Results for 'Copernicanism'

70 found
Order:
  1.  21
    Copernicanism Reformed.Marcus Hellyer - 2003 - Metascience 12 (2):257-260.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  36
    Copernicanism, Old and New.Robert Palter - 1964 - The Monist 48 (2):143-184.
    In this paper I shall attempt to illustrate the way in which philosophical principles diversify scientific theories. By this I mean that alternative philosophical views may inspire and even form part of the basis of alternative scientific theories of the same phenomena, e.g., gravitation. I shall make no attempt, however, to explain the mode of logical connection between a set of philosophical principles and a correlated scientific theory—a question which I consider extremely difficult and perhaps not even amenable to a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. Copernicanism, jansenism, and remonstrantism in the seventeenth century netherlands.Tabitta Van Nouhuys - 2005 - In John Hedley Brooke & Ian Maclean (eds.), Heterodoxy in Early Modern Science and Religion. Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. David Hume and Copernicanism.Silvia Manzo - 2009 - In Letitia Meynell, Donald Baxter, Nathan Brett & Lívia Guimaraes (eds.), 36th International Hume Society Conference. Naturalism and Hume’s Philosophy. Conference Papers. Halifax, N.S.: The Printer. pp. 85-88.
    The aim of this paper is to examine how much Hume knew about astronomy, in order to understand the reasons for his acceptance of Copernicanism. My contention is that Hume’s positive reception of the Copernican system arises at least from the importance that he gives to three features that he attributes to the Copernican system: beauty, simplicity and uniformity. I also give some evidence that Hume had first-hand knowledge of some sections of Galileo’s Dialogo sopra i due massimi sistemi (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  13
    Copernicanism, scientific autonomy and religious authority in Marin Mersenne.Paulo Tadeu da Silva - 2004 - Scientiae Studia 2 (2):239-250.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  10
    Copernicanism and realism: towards the unification of astronomy and cosmology.Claudemir Roque Tossato - 2003 - Scientiae Studia 1 (4):553-564.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Copernicus' First Friends: Physical Copernicanism from 1543 to 1610.Katherine A. Tredwell & Peter Barker - 2004 - Filozofski Vestnik 25 (2).
    Between the appearance of Copernicus’ De Revolutionibus in 1543 and the works of Kepler and Galileo that appeared in 1609–10, there were probably no more than a dozen converts to physical heliocentrism. Following Westman we take this list to include Rheticus, Maestlin, Rothmann, Kepler, Bruno, Galileo, Digges, Harriot, de Zúńiga, and Stevin, but we include Gemma Frisius and William Gilbert, and omit Thomas Harriot. In this paper we discuss the reasons this tiny group of true Copernicans give for believing that (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  8.  10
    Descartes and Galileo: Copernicanism and the Metaphysical Foundations of Physics.Michael Friedman - 2007 - In Janet Broughton & John Carriero (eds.), A Companion to Descartes. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 69–83.
    This chapter contains section titled: The Crime of Galileo A Discourse on Method The Metaphysical Foundations of Physics References and Further Reading.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  9.  39
    Galileo: For Copernicanism and for the Church.George V. Coyne - 2003 - Zagadnienia Filozoficzne W Nauce 32.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  46
    Galileo and Descartes on Copernicanism and the cause of the tides.Tad M. Schmaltz - 2015 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 51:70-81.
  11. Science and copernicanism in the works of Bruno-principal orientations of the criticism from 1950 to today.R. Maspero - 1989 - Rivista di Storia Della Filosofia 44 (1):141-162.
  12.  10
    Mersenne and Copernicanism.William L. Hine - 1973 - Isis 64 (1):18-32.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  13.  10
    Philosophic pre-copernicanism.D. L. Murray - 1910 - Mind 19 (74):231-237.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  21
    Philosophic pre-copernicanism-an answer.H. A. Prichard - 1910 - Mind 19 (76):541-543.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  30
    Galileo: For Copernicanism and for the Church. Annibale Fantoli, George V. CoyneGalileo: A Life. James Reston, Jr.Maurice A. Finocchiaro - 1995 - Isis 86 (3):486-488.
  16. Wonder in the face of scientific revolutions: Adam Smith on Newton's ‘Proof’ of Copernicanism 1.Eric Schliesser - 2005 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 13 (4):697-732.
    (2005). Wonder in the face of scientific revolutions: Adam Smith on Newton's ‘Proof’ of Copernicanism. British Journal for the History of Philosophy: Vol. 13, No. 4, pp. 697-732. doi: 10.1080/09608780500293042.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  17.  25
    Annibale Fantoli, Galileo: For Copernicanism and for the Church, translated by George V. Coyne, SJ. Studi Galileiani, 3. Rome: Vatican Observatory Publications, 1994 . First edition: pp. xix+540. ISBN 0-268-01029-3. Second edition, revised and corrected, 1996, pp. xx+567. ISBN 0-268-01032-3. $21.95. Rivka Feldhay, Galileo and the Church: Political Inquisition or Critical Dialogue? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995. Pp. viii+303. ISBN 0-521-34468-8. £35.00, $54.95. [REVIEW]Michael Shank - 1997 - British Journal for the History of Science 30 (1):101-121.
  18.  25
    Rational Magic: Thomas Digges' Sixteenth Century Defense of Copernicanism.Lynn Holt - 2001 - Modern Schoolman 79 (1):23-40.
  19.  43
    Impetus Mechanics as a Physical Argument for Copernicanism Copernicus, Benedetti, Galileo.Michael Wolff - 1987 - Science in Context 1 (2):215-256.
    The ArgumentOne of the earliest arguments for Copernicanism was a widely accepted fact: that on a horizontal plane a body subject to no external resistance can be set in motion by the smallest of all possible forces. This fact was contrary to Aristotelian physics; but it was a physical argument (by abduction) for the possibility of the Copernican world system. For it would be explained if that system was true or at least possible.Galileo argued: only nonviolent motions can be (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  3
    In Defense of the Earth's Centrality and Immobility: Scholastic Reaction to Copernicanism in the Seventeenth Century.Edward Grant - 1984 - Philadelphia: American Philosophical Society.
  21.  42
    Galileo's Steps to Full Copernicanism, and Back.Stillman Drake - 1987 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 18 (1):93.
  22. Annibale Fantoli, "Galileo: For Copernicanism and for the Church". [REVIEW]Richard S. Westfall - 1995 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 33 (3):520.
  23.  8
    Galileo: For Copernicanism and for the Church by Annibale Fantoli; George V. Coyne; Galileo: A Life by James Reston. [REVIEW]Maurice Finocchiaro - 1995 - Isis 86:486-488.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. Twelve essays on the history of copernicanism.Editors Revue de Synthèse - 1973 - Revue de Synthèse 94 (69):149-152.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  64
    How and how not to make predictions with temporal Copernicanism.Kevin Nelson - 2009 - Synthese 166 (1):91-111.
    Gott (Nature 363:315–319, 1993) considers the problem of obtaining a probabilistic prediction for the duration of a process, given the observation that the process is currently underway and began a time t ago. He uses a temporal Copernican principle according to which the observation time can be treated as a random variable with uniform probability density. A simple rule follows: with a 95% probability.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  13
    A Defense of Galileo, the Mathematician from Florence, and: Galileo: For Copernicanism and for the Church.Richard S. Westfall - 1995 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 33 (3):520-521.
  27.  45
    New philosophy and old prejudices: Aspects of the reception of Copernicanism in a divided Europe.Isabelle Pantin - 1999 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 30 (2):237-262.
  28.  33
    Edward Grant. In Defense of the Earth's Centrality and Immobility: Scholastic Reaction to Copernicanism in the Seventeenth Century. Philadelphia: American Philosophical Society 1984. Pp. 69. ISBN 0-87169-744-0. Price $10.00 .Edward Rosen. Copernicus and the Scientific Revolution. Malabar, Florida: Robert E. Krieger Publishing Company, 1984. Pp. 220. ISBN 0-89874-573-X. Price $6.50. [REVIEW]E. J. Aiton - 1986 - British Journal for the History of Science 19 (1):126-127.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  3
    In Defense of the Earth's Centrality and Immobility: Scholastic Reaction to Copernicanism in the Seventeenth Century by Edward Grant. [REVIEW]Bruce Eastwood - 1985 - Isis 76:378-379.
  30. Teleology and Realism in Leibniz's Philosophy of Science.Nabeel Hamid - 2019 - In Vincenzo De Risi (ed.), Leibniz and the Structure of Sciences: Modern Perspectives on the History of Logic, Mathematics, Epistemology. Springer. pp. 271-298.
    This paper argues for an interpretation of Leibniz’s claim that physics requires both mechanical and teleological principles as a view regarding the interpretation of physical theories. Granting that Leibniz’s fundamental ontology remains non-physical, or mentalistic, it argues that teleological principles nevertheless ground a realist commitment about mechanical descriptions of phenomena. The empirical results of the new sciences, according to Leibniz, have genuine truth conditions: there is a fact of the matter about the regularities observed in experience. Taking this stance, however, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31.  34
    Playing with the Ancients: The Cosmology of Gilles Personne de Roberval.Ovidiu Babeş - 2022 - Perspectives on Science 30 (6):950-981.
    This contribution explores Gilles Personne de Roberval’s 1644 Aristarchi Samii de mundi systemate, partibus, & motibus eiusdem, libellus. I focus on the complex circumstances of publication, the intellectual context of the polemics of Copernicanism within the scientific community, as well as the natural philosophy of the treatise. Roberval’s strategy of publication provides a very sophisticated example of authorship in early modern natural philosophy. The strategy lies at the conflux of certain specific motivations. I contextualize these motivations by accounting for (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  84
    Blaski i (pół)cienie Galileusza Annibale Fantolego. [REVIEW]Michał Kokowski - 2003 - Zagadnienia Filozoficzne W Nauce 32:26–44.
    The article presents a critical discussion of Annibale Fantoli's book, Galileo: For Copernicanism and for the Church.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  8
    Rheticus' Accommodation Hermeneutics in Defense of the New Astronomy.Daniel Blanco - 2023 - Scientia et Fides 11 (2):131-147.
    In this contribution, we explore a little-referenced effort of Rheticus in favor of the reception of the astronomy of his teacher Copernicus in the religious circle of his time. This appears in his "Treatise on Sacred Scripture and the Motion of the Earth", a document lost for centuries, and rediscovered by Hooykaas in 1972. Here, we offer an elucidation of the main ideas of Rheticus and suggest – from the comparative study of a concrete case – that he should be (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. Giordano Bruno's Copernican Diagrams.Hilary Gatti - 2004 - Filozofski Vestnik 25 (2).
    The paper considers the Copernicanism of Giordano Bruno (1548–1600) as a central moment of his philosophy of nature, concentrating on his two principal cosmological works, La cena de le ceneri (The Ash Wednesday Supper), written and published in London in 1584, and the Latin De immenso, published in Frankfurt in 1591. The principal characteristic of Bruno’s reading of Copernicus which is underlined is his physical realism, which was particularly complex due to his extension of the still finite Copernican cosmology (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  58
    The View from a Wigner Bubble.Eric G. Cavalcanti - 2021 - Foundations of Physics 51 (2):1-31.
    In a recent no-go theorem [Bong et al., Nature Physics (2020)], we proved that the predictions of unitary quantum mechanics for an extended Wigner’s friend scenario are incompatible with any theory satisfying three metaphysical assumptions, the conjunction of which we call “Local Friendliness”: Absoluteness of Observed Events, Locality and No-Superdeterminism. In this paper (based on an invited talk for the QBism jubilee at the 2019 Växjö conference) I discuss the implications of this theorem for QBism, as seen from the point (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  36. Kant’s ‘Five Ways’: Transcendental Idealism in Context.Murray Miles - 2018 - Dialogue 57 (1):137-161.
    In 1772, Kant outlined the new problem of his critical period in terms of four possible “ways” of understanding the agreement of knowledge with its object. This study expands Kant’s terse descriptions of these ways, examining why he rejected them. Apart from clarifying the historical context in which Kant saw his own achievement (the Fifth Way), the chief benefits of exploring the historical background of Way Two, in particular, are that it (1) explains the puzzling intuitus originarius/intellectus archetypus dichotomy, and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37.  93
    Galileo's theological venture.Ernan McMullin - 2013 - Zygon 48 (1):192-220.
    In this essay, I will lay out first in some detail the exegetical principles implicit in Augustine's treatment of an early apparent conflict between Scripture and the findings of “sense or reason.” Then I will analyze Galileo's two major discussions of the issue, first in his Letter to Castelli, and then in his Letter to the Grand Duchess, touching on Foscarini's ill-fated Letter in between. I will turn then to an internal tension that many commentators have perceived within the exegetic (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  38.  23
    The Primacy of Practical Reason.Sebastian Gardner - 2006 - In Graham Bird (ed.), A Companion to Kant. Malden, MA, USA: Blackwell. pp. 259–274.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Kant's Statement of the Principle of the Primacy of Practical Reason, and its Role in Kant's Moral Theology The Primacy of Practical Reason in the Broader Sense The Primacy of Practical Reason and the Assumption of Freedom: Their Relation The Primacy of Practical Reason in Relation to the Theological Postulates Kant's Argument in “On the Primacy” Other Texts Kant's Copernicanism and the Concept of Practical Cognition in the Context of the Postulates Influence.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  39.  26
    Cause, principle, and unity.Giordano Bruno - 1998 - New York: Cambridge University Press. Edited by Robert de Lucca, Richard J. Blackwell & Giordano Bruno.
    Giordano Bruno's notorious public death in 1600, at the hands of the Inquisition in Rome, marked the transition from Renaissance philosophy to the Scientific Revolution of the seventeenth century. In his philosophical works he addressed such delicate issues as the role of Christ as mediator and the distinction, in human beings, between soul and matter. This volume presents new translations of Cause, Principle and Unity, in which he challenges Aristotelian accounts of causality and spells out the implications of Copernicanism (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  40. El “caso Galileo”, sin final previsible (The “Galileo's case”, no end in sight).Antonio Beltrán Marí - 2005 - Theoria 20 (2):125-141.
    La Iglesia ha dado por zanjado el caso Galileo en más de una ocasion. No obstante, la polémica ha continuado. Aquí se argumenta que las distintas iniciativas de la Iglesia respecto al caso Galileo -la revision de la condena dei copernicanismo a partir de 1820; la utilización de los documentos dei dossier inquisitorial de Galileo a partir de 1850 y la polémica suscitada; el caso Paschini (1942-1965); y las conclusiones de Juan Pablo II en 1992-1993- ponen de manifiesto la misma (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. Cocceius and the Jewish Commentators.Adina M. Yoffie - 2004 - Journal of the History of Ideas 65 (3):393-398.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Cocceius and the Jewish CommentatorsAdina M. YoffieThe case of Johannes Cocceius defies the commonplace that Leiden University (and perhaps post-Reformation, confessionalized Europe in general) turned away from humanist scholarship in the first quarter of the seventeenth century. In 1650 Cocceius (1603-69), a Bremen-born Oriental philology professor at Franeker, joined the Leiden theological faculty and wrote a treatise, Protheoria de ratione interpretandi sive introductio in philologiam sacram (De ratione). He (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  5
    Naturwissenschaft und Religion in den Niederlanden um 1600.Harry A. M. Snelders - 1995 - Berichte Zur Wissenschaftsgeschichte 18 (2):67-78.
    Dutch science flourished in the late sixteenth and in the seventeenth century thanks to the immigration of cartographers, botanists, mathematicians, astronomers and the like from the Southern Netherlands after the Spanish army had captured the city of Antwerp in 1585, and thanks to the religious and the socio‐economic situation of the country. A strong impulse for practical scientific activities started from the Reformation, mainly thanks to its anti‐traditional attitude, which had an anti‐rationalistic tendency. Therefore, in the Northern Netherlands there was (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  40
    The role of probability arguments in the history of science.Friedel Weinert - 2010 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 41 (1):95-104.
    The paper examines Wesley Salmon’s claim that the primary role of plausibility arguments in the history of science is to impose constraints on the prior probability of hypotheses. A detailed look at Copernicanism and Darwinism and, more briefly, Rutherford’s discovery of the atomic nucleus reveals a further and arguably more important role of plausibility arguments. It resides in the consideration of likelihoods, which state how likely a given hypothesis makes a given piece of evidence. In each case the likelihoods (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44. Copernicus, Kant, and the anthropic cosmological principles.Sherrilyn Roush - 2003 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 34 (1):5-35.
    In the last three decades several cosmological principles and styles of reasoning termed 'anthropic' have been introduced into physics research and popular accounts of the universe and human beings' place in it. I discuss the circumstances of 'fine tuning' that have motivated this development, and what is common among the principles. I examine the two primary principles, and find a sharp difference between these 'Weak' and 'Strong' varieties: contrary to the view of the progenitors that all anthropic principles represent a (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  45.  78
    Constructing copernicus.Peter Barker - 2002 - Perspectives on Science 10 (2):208-227.
    : This paper offers my current view of a joint research project, with Bernard R. Goldstein, that examines Kepler's unification of physics and astronomy. As an organizing theme, I describe the extent to which the work of Kepler led to the appearance of the form of Copernicanism that we accept today. In the half century before Kepler's career began, the understanding of Copernicus and his work was significantly different from the modern one. In successive sections I consider the modern (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  46.  70
    Copernican revolutions revisited in Adam Smith by way of David Hume.Eric Schliesser - unknown
    In this paper I revisit Adam Smith’s treatment of Copernicanism and Newtonianism in his essay, “The History of Astronomy” (hereafter: “Astronomy”), in light of a surprisingly ignored context: David Hume. This remark will strike most scholars of Adam Smith as unfounded—David Hume’s philosophy is often invoked as a source of Smith’s approach in the “Astronomy” or as its target. Yet, Hume’s occasional remarks on Copernicanism nor his treatment of the history of science in the History of England (1754-62, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  47.  21
    Gassendi and l'Affaire Galilée of the Laws of Motion.Paolo Galluzzi - 2001 - Science in Context 14 (s1):239-275.
    In the lively discussions on Galileo's laws of motion after the Pisan's death, we observe what might be called a new “Galilean affair.” That is, a trial brought against his new science of motion mainly by French and Italian Jesuits with the substantial adherence of M. Mersenne. This new trail was originated by Gassendi's presentation of Galileo's de motu not simply as a perfectly coherent doctrine, but also as a convincing argument in favor of the truth of Copernicanism.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  48.  15
    El “caso Galileo”, sin final previsible (The “Galileo’s case”, no end in sight).Antonio Beltrán Marí - 2005 - Theoria: Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia 20 (2):125-141.
    La Iglesia ha dado por zanjado el caso Galileo en más de una ocasion. No obstante, la polémica ha continuado. Aquí se argumenta que las distintas iniciativas de la Iglesia respecto al caso Galileo -la revision de la condena dei copernicanismo a partir de 1820; la utilización de los documentos dei dossier inquisitorial de Galileo a partir de 1850 y la polémica suscitada; el caso Paschini (1942-1965); y las conclusiones de Juan Pablo II en 1992-1993- ponen de manifiesto la misma (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  9
    Giordano Bruno: Cause, Principle and Unity: And Essays on Magic.Richard J. Blackwell & Robert de Lucca (eds.) - 1998 - Cambridge University Press.
    Giordano Bruno's notorious public death in 1600, at the hands of the Inquisition in Rome, marked the transition from Renaissance philosophy to the Scientific Revolution of the seventeenth century. In his philosophical works he addressed such delicate issues as the role of Christ as mediator and the distinction, in human beings, between soul and matter. This volume presents new translations of Cause, Principle and Unity, in which he challenges Aristotelian accounts of causality and spells out the implications of Copernicanism (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. Giordano Bruno: Cause, Principle and Unity: And Essays on Magic.Richard J. Blackwell & Robert de Lucca (eds.) - 1998 - Cambridge University Press.
    Giordano Bruno's notorious public death in 1600, at the hands of the Inquisition in Rome, marked the transition from Renaissance philosophy to the Scientific Revolution of the seventeenth century. In his philosophical works he addressed such delicate issues as the role of Christ as mediator and the distinction, in human beings, between soul and matter. This volume presents new translations of Cause, Principle and Unity, in which he challenges Aristotelian accounts of causality and spells out the implications of Copernicanism (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 70