprivation approach,” a person’s death is bad for her to the extent that it deprives her of goods. This approach faces the Lucretian problem that prenatal non-existence deprives us of goods just as much as death does, but does not seem bad at all. The two most prominent responses to this challenge—one of which is provided by Frederik Kaufman and the other by Anthony Brueckner and John Martin Fischer—claim that prenatal non-existence is relevantly different from (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  32.  5
    The Thread of Death, or the Compulsion to Kill.J. S. Piven - 2010-09-24 - In Fritz Allhoff & S. Waller (eds.), Serial Killers ‐ Philosophy for Everyone. Wiley‐Blackwell. pp. 206–217.
    This chapter contains sections titled: The Epistemology of Murder Violence and Human Nature The Gestation of Terrorists and Serial Killers Conclusions.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  13
    Annihilation: The Sense and Significance of Death.Christopher Belshaw - 2008 - Routledge.
    The ever-present possibility of death forces upon us the question of life's meaning and for this reason death has been a central concern of philosophers throughout history. From Socrates to Heidegger, philosophers have grappled with the nature and significance of death. In "Annihilation", Christopher Belshaw explores two central questions at the heart of philosophy's engagement with death: what is death; and is it bad that we die? Belshaw begins by distinguishing between literal and metaphorical uses (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  34.  62
    Annihilation: The Sense and Significance of Death.Christopher Belshaw - 2008 - Routledge.
    The ever-present possibility of death forces upon us the question of life's meaning and for this reason death has been a central concern of philosophers throughout history. From Socrates to Heidegger, philosophers have grappled with the nature and significance of death. In "Annihilation", Christopher Belshaw explores two central questions at the heart of philosophy's engagement with death: what is death; and is it bad that we die? Belshaw begins by distinguishing between literal and metaphorical uses (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  35.  92
    Choosing death in unjust conditions: hope, autonomy and harm reduction.Kayla Wiebe & Amy Mullin - 2024 - Journal of Medical Ethics 50 (6):407-412.
    In this essay, we consider questions arising from cases in which people request medical assistance in dying (MAiD) in unjust social circumstances. We develop our argument by asking two questions. First, can decisions made in the context of unjust social circumstance be meaningfully autonomous? We understand ‘unjust social circumstances’ to be circumstances in which people do not have meaningful access to the range of options to which they are entitled and ‘autonomy’ as self-governance in the service of personally meaningful goals, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  36. The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Death.Ben Bradley, Fred Feldman & Jens Johansson (eds.) - 2012 - Oxford University Press USA.
    Death has long been a pre-occupation of philosophers, and this is especially so today. The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Death collects 21 newly commissioned essays that cover current philosophical thinking of death-related topics across the entire range of the discipline. These include metaphysical topics--such as the nature of death, the possibility of an afterlife, the nature of persons, and how our thinking about time affects what we think about death--as well as axiological topics, such (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  37.  89
    The Time of Death's Badness.J. Johansson - 2012 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 37 (5):464-479.
    Those who endorse the view that death is in some cases bad for the deceased—a view that, as I shall explain, has considerable bearing on many bioethical issues—need to address the following, Epicurean question: When is death bad for the one who dies? The two most popular answers are "before death" (priorism) and "after death" (subsequentism). Part of the support for these two views consists in the idea that a third answer, "at no time" (atemporalism), makes (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  38.  18
    Death, Posthumous Harm, and Bioethics.James Stacey Taylor - 2012 - New York: Routledge.
    Death, Posthumous Harm, and Bioethics offers a highly distinctive and original approach to the metaphysics of death and applies this approach to contemporary debates in bioethics that address end-of-life and post-mortem issues. Taylor defends the controversial Epicurean view that death is not a harm to the person who dies and the neo-Epicurean thesis that persons cannot be affected by events that occur after their deaths, and hence that posthumous harms are impossible. He then extends this argument by (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  39. Death, Posthumous Harm, and Bioethics.James Stacey Taylor - 2012 - New York: Routledge.
    _Death, Posthumous Harm, and Bioethics_ offers a highly distinctive and original approach to the metaphysics of death and applies this approach to contemporary debates in bioethics that address end-of-life and post-mortem issues. Taylor defends the controversial Epicurean view that death is not a harm to the person who dies and the neo-Epicurean thesis that persons cannot be affected by events that occur after their deaths, and hence that posthumous harms are impossible. He then extends this argument by asserting (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  40.  54
    Harm, ethics committees and the gene therapy death.Julian Savulescu - 2001 - Journal of Medical Ethics 27 (3):148-150.
    The recent tragic and widely publicised death of Jesse Gelsinger in a gene therapy trial has many important lessons for those engaged in the ethical review of research. One of the most important lessons is that ethics committees can give too much weight to ensuring informed consent and not enough attention to minimising the harm associated with participation in research. The first responsibility of ethics committees should be to ensure that the expected harm associated with participation is reasonable. Jesse (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  41.  91
    Death as a Social Harm.Lori Gruen - 2014 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 52 (S1):53-65.
    Lately there has been increased attention to the philosophical issues that death raises, but the focus remains individualistic. Death is philosophically puzzling. Death is thought to be bad for the individual who dies, but there is no one there to experience death as a harm. In this paper I argue that the harm of death is a social harm. Of course, social relationships are fundamentally changed when any member of a social group dies. Death (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  42. Think Least of Death: Spinoza on How to Live and How to Die by Steven Nadler. [REVIEW]John Grey - 2023 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 61 (4):708-709.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Think Least of Death: Spinoza on How to Live and How to Die by Steven NadlerJohn GreySteven Nadler. Think Least of Death: Spinoza on How to Live and How to Die. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2020. Pp. x + 234. Hardback, $39.95.Think Least of Death is not just an interpretation of Spinoza, but a defense of his philosophy. Nadler develops Spinoza's arguments in ways (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  3
    Fischer on the Time of Death’s Badness.Erik Carlson, Karl Ekendahl & Jens Johansson - 2024 - Philosophia:1-10.
    In a recent article in this journal, John Martin Fischer defends the view that death harms its victim after she dies. More specifically, he develops a “truthmaking” account in order to solve what he calls the Problem of Predication for this view. In this reply, we argue that Fischer’s proposed solution to this problem is unsuccessful.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  87
    Life, death, and harm: Staying within the boundaries of nonmaleficence.Sandra Woien - 2008 - American Journal of Bioethics 8 (11):31 – 32.
  45. The badness of death : implications for summary measures and fair priority setting in health.Ofrithjof Norheim - 2019 - In Espen Gamlund & Carl Tollef Solberg (eds.), Saving People from the Harm of Death. New York: Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  9
    On the Proper Treatment of the N400 and P600 in Language Comprehension.Brouwer Harm & W. Crocker Matthew - 2017 - Frontiers in Psychology 8.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  47. The badness of death for us, the worth in us, and priorities in saving lives.Samuel J. Kerstein - 2019 - In Espen Gamlund & Carl Tollef Solberg (eds.), Saving People from the Harm of Death. New York: Oxford University Press.
  48. Comparative Harm, Creation and Death.Neil Feit - 2016 - Utilitas 28 (2):136-163.
    Given that a person's death is bad for her,whenis it bad? I defendsubsequentism, the view that things that are bad in the relevant way are bad after they occur. Some have objected to this view on the grounds that it requires us to compare the amount of well-being the victim would have enjoyed, had she not died, with the amount she receives while dead; however, we cannot assign any level of well-being, not even zero, to a dead person. In (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  49.  42
    Does Death Restriction-Harm Us?Eric Yang - 2018 - Journal of Value Inquiry 52 (4):429-436.
    Recently, Stephan Blatti has argued that a deprivationist view (DV) of death’s harm is incomplete, and he presents a view such that the kind of distinctive harm that death brings to an individual involves the restriction of that individual’s autonomy.2 Not only does death deprivation-harm us, but it also restriction-harms us. Let us label such an account—one that includes both deprivation and restriction as comprising death’s harm—as a ‘deprivationist-restrictionist view’ (or ‘DRV’). Blatti favors DRV because it (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50.  28
    Does Viral Communication Context Increase the Harmfulness of Controversial Taboo Advertising?Ouidade Sabri - 2017 - Journal of Business Ethics 141 (2):235-247.
    Controversial taboo appeals as an executional cue in viral advertising have commonly been used by advertisers. In this context, the study investigates the role of medium context on the effectiveness of controversial taboo ads. By implementing a tightly controlled experiment which deals with controversial taboo ads embedded in a press article and in a viral context, the study finds that the viral medium context does not lead to a more positive attitude toward the embedded brand or to more positive purchase (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
1 — 50 / 993