Order:
Disambiguations
Daniel L. Feldman [3]Daniel Feldman [2]Dan Feldman [1]
  1.  45
    AI and Phronesis.Dan Feldman & Nir Eisikovits - 2022 - Moral Philosophy and Politics 9 (2):181-199.
    We argue that the growing prevalence of statistical machine learning in everyday decision making – from creditworthiness to police force allocation – effectively replaces many of our humdrum practical judgments and that this will eventually undermine our capacity for making such judgments. We lean on Aristotle’s famous account of how phronesis and moral virtues develop to make our case. If Aristotle is right that the habitual exercise of practical judgment allows us to incrementally hone virtues, and if AI saves us (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  2.  16
    Principled compromise: The New York state organized crime control act.Daniel L. Feldman - 1987 - Criminal Justice Ethics 6 (1):50-60.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  19
    Aftermaths: Exile, Migration, and Diaspora Reconsidered.Daniel Feldman - 2013 - Common Knowledge 19 (3):573-574.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  15
    Aftermaths: Exile, Migration, and Diaspora Reconsidered by ed. by Marcus Bullock and Peter Paik (review).Daniel Feldman - 2013 - Common Knowledge 19 (3):573-574.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. Corruption in Italy : indigenous impediments to reform.Daniel L. Feldman - 2020 - In Carole L. Jurkiewicz, Stuart Gilman & Carol W. Lewis (eds.), Global corruption and ethics management: translating theory into action. Lanham, Maryland: Rowman & Littlefield.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  21
    Should Judges Justify Recourse to Broader Contexts When Interpreting Statutes?Daniel L. Feldman - 2020 - International Journal for the Semiotics of Law - Revue Internationale de Sémiotique Juridique 34 (2):377-388.
    Courts purport to abandon ordinary meaning only when words in a statute accommodate more than one meaning; to look to surrounding words, legislative history, and then public policy considerations, only if those previous efforts fail. The canon of statutory construction, “a word is known by its associates,” generally means nearest associates, or near as possible. An analogous language philosophy principle counsels increasing search radius only as needed. Dimensional extension advances the sequence to broader domains of information. Such incrementalist restrictions should (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark