Results for '“believes that …”'

999 found
Order:
  1.  51
    On believing that I am thinking.Tom Stoneham - 1998 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 98 (2):125-44.
    It is argued that a second-order belief to the effect that I now have some particular propositional attitude is always true (Incorrigibility). This is not because we possess an infallible cognitive faculty of introspection, but because that x believes that he himself now has attitude A to proposition P entails that x has A to P. Incorrigibility applies only to second-order beliefs and not to mere linguistic avowals of attitudes. This view combines a necessary asymmetry (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  2. On believing that the scriptures are divinely inspired.Thomas M. Crisp - 2009 - In Oliver D. Crisp & Michael C. Rea (eds.), Analytic Theology: New Essays in the Philosophy of Theology. Oxford Up. pp. 187--213.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  3. On believing that time does not flow, but thinking that it seems to.Kristie Miller, Alex Holcombe & Andrew J. Latham - 2019 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 42.
    Hoerl & McCormack posit two systems – the temporal updating system and the temporal reasoning system – and suggest that they explain an inherent contradiction in people's naïve theory of time. We suggest there is no contradiction. Something does, however, require explanation: the tension between certain sophisticated beliefs about time, and certain phenomenological states or beliefs about those phenomenological states. The temporal updating mechanism posited by H&M may contribute to this tension.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  4. You just believe that because….Roger White - 2010 - Philosophical Perspectives 24 (1):573-615.
    I believe that Tom is the proud father of a baby boy. Why do I think his child is a boy? A natural answer might be that I remember that his name is ‘Owen’ which is usually a boy’s name. Here I’ve given information that might be part of a causal explanation of my believing that Tom’s baby is a boy. I do have such a memory and it is largely what sustains my conviction. But (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   127 citations  
  5.  52
    Does believing that everyone else is less ethical have an impact on work behavior?Thomas Tyson - 1992 - Journal of Business Ethics 11 (9):707 - 717.
    Researchers consistently report that individuals see themselves acting far more ethically than comparable others when confronted with ethically uncertain work-related behaviors. They suggest that this belief encourages unethical conduct and contributes to the degeneration of business ethics; however, they have not specifically investigated the consequences of this belief. If undesirable work behaviors actually do occur, educators and other ethics advocates would be strongly encouraged to dispel this widely held notion.In the present study, data was collected from college students (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  6. I believe that "p"'.Norman Malcolm - 1991 - In Ernest Lepore (ed.), John Searle and His Critics. Cambridge: Blackwell.
  7. If you justifiably believe that you ought to Φ, you ought to Φ.Jonathan Way & Daniel Whiting - 2016 - Philosophical Studies 173 (7):1873-1895.
    In this paper, we claim that, if you justifiably believe that you ought to perform some act, it follows that you ought to perform that act. In the first half, we argue for this claim by reflection on what makes for correct reasoning from beliefs about what you ought to do. In the second half, we consider a number of objections to this argument and its conclusion. In doing so, we arrive at another argument for the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  8.  29
    Believing that You Know and Knowing that You Believe.Sven Bernecker - 2004 - In Richard Schantz (ed.), The Externalist Challenge. De Gruyter. pp. 369-376.
    Sections 1 and 2 examine Hilary Putnam's brain-in-a-vat argument and an analogous argument by Fred Dretske and show that anti-skeptical arguments from semantic externalism presuppose that we can know non-empirically that we possess beliefs and thus aren't zombies. In section 3 I argue that, given semantic externalism, we cannot non-empirically know whether we have beliefs or are zombies. Section 4 spells out the consequences of this position for Putnam's and Dretske's anti-skeptical arguments.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  55
    Believing that one knows.Keith Lehrer - 1970 - Synthese 21 (2):133 - 140.
  10. Knowing That P without Believing That P.Blake Myers-Schulz & Eric Schwitzgebel - 2013 - Noûs 47 (2):371-384.
    Most epistemologists hold that knowledge entails belief. However, proponents of this claim rarely offer a positive argument in support of it. Rather, they tend to treat the view as obvious and assert that there are no convincing counterexamples. We find this strategy to be problematic. We do not find the standard view obvious, and moreover, we think there are cases in which it is intuitively plausible that a subject knows some proposition P without—or at least without determinately—believing (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   98 citations  
  11.  10
    I believe that he didn’t do it and I don’t believe that he did it. The influence of context on the semantic-communicative relations between sentence negation and performative negation.Józef Maciuszek - 2018 - Studies in Logic, Grammar and Rhetoric 54 (1):61-76.
    The subject matter of the paper is an analysis of the semantic relations between sentence negation, performative negation, and declarations in reference to utterances which speech acts theory gives the label of representatives. Apart from linguistic-semantic analyses, empirical studies have been conducted on the manner in which sentence negation and performative negation are processed. The results of Study I demonstrate that the semantic relation between sentence negation and performative negation changes depend on the type of comment (positive vs. negative), (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  36
    Does Aristotle believe that habituation is only for children?Wouter Sanderse - 2020 - Journal of Moral Education 49 (1):98-110.
    Full virtue and practical wisdom comprise the end of neo-Aristotelian moral development, but wisdom cannot be cultivated straight away through arguments and teaching. Wisdom is integrated with, and builds upon, habituation: the acquisition of virtuous character traits through the repeated practice of corresponding virtuous actions. Habit formation equips people with a taste for, and commitment to, the good life; furthermore it provides one with discriminatory and reflective capacities to know how to act in particular circumstances. Unfortunately, habituation is often understood (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  13.  92
    Believing That God Exists Because the Bible Says So.John Lamont - 1996 - Faith and Philosophy 13 (1):121-124.
    The paper considers Renee Descartes’ assertion that believing that God exists because the Bible says so, and believing that what the Bible says is true because God says it, involves circular reasoning. It argues that there is no circularity involved in holding these beliefs, and maintains that the appearance of circularity results from an equivocation. It considers a line of argument that would defend the rationality of holding these beliefs, but does not try to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. On (Not) Believing That God Has Answered a Prayer.Brian Embry - 2017 - Faith and Philosophy (1):132-141.
    Scott Davison has raised an epistemic challenge to the doctrine of petitionary prayer. Roughly, the challenge is that we cannot know or have reason to believe that a prayer has been answered. Davison argues that the epistemic challenge undermines all the extant defenses of petitionary prayer. I argue that it does not.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  20
    I Believe That in America, Whoever Works Hard Will Achieve.Bao Xiaotian - 2002 - Chinese Studies in History 35 (4):42-44.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  61
    Believing that P requires taking it to be the case that P: a reply to Grzankowski and Sankey.James Simpson - 2020 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 24 (1):233-237.
    In a recent paper in this journal, Alex Grzankowski argues, contra Howard Sankey, that to believe that p isn’t to believe that p is true. In this short reply, I’ll agree with Grzankowski that to believe that p isn’t to believe that p is true, and I’ll argue that Sankey’s recent response to Grzankowski is inadequate as it stands. However, it’ll be my contention that Grzankowski’s argument doesn’t demonstrate that believing (...) p doesn’t require taking it to be the case that p. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. Why Einstein did not believe that general relativity geometrizes gravity.Dennis Lehmkuhl - unknown
    I argue that, contrary to folklore, Einstein never really cared for geometrizing the gravitational or the electromagnetic field; indeed, he thought that the very statement that General Relativity geometrizes gravity "is not saying anything at all". Instead, I shall show that Einstein saw the "unification" of inertia and gravity as one of the major achievements of General Relativity. Interestingly, Einstein did not locate this unification in the field equations but in his interpretation of the geodesic equation, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  18. Why a believer could believe that God answers prayers.W. Paul Franks - 2009 - Sophia 48 (3):319-324.
    In a previous issue of this journal Michael Veber argued that God could not answer certain prayers because doing so would be immoral. In this article I attempt to demonstrate that Veber’s argument is simply the logical problem of evil applied to a possible world. Because of this, his argument is susceptible to a Plantinga-style defense.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  19.  58
    Believing that everyone else is less ethical: Implications for work behavior and ethics instruction. [REVIEW]Thomas Tyson - 1990 - Journal of Business Ethics 9 (9):715 - 721.
    Studies consistently report that individuals believe they are far more ethical than co-workers, superiors, or managers in other firms. The present study confirms this finding when comparing undergraduate students' own ethical standards to their perceptions of the standards held by most managers or supervisors. By maintaining a holier than thou ethical perception, new and future managers might rationalize their unethical behavior as being necessary for success in an unethical world. A prisoner's dilemma type problem can be said to exist (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  20. I Falsely Believe That P.Mark Crimmins - 1992 - Analysis 52 (3):191.
    I present a counterexample to the claim that it is never true to say "I falsely believe that so-and-so." .
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  21. “P and I Will Believe that not-P”: Diachronic Constraints on Rational Belief.Luc Bovens - 1995 - Mind 104 (416):737-760.
    I provide a taxonomy of the various circumstances under which one might reasonably say "P and I will believe that not-P" or violate the Reflection Principle.
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  22.  26
    On Believing that God Exists.Kai Nielsen - 1967 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 5 (3):167-172.
  23.  18
    You Just Believe That Because... It’s a Hinge.Annalisa Coliva - 2023 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 47:53-71.
    This paper looks at the genealogical challenge encapsulated in the schema “You just believe that because...” through the lens of hinge epistemology. It is claimed that hinges are typically held just because one has been brought up to believe them. It is further claimed that, while fitting into the YJBTB schema, hinges are rationally held when different de facto hinges are taken for granted merely because of one’s position in history. Moreover, they are rationally held if they (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24.  25
    The modern who believed that he was the ancient: Niccolo Machiavelli in european thought and political imagination.Leonidas Donskis - 2011 - In Niccolò Machiavelli: History, Power, and Virtue. Rodopi. pp. 226--49.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. Is it Reasonable to Believe that Miracles Occur?Alberto Oya - 2019 - Teorema: International Journal of Philosophy 38 (2):39-50.
    Traditionally, miracles have been defined as supernaturally caused events which are outside the scope of scientific explicability. In this paper I will criticize the argument that, when we lack a scientific explanation for an event but it has an adequate explanation in theistic terms, then the most reasonable conclusion is to claim that the event is a miracle. I will defend that this argument would not work unless we had prior independent evidence for God’s existence. Furthermore, I (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26. Compositionality and Believing That.Tony Cheng - 2016 - Linguistic and Philosophical Investigations 15:60-76.
    This paper is about compositionality, belief reports, and related issues. I begin by introducing Putnam’s proposal for understanding compositionality, namely that the sense of a sentence is a function of the sense of its parts and of its logical structure (section 1). Both Church and Sellars think that Putnam’s move is superfluous or unnecessary since there is no relevant puzzle to begin with (section 2). I will urge that Putnam is right in thinking that there is (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  17
    Why do we believe that an atom is colourless? Reflections about the teaching of the particle model.Alessandro Albanese & Matilde Vicentini - 1997 - Science & Education 6 (3):251-261.
  28.  92
    Would you believe that?Joseph Almog - 1984 - Synthese 58 (1):1 - 37.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  29.  59
    Did Einstein Really Believe that Principle Theories are Explanatorily Powerless?Marc Lange - 2014 - Perspectives on Science 22 (4):449-463.
    In a notable article entitled “What is the Theory of Relativity?” written at the request of The Times and published in its November 28, 1919 edition, Albert Einstein famously distinguished “theories of principle” from “constructive theories.” Einstein placed relativity theory among the principle theories. His distinction has recently received increased attention, especially as it relates to scientific explanation. In particular, there has been considerable discussion of how to explain why there obtain the Lorentz transformations as well as of how to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  30. Chapter 20. Believing That I Don’t Know.Richard Foley - 2012 - In When is True Belief Knowledge? Princeton University Press. pp. 99-101.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  6
    Despite my objections I believe that this is an interesting and carefully worked-out book, well worth reading if one's aim is to think clearly about concepts and issues in the area of life and death.Larry May - 1994 - In Peter Singer (ed.), Ethics. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  37
    A note on believing that one knows and Lehrer's proof that knowledge entails belief.Jay E. Harker - 1980 - Philosophical Studies 37 (3):321 - 324.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  33. You ought to ϕ only if you may believe that you ought to ϕ.Benjamin Kiesewetter - 2016 - Philosophical Quarterly 66 (265):760-82.
    In this paper I present an argument for the claim that you ought to do something only if you may believe that you ought to do it. More exactly, I defend the following principle about normative reasons: An agent A has decisive reason to φ only if she also has sufficient reason to believe that she has decisive reason to φ. I argue that this principle follows from the plausible assumption that it must be possible (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  34. Do you believe that aliens feel pain? An empirical investigation of mental state attributions.Gregory Johnson & Alana Knowles - 2023 - Cognition, Brain, Behavior. An Interdisciplinary Journal 27 (2):199-213.
    On what basis do we attribute phenomenal states to others? One answer, defended by John Stuart Mill, appeals to an analogy between ourselves and the similar bodies and actions of others (1865, p. 208). Despite its intuitive plausibility, this position is often rejected (Arico et al., 2011; Buckwalter & Phelan, 2014; Knobe & Prinz, 2008). In line with Mill’s account, we propose that the primary factors used when making phenomenal state ascriptions are the appropriate display of functional and behavioral (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  78
    On knowing (or believing) that one knows (or believes).Hector-Neri Castañeda - 1970 - Synthese 21 (2):187 - 203.
  36.  18
    "This house believes that the state of Israel has the right to exist" -- oxford union debate speech in favour of the.Ted Honderich - manuscript
    What is it to have a moral right to get or to keep something? The answer comes from what is different -- having a legal right. To have a legal right to something is to have the support of the law of the land, positive law, good or bad, in getting or keeping the thing.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. My religion preaches ‘p’, but I don't believe that p: Moore's Paradox in religious assertions.Maciej Tarnowski - forthcoming - Religious Studies.
    In this article, I consider the cases of religious Moorean propositions of the form ‘d, but I don't believe that d’ and ‘d, but I believe that ~d’, where d is a religious dogma, proposition, or part of a creed. I argue that such propositions can be genuinely and rationally asserted and that this fact poses a problem for traditional analysis of religious assertion as an expression of faith and of religious faith as entailing belief. In (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  33
    Moral Agency in Nursing: seeing value In the work and believing that i make a difference.Elizabeth J. Pask - 2003 - Nursing Ethics 10 (2):165-174.
    The subject of this article is moral agency in nursing, studied by the use of an applied philosophical method. It draws upon nurses’ accounts of how they see intrinsic value in their work and believe that they make a difference to patients in terms that leave their patients feeling better. The analysis is based on the philosophy of Iris Murdoch to reveal how nurses’ accounts demonstrated that they hold a view of themselves and their professional practice (...) is intrinsically linked to, and dependent upon, their capacity to see good in the work they do. (shrink)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  39. Just Another Article on Moore’s Paradox, But We Don’t Believe That.Iskra Fileva & Linda A. W. Brakel - 2019 - Synthese 196 (12):5153-5167.
    We present counterexamples to the widespread assumption that Moorean sentences cannot be rationally asserted. We then explain why Moorean assertions of the sort we discuss do not incur the irrationality charge. Our argument involves an appeal to the dual-process theory of the mind and a contrast between the conditions for ascribing beliefs to oneself and the conditions for making assertions about independently existing states of affairs. We conclude by contrasting beliefs of the sort we discuss with the structurally similar (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  40. Religious Dietary Practices and Secular Food Ethics; or, How to Hope that Your Food Choices Make a Difference Even When You Reasonably Believe That They Don't.Andrew Chignell - 2017 - In Anne Barnhill, Mark Budolfson & Tyler Doggett (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Food Ethics. Oxford University Press.
    Religious dietary practices foster a sense of communal identity, certainly, but traditionally they are also regarded as pleasing to God (or the gods, or the ancestors) and spiritually beneficial. In other words, for many religious people, the effects of fasting go well beyond what is immediately observed or empirically measurable, and that is a large part of what motivates participation in the practice. The goal of this chapter is to develop that religious way of thinking into a response (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  41.  23
    Beliefs, make-beliefs, and making believe that beliefs are not make-beliefs.Alberto Voltolini - 2021 - Synthese 199 (1-2):5061-5078.
    In this paper I want to hold, first, that one may suitably reconstruct the relevant kind of mental representational states that fiction typically involves, make-beliefs, as contextually unreal beliefs that, outside fiction, are either matched or non-matched by contextually real beliefs. Yet moreover, I want to claim that the kind of make-believe that may yield the mark of fictionality is not Kendall Walton’s invitation or prescription to imagine. Indeed, in order to appeal in terms of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42.  29
    Three consequences of believing that information lies in global arrays and that perceptual systems use this information.John B. Pittenger - 2001 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 24 (2):236-237.
    Stoffregen & Bardy provide grounds to suppose that specification requires global arrays and that this information is used by perceptual systems. Three conclusions follow from this supposition; (1) global specification will be taken seriously only if additional examples are discovered; (2) research into single-sense information must take global information into account, and (3) ecological psychologists must account for perceptions based upon non-specific information.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  11
    Did Platon (Politeia 571d) Believe That Every One of Us Is a Repressed Cannibal?Cătălin Enache - 2023 - Polis 40 (2):221-233.
    At the beginning of Book 9 of the Politeia (571cd), Platon suggests that all people bear in themselves unlawful desires like the desire to have sex with their own mother or with any other human, god, or beast, the desire to murder anyone, or the desire to eat anything. Modern scholars take it for granted that by the desire to eat anything, Platon means cannibalism. This view is based on the fact that Platon discusses unlawful desires in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  7
    Can We Be Justified in Believing That Humans Are Irrational?Edward Stein - 1997 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57 (3):545-565.
    In this paper, the author considers an argument against the thesis that humans are irrational in the sense that we reason according to principles that differ from those we ought to follow. The argument begins by noting that if humans are irrational, we should not trust the results of our reasoning processes. If we are justified in believing that humans are irrational, then, since this belief results from a reasoning process, we should not accept this (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  45.  87
    Einstein׳s physical strategy, energy conservation, symmetries, and stability: “But Grossmann & I believed that the conservation laws were not satisfied”.J. Brian Pitts - 2016 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 54 (C):52-72.
    Recent work on the history of General Relativity by Renn, Sauer, Janssen et al. shows that Einstein found his field equations partly by a physical strategy including the Newtonian limit, the electromagnetic analogy, and energy conservation. Such themes are similar to those later used by particle physicists. How do Einstein's physical strategy and the particle physics derivations compare? What energy-momentum complex did he use and why? Did Einstein tie conservation to symmetries, and if so, to which? How did his (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  46.  60
    Can we be justified in believing that humans are irrational?Edward Stein - 1997 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57 (3):545-565.
    In this paper, the author considers an argument against the thesis that humans are irrational in the sense that we reason according to principles that differ from those we ought to follow. The argument begins by noting that if humans are irrational, we should not trust the results of our reasoning processes. If we are justified in believing that humans are irrational, then, since this belief results from a reasoning process, we should not accept this (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  47.  47
    Could it have been Reasonable for the Disciples to have Believed that Jesus had Risen from the Dead?Stephen Griffith - 1996 - Journal of Philosophical Research 21:307-319.
    It cannot be reasonable to beIieve in the resurrection unless we can overcome certain a priori objections. It is argued that these objections can in fact be overcome. It is further argued that, whether or not it is reasonabIe for us to believe in the resurrection, it couId have been not onIy reasonabIe for the discipIes to believe that it had, but unreasonabIe for them not to believe this.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  7
    Could it have been Reasonable for the Disciples to have Believed that Jesus had Risen from the Dead?Stephen Griffith - 1996 - Journal of Philosophical Research 21:307-319.
    It cannot be reasonable to beIieve in the resurrection unless we can overcome certain a priori objections. It is argued that these objections can in fact be overcome. It is further argued that, whether or not it is reasonabIe for us to believe in the resurrection, it couId have been not onIy reasonabIe for the discipIes to believe that it had, but unreasonabIe for them not to believe this.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. Debunking The Hellenistic Myth: Why Christians Should Believe That God Is In Time.Alin C. Cucu - 2017 - Piate Pietro 2 (2):16-22.
    In this essay I will try to convince you: (1) that the question of God’s relation to time is of practical relevance for every believer (2) that the idea of God being outside time is a philosophically untenable concept which creates major clashes with Christian doctrine and therefore that every Christian should adopt some temporalist view of God To do that, I will present four arguments against the “outside time” view of God. I then briefly treat (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  16
    When a Person Feels that She Is Guilty and Believes that She Is Not Guilty.Juha Räikkä - 2006 - The Proceedings of the Twenty-First World Congress of Philosophy 9:149-152.
    Guilt feelings are an important part of our emotional life that is relevant to moral philosophy, and guilt feelings raise many theoretically interesting questions. One such question is the problem of how it is possible that sometimes people seem to feel guilty because of an act they have committed even if they believe that the act is not wrong and that it does not have any moral costs. A person raised in a religious family may have (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 999