Results for ' Aristotle, De anima, passive intellect, productive intellect, nature, order, intelligibility, sensory power, phantasìa'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  7
    Order, intelligence and Cosmos’ intelligibility in Aristotle’s De anima (III, 4-5). [REVIEW]Giuseppe Feola - 2016 - Methodos 16.
    Dans mon article, je vais essayer de développer une analyse de deux des plus importants chapitres du De anima d'Aristote : les chapitres 4 et 5 du livre III, où Aristote propose son traitement de la question de l'intellect (Nous). Sans entrer dans les détails de l'histoire de l'interprétation de ce texte, je propose d'identifier l'intellect dit ‘passif’ avec quelques traits distinctifs de la puissance de la phantasia ou imagination, et ce que l'on appelle ‘l'intelligence productive’ avec l'environnement cosmique, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  15
    Ordine, intelligenza e intelligibilità del cosmo nel De anima di Aristotele.Giuseppe Feola - 2016 - Methodos 16.
    Dans mon article, je vais essayer de développer une analyse de deux des plus importants chapitres du De anima d'Aristote : les chapitres 4 et 5 du livre III, où Aristote propose son traitement de la question de l'intellect. Sans entrer dans les détails de l'histoire de l'interprétation de ce texte, je propose d'identifier l'intellect dit ‘passif’ avec quelques traits distinctifs de la puissance de la phantasia ou imagination, et ce que l'on appelle ‘l'intelligence productive’ avec l'environnement cosmique, qui, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  16
    The "thinking of thinking" in.Joseph G. De Filippo - 1995 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 33 (4):543-562.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:The "Thinking of Thinking" in MetaphysicsA.9 JOSEPH G. DE FILIPPO a+~6v &Qa voE[, e~eQ ~o~t ~6 XQ&~O~OV, xetl. I~o~tv ~1VdOloLgvo1]o~t0g v6"qotg. (A.9, 1o74b33-34) Therefore it thinks itself, if indeed it is most powerful, and its thinking is the thinking of thinking. Thus culminates Aristotle's treatment of God's activity in the twelfth book of the Metaphysics. The conclusion seems transparent. God is an intellect (vo~Sg); since he is also the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  7
    The "Thinking of Thinking" in Metaphysics Λ.9.Joseph G. De Filippo - 1995 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 33 (4):543-562.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:The "Thinking of Thinking" in MetaphysicsA.9 JOSEPH G. DE FILIPPO a+~6v &Qa voE[, e~eQ ~o~t ~6 XQ&~O~OV, xetl. I~o~tv ~1VdOloLgvo1]o~t0g v6"qotg. (A.9, 1o74b33-34) Therefore it thinks itself, if indeed it is most powerful, and its thinking is the thinking of thinking. Thus culminates Aristotle's treatment of God's activity in the twelfth book of the Metaphysics. The conclusion seems transparent. God is an intellect (vo~Sg); since he is also the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5.  35
    Aristotle and Neoplatonism in Late Antiquity: Interpretations of the "De Anima" (review).Lloyd P. Gerson - 1998 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 36 (2):315-316.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Aristotle and Neoplatonism in Late Antiquity: Interpretations of the “De Anima.” by H.J. BlumenthalLloyd P. GersonH.J. Blumenthal. Aristotle and Neoplatonism in Late Antiquity: Interpretations of the “De Anima.” Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1996. Pp. x + 244. Cloth, $57.50.The label ‘Neoplatonism’, coined in the eighteenth century to indicate a putative and rather ill-defined development within the Platonic tradition, is to this day applied in sundry ways. Presumably, ‘Neoplatonic’ (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  15
    Mind and World in Aristotle's de Anima.Sean Kelsey - 2021 - New York, NY, USA: Cambridge University Press.
    Why is the human mind able to perceive and understand the truth about reality; that is, why does it seem to be the mind's specific function to know the world? Sean Kelsey argues that both the question itself and the way Aristotle answers it are key to understanding his work De Anima, a systematic philosophical account of the soul and its powers. In this original reading of a familiar but highly compressed text, Kelsey shows how this question underpins Aristotle's inquiry (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  72
    Long commentary on the de Anima of Aristotle. [REVIEW]Kara Richardson - 2010 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 48 (3):398-399.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Long Commentary on theDe Anima of AristotleKara RichardsonAverroes (Ibn Rushd) of Cordoba. Long Commentary on the De Animaof Aristotle. Translated with an introduction and notes by Richard C. Taylor, with Thérèse-Anne Druart, sub-editor. Yale Library of Medieval Philosophy. New Haven-London: Yale University Press, 2009. Pp. cix + 498. Cloth, $85.00.The Andalusian philosopher Ibn Rushd (d. 1198) had two names in the medieval Latin West: 'the Commentator', and 'Averroes'. (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  8
    Sententia super II et III De anima: (Oxford, Bodleian Libr., Lat. misc. c. 70, f. 1ra-25b, Roma, Bibl. naz. V.E. 828, f. 46vb, 48ra-52ra).Bernardo C. Anonymus, Kevin Aristotle, Bazàn & White - 1998 - Paris: Editions Peeters. Edited by Bernardo C. Bazàn, Kevin White & Aristotle.
    Il s'agit du temoin le plus ancien d'un cours portant sur les livres II et III au complet du Traite de l'ame d'Aristote. Le cours, enseigne a la Faculte des Arts d'une Universite difficile a preciser (Paris?), est un exemple paradigmatique de la methode litterale (ce qui a permis de reconstituer la version de la Vetus utilisee par le maitre, que l'on pourra ajouter au dossier de l'Aristoteles Latinus) et un temoin precieux de la premiere reception d'Aristote. Le texte permet (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9. The Unity of Intellect in Aristotle's De Anima.Lloyd Gerson - 2004 - Phronesis 49 (4):348-373.
    Desperately difficult texts inevitably elicit desperate hermeneutical measures. Aristotle's De Anima, book three, chapter five, is evidently one such text. At least since the time of Alexander of Aphrodisias, scholars have felt compelled to draw some remarkable conclusions regarding Aristotle's brief remarks in this passage regarding intellect. One such claim is that in chapter five, Aristotle introduces a second intellect, the so-called 'agent intellect', an intellect distinct from the 'passive intellect', the supposed focus of discussion up until this passage.1 (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  10. Why the Intellect Cannot Have a Bodily Organ: De Anima 3.4.Caleb Cohoe - 2013 - Phronesis 58 (4):347-377.
    I reconstruct Aristotle’s reasons for thinking that the intellect cannot have a bodily organ. I present Aristotle’s account of the aboutness or intentionality of cognitive states, both perceptual and intellectual. On my interpretation, Aristotle’s account is based around the notion of cognitive powers taking on forms in a special preservative way. Based on this account, Aristotle argues that no physical structure could enable a bodily part or combination of bodily parts to produce or determine the full range of forms that (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  11.  49
    Philosophiehistorie als Rezeptionsgeschichte: Die Reaktion auf Aristoteles' De Anima-Noetik: Der fruhe Hellenismus (review).Hendrik Lorenz - 2003 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 41 (1):122-123.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Philosophy 41.1 (2003) 122-123 [Access article in PDF] Andreas Kamp. Philosophiehistorie als Rezeptionsgeschichte. Die Reaktion auf Aristoteles' De Anima-Noetik. Der frühe Hellenismus. Amsterdam: B. R. Grüner, 2001. Pp. viii + 315. Cloth, $82.00. This book is the first installment of an extraordinarily ambitious project. The plan is to investigate the reception of Aristotle's conception of the intellect, set out in De Anima 3.4-5, in (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  18
    A herança Greco-árabe na filosofia de maimônides: Profecia E imaginação.Rosalie Helena de Souza Pereira - 2015 - Kriterion: Journal of Philosophy 56 (131):107-128.
    Para elaborar sua profetologia, Maimônides retoma conceitos relativos às teorias do intelecto de Al-Fārābī e de Avicena, que, por sua vez, se baseiam nas noções sobre a alma de Aristóteles. Dessa perspectiva, a Revelação divina deve ser considerada um fato natural inserido na totalidade da natureza criada por Deus. Compreender a Revelação significa, portanto, compreendê-la a partir do homem, uma vez que o profeta, apesar de se tratar de alguém que se destaca do conjunto da humanidade, é sempre um ser (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13. Nous in Aristotle's De Anima.Caleb Murray Cohoe - 2014 - Philosophy Compass 9 (9):594-604.
    I lay out and examine two sharply conflicting interpretations of Aristotle's claims about nous in the De Anima (DA). On the human separability approach, Aristotle is taken to have identified reasons for thinking that the intellect can, in some way, exist on its own. On the naturalist approach, the soul, including intellectual soul, is inseparable from the body of which it is the form. I discuss how proponents of each approach deal with the key texts from the DA, focusing on (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  14.  43
    Commentary on Aristotle’s de Anima.Thomas Aquinas - 1951 - Yale University Press. Edited by O. P. Kenny & Joseph.
    This new translation of Thomas Aquinas’s most important study of Aristotle casts bright light on the thinking of both philosophers. Using a new text of Aquinas’s original Latin commentary, Robert Pasnau provides a precise translation that will enable students to undertake close philosophical readings. He includes an introduction and notes to set context and clarify difficult points as well as a translation of the medieval Latin version of Aristotle’s _De anima _ so that readers can refer to the text Aquinas (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  15.  8
    Die doppelte Natur des menschlichen Intellekts bei Aristoteles.Christian Jung - 2011 - Königshausen & Neumann.
    Aristotle's theory of intellect is notoriously difficult, due basically to the scarcity of textual evidence. It has therefore always been controversial and often subject to the systematic biases of its interpretators. In order to provide a fresh and objective perspective on the text itself this book offers a detailed study of the fundamental text, Aristotle's De anima III 4-5, by giving an improved Greek text, extensive commentary, and discussion. An examination of several other important Aristotelian passages on the intellect is (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. Touching, thinking, being: The sense of touch in Aristotle's De Anima and its implications.Pascal Massie - 2013 - Minerva - An Internet Journal of Philosophy 17 (1):74-101.
    Aristotle’s treatment of tactility is at odds with the hierarchical order of psyche’s faculties. Touching is the commonest and lowest power; it is possessed by all sentient beings; thinking is, on the contrary, the highest faculty that distinguishes human beings. Yet, while Aristotle maintains against some of his predecessors that to think is not to sense, he nevertheless posits a causal link between practical intelligence and tactility and even describes noetic activity as a certain kind of touch. This essay elucidates (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17. When and Why Understanding Needs Phantasmata: A Moderate Interpretation of Aristotle’s De Memoria and De Anima on the Role of Images in Intellectual Activities.Caleb Cohoe - 2016 - Phronesis: A Journal for Ancient Philosophy 61 (3):337-372.
    I examine the passages where Aristotle maintains that intellectual activity employs φαντάσματα (images) and argue that he requires awareness of the relevant images. This, together with Aristotle’s claims about the universality of understanding, gives us reason to reject the interpretation of Michael Wedin and Victor Caston, on which φαντάσματα serve as the material basis for thinking. I develop a new interpretation by unpacking the comparison Aristotle makes to the role of diagrams in doing geometry. In theoretical understanding of mathematical and (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  18.  21
    Désir, phantasia et intellect dans le de Anima, III, 9-11: Une réplique à Monique canto-Sperber.Jean-Louis Labarrière - forthcoming - Les Etudes Philosophiques.
    Le présent article vise à montrer qu'on ne peut ranger Aristote parmi les « intellectualistes tempérés » que si l'on privilégie la représentation de l'objet désirable par rapport à la faculté motrice elle-même, qui est bien la faculté désirante et elle seule. Si la phantasia semble être finalement la seule faculté cognitive dont on ne saurait se passer pour se mouvoir et agir, c'est parce qu'elle régit la forme de base du mode de présentation du désirable ou bien pratique, qui (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19.  65
    Aristotle, De Anima III.3-5.Seth Benardete - 1975 - Review of Metaphysics 28 (4):611 - 622.
    The physicist defines anger in terms of heart, blood, and heat; the dialectician says it is the desire to inflict pain in retaliation. Both give fairly sure signs for its recognition; but neither can show why these signs must go together and in what they can cohere. Aristotelian physics is presumably a way to avoid such a split, and whatever defects his account of perception or intellection suffers from cannot be traced to it. Phantasia, however, seems to be dialectically distinguished (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  20. Time’s Causal Power: Proclus and the Natural Theology of Time by Antonio Luis Costa Vargas (review).M. Martijn - 2024 - Review of Metaphysics 77 (4):732-734.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Time’s Causal Power: Proclus and the Natural Theology of Time by Antonio Luis Costa VargasM. MartijnVARGAS, Antonio Luis Costa. Time’s Causal Power: Proclus and the Natural Theology of Time. Boston: Brill, 2021. i + 231 pp. Cloth and eBook, $162.00The metaphysics of time in Neoplatonism tends to be described top-down: From transcendent eternity, time as we know it emanates. This is hardly informative about the nature of time (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  26
    Review of Sean Kelsey, Mind and World in Aristotle's De Anima. [REVIEW]Emily Kress - 2023 - Philosophical Review 132 (3):491-4.
    Here is a fact about humans: we use our senses to pick up on things around us and our intellect to understand whatever is out there to be understood. In Mind and World in Aristotle’s De Anima, Kelsey argues that this fact is, in Aristotle’s view, in need of an explanation. He finds one in De Anima 3.8’s suggestion that “intelligence [is] form of forms, and sensibility form of sensibilia” (432a2–3; quoted on p. 2). Roughly, his proposal is that our (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  10
    Avicenna and the issue of intellectual abstraction of intelligibles.Richard Taylor - 2018 - In Margaret Cameron (ed.), Philosophy of Mind in the Early and High Middle Ages: The History of the Philosophy of Mind. New York: Routledge.
    Al-Farabi, Avicenna and Averroes, widely known classical rationalists in the Arabic/Islamic philosophical tradition and strongly infl uential sources for Latin philosophy in the High Middle Ages, all thought themselves to be following Aristotle’s lead regarding the intellectual abstraction of intelligibles in the formation of necessary and unchanging scientific knowledge. For Aristotle it is clear that sensation is a potentiality for apprehending or coming to be individual sensed objects found in the world exterior to the human soul. This takes place by (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23. Why the View of Intellect in De Anima I 4 Isn’t Aristotle’s Own.Caleb Cohoe - 2018 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 26 (2):241-254.
    In De Anima I 4, Aristotle describes the intellect (nous) as a sort of substance, separate and incorruptible. Myles Burnyeat and Lloyd Gerson take this as proof that, for Aristotle, the intellect is a separate eternal entity, not a power belonging to individual humans. Against this reading, I show that this passage does not express Aristotle’s own views, but dialectically examines a reputable position (endoxon) about the intellect that seems to show that it can be subject to change. The passage’s (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  34
    Speculum animae: Richard Rufus on Perception and Cognition.Matthew Etchemendy & Rega Wood - 2011 - Franciscan Studies 69:53-115.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:“Garrulus sum et loquax et expedire nescio. Diu te tenui in istis, sed de cetero procedam.” These are the words of Richard Rufus of Cornwall, a thirteenth-century Scholastic and lecturer at the Universities of Paris and Oxford. Rufus is apologizing to his readers: “I am garrulous and loquacious, and I don’t know how to be efficient. I have detained you with these things a long while, but let me (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  18
    Self-Intellection and its Epistemological Origins in Ancient Greek Thought (review).Scott Carson - 2004 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 42 (4):489-490.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Philosophy 42.4 (2004) 489-490 [Access article in PDF] Ian M. Crystal. Self-Intellection and its Epistemological Origins in Ancient Greek Thought. Aldershot, England: Ashgate Publishing, 2002. Pp. x + 220. Cloth, $79.95. In this excellent re-working of his King's College Ph.D. thesis, Ian Crystal presents an account of the problem of self-intellection in Greek philosophy from Parmenides through Plotinus. The problem, at least as it (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  5
    The Intellect’s Thinking of Itself in Aristotle’s De Anima Ⅲ 4. 오지은 - 2023 - Journal of the New Korean Philosophical Association 114:165-187.
    본고의 목표는 『영혼론』 3권 4장에 언급된 ‘지성의 자기 사유’가 어떤 특징을 지니는지를 선명하게 드러내는 것이다. 이를 위해 먼저 필자는 429b9행이 왜 연구자들 사이에서 논란이 되었는지 소개한 후, 일부 번역서들과 달리 본고는 필사본대로 읽겠다는 계획과 그 이유를 밝힌다. 그런 다음, 『영혼론』 3권 4장에 제시된 두 가지 난제가 왜 난제인지, 그리고 각 난제에 제시된 해법이 어떻게 해법으로 기능하는지 설명한다. 본고는 특히 두 번째 난제와 해법에 초점을 맞춰, 아리스토텔레스가 ‘지성도 사유될 수 있다’는 사실과 ‘현실태인 지성과 현실태인 여타 사유 대상이 인식적으로 동일하다’는 사실을 당연시했음을 (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. Aristotle’s “De Anima”: A Critical Commentary.Ronald M. Polansky - 2007 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Aristotle's De Anima is the first systematic philosophical account of the soul, which serves to explain the functioning of all mortal living things. In his commentary, Ronald Polansky argues that the work is far more structured and systematic than previously supposed. He contends that Aristotle seeks a comprehensive understanding of the soul and its faculties. By closely tracing the unfolding of the many-layered argumentation and the way Aristotle fits his inquiry meticulously within his scheme of the sciences, Polansky answers questions (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  28. "Self-Knowledge and the Science of the Soul in Buridan's Quaestiones De Anima".Susan Brower-Toland - 2017 - In Gyula Klima (ed.), Questions on the soul by John Buridan and others. Berlin, Germany: Springer.
    Buridan holds that the proper subject of psychology (i.e., the science undertaken in Aristotle’s De Anima) is the soul, its powers, and characteristic functions. But, on his view, the science of psychology should not be understood as including the body nor even the soul-body composite as its proper subject. Rather its subject is just “the soul in itself and its powers and functions insofar as they stand on the side of the soul". Buridan takes it as obvious that, even thus (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  5
    Consideraciones sobre la interpretación de Tomás de Aquino acerca de la universalidad de lo justo natural / Reflexions on Thomas Aquinas' Interpretation About the Universality of Natural Law.Fernando M. de Blassi - 2013 - Revista Española de Filosofía Medieval 20:39.
    This paper will study the universality of natural law that Thomas Aquinas explains in Sententia Libri EthicorumV. In the 5th book of the Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle tells the difference between natural law and positive law in the context of politic law. This reference point raises the question about the naturalness of the justice rules within the political society. Especially when it comes to the variability inherent in practical matters. Thomas, by contrast, appeals the first principles recognized by practical intellect in (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30. Aristotle on Phone: De Anima 420B – 421 A.Mostafa Younesie - 2019 - Politeia 1 (1):47-55.
    With regard to the importance and position of phone for thought and language in Aristotle, and his brief account of it in Περὶ Ψυχῆς / De Anima, here I am going to paraphrase his brief mentioning in the chapter eight of the second book of the mentioned treatise. When we read the pertinent section of 4201b - 421a, we see that Aristotle examines it in connection with “hearing” as a sense that is embedded in his wide discussion about “soul”. But (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  51
    Aristotle’s Appropriation of Plato’s Sun Analogy in De Anima.Eli Diamond - 2014 - Apeiron 47 (3):356-389.
    Aristotle’s chapter on productive mind (De Anima III.5) and its comparison of this mind to light are best understood as a careful revision to Plato’s Sun-Good analogy from Republic VI. Through a rigorous juxtaposed reading of De Anima II.7 on vision and III.5 on thinking, one can see how Aristotle is almost wholeheartedly taking up Plato’s analogy between vision and thought. When one accounts for all the detail of Aristotle’s explanation of light and vision in II.7 by seeing that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  12
    Quaestiones super secundum et tertium De anima.John Duns Scotus - 2006 - St. Bonaventure, N.Y.: Franciscan Institute of St. Bonaventure University. Edited by Bernardo C. Bazàn.
    This volume is the fifth and final volume in the Blessed John Duns Scotus Opera philosophica series. It offers readers Scotus' questions on Aristotle's De anima wherein he focuses his attention upon the faculties of sensation, the nature of the intellect, the role of the intelligible species in cognition, and the formal object of the intellect.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33.  44
    The Notion of Intellect in Duns Scotus’ De Spiritualitate et Immortalitate Animae Humanae: An Aristotelian Approach.Athanasia Theodoropoulou - 2015 - In Burçin Ercan (ed.), Interactions in the History of Philosophy II. Delta Publishing House. pp. 39-46.
    This paper offers an interpretative presentation of Duns Scotus’ notion of intellect, as it is delineated in his treatise entitled De Spiritualitate et Immortalitate Animae Humanae. Duns Scotus’ theory is gradually formed through his critical examination of the Aristotelian views which are presented in De Anima and Metaphysics.Duns Scotus accepts the Aristotelian definition of the soul, according to which the soul knows and thinks through its intellective power, and he claims that the intellective soul is the proper form of man. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  8
    Aristotelian Subjectivism: Francisco Suárez’s Philosophy of Perception.Daniel Heider - 2021 - Springer Verlag.
    This monograph presents new material on Francisco Suárez’s comprehensive theory of sense perception. The core theme is perceptual intentionality in Suárez’s theory of the senses, external and internal, as presented in his Commentaria una cum quaestionibus in libros Aristotelis De anima published in 1621. The author targets the question of the multistage genesis of perceptual acts by considering the ontological “items” involved in the procession of sensory information. However, the structural issue is not left aside, and the nature of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35.  25
    Aristotle's de Anima in Focus.Michael Durrant (ed.) - 1993 - New York: Routledge.
    Originally published in 1993. This book presents an amended version of R.D. Hick's classic translation of Aristotle's "De Anima" Books 2 and 3, with pertinent extracts from Book 1, together with an introduction and six papers by prominent international Aristotelian scholars. The editor brings together up-to-date discussions of Aristotle's "De Anima", examining central topics such as the nature of perception, perception and thought, thinking and the intellect, the nature of the soul and the relation between body and soul. These papers (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  36. Kant’s concept of the technique of nature in the Critique of the Power of Judgment: Série 2.Silvia de Bianchi - 2011 - Kant E-Prints 6:12-28.
    a relação entre razão e natureza envolve um dos principais aspectos da crítica da teleologia de Kant. Visando destacar esta relação, investigarei o conceito de técnica da natureza, tal como introduzida na Crítica da faculdade de julgar. De acordo com Kant, a técnica da natureza permite as leis da razão a representarem o acordo dos princípios transcendentais da razão com a natureza. Deste modo, o conceito da técnica da natureza assume um papel prolífico ao expor, através de uma analogia com (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37.  23
    Aristotle on Perception and Perception-like Appearance: De Anima 3.3, 428b10–29a9.Evan Keeling - forthcoming - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie.
    It is now common to explain some of incidental perception’s features by means of a different capacity, called phantasia. Phantasia, usually translated as ‘imagination,’ is thought to explain how incidental perception can be false and representational by being a constitutive part of perception. Through a close reading of De Anima 3.3, 428b10–29a9, I argue against this and for perception first: phantasia is always a product of perception, from which it initially inherits all its characteristics. No feature of perception is explained (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  11
    Human Nature in Early Franciscan Thought: Philosophical Background and Theological Significance by Lydia SCHUMACHER (review).John Marshall Diamond - 2023 - Review of Metaphysics 77 (1):161-162.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Human Nature in Early Franciscan Thought: Philosophical Background and Theological Significance by Lydia SCHUMACHERJohn Marshall DiamondSCHUMACHER, Lydia. Human Nature in Early Franciscan Thought: Philosophical Background and Theological Significance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2023. xiv + 343 pp. Cloth, $120.00Lydia Schumacher’s recent work, Human Nature in Early Franciscan Thought: Philosophical Background and Theological Significance, is a welcome contribution to the study of the development of scholastic thought on the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  54
    Rethinking the Encounter Between Law and Nature in the Anthropocene: From Biopolitical Sovereignty to Wonder.Vito De Lucia - 2020 - Law and Critique 31 (3):329-349.
    The rise of the idea of the Anthropocene is promoting multiple reflections on its meaning. As we consider entering this new geological epoch, we realize the pervasiveness of humankind’s deconstruction and reconstruction of the Earth, in both geophysical and discursive terms. As the body of the Earth is marked and reshaped, so is its idea. From a hostile territory to be subjugated and exploited through sovereign commands, the Earth is now reframed as a vulnerable domain in need of protection. The (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  40.  67
    Delectatio, gaudium, fruitio. Three Kinds of Pleasure for Three Kinds of Knowledge in Thomas Aquinas.Daniel De Haan - 2015 - Quaestio 15:543-552.
    This paper investigates Thomas Aquinas’s threefold division of pleasure into delectatio, gaudium, and fruitio, and its taxonomical basis in his threefold division of knowledge into tactility, the cogitative power, and the intellect. -/- Thomas Aquinas distinguishes three ways in which the sensory and intellectual appetites rest in the good. When the will rests in the intellectually apprehended good, this act is called fruitio; when the concupiscible appetite rests in a good apprehended by the internal senses this passion is called (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  13
    é tão estranho a gente sentir que existe”: Inf'ncia no curta-metragem “Alma.Caroline Trapp de Queiroz - 2022 - Childhood and Philosophy 18:01-19.
    This article aims to present a discussion about childhood from the issues raised by the short film entitled Alma, directed, produced and scripted by the filmmaker André Morais. In the work, we experience a day in the life of a girl who lives with her grandmother and who, throughout the plot, weaves questions about her own existence, the senses of life and the dimensions of the relationships we establish with each other. It is discussed in this article, therefore, the power (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Aristotle’s Intellects: Now and Then.Jonathan Buttaci - 2013 - Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 87:127-143.
    One of the most highly debated passages in Aristotle is his doctrine of the nous poiētikos of de Anima III.5. The interpretations of its precise nature and operation that were given by ancient and medieval commentators abound also today. With few exceptions, however, present-day interpretations disagree with the ancients and others on the logic of the passage. In particular, while most ancient and medieval commentators agree that there are three intellects or intellectual powers on scene in the passage, most contemporary (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  5
    With No Attention Specifically Directed to It, Rhythmic Sound Does Not Automatically Facilitate Visual Task Performance.Jorg De Winne, Paul Devos, Marc Leman & Dick Botteldooren - 2022 - Frontiers in Psychology 13.
    In a century where humans and machines—powered by artificial intelligence or not—increasingly work together, it is of interest to understand human processing of multi-sensory stimuli in relation to attention and working memory. This paper explores whether and when supporting visual information with rhythmic auditory stimuli can optimize multi-sensory information processing. In turn, this can make the interaction between humans or between machines and humans more engaging, rewarding and activating. For this purpose a novel working memory paradigm was developed (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  23
    Aquinas’s Abstractionism.Houston Smit - 2001 - Medieval Philosophy & Theology 10 (1):85-118.
    According to St. Thomas, the natures of material things are the proper objects of human understanding.Thomas claims only that the natures of things are the proper objects of the intellect, not that they are its only objects: he does not deny that we have intellective cognition also of the contingent states and situations of particular material things. And he holds that, at least in this life, humans cognize these natures, not through innate species or by perceiving the divine exemplars, but (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  45. Coming-to-Know as a Way of Coming-to-Be: Aristotle’s De Anima III.5.Michael Baur - 2011 - In Michael Bauer & Robert Wood (eds.), Person, Being, and History: Essays in Honor of Kenneth L. Schmitz. pp. 77-102.
    This chapter argues that it is possible to identify, in the coming to be of knowledge, the three elements that Aristotle says are involved in any kind of coming to be whatsoever (viz., matter, form, and the generated composite object). Specifically, it is argued that in this schema the passive intellect (pathetikos nous) corresponds to the matter, the active intellect (poetikos nous) corresponds to the form, and the composite object corresponds to the mind as actually knowing.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  10
    Aristotele sull’analogia tra le facoltà cognitive degli esseri umani e degli altri animali / Aristotle on the Analogy between the Cognitive Faculties of Human Beings and Other Animals.Giuseppe Feola - 2023 - Aristotelica 4 (4):79-108.
    In _Historia animalium_ VIII 1.588a18 ff., Aristotle describes the cognitive powers of non-human animals as sketches of human cognitive powers. According to the wording he chooses here, the cognitive powers of non-human animals are “traces” or “footprints” (ἴχνη, 588a19) of human ones. In this paper I explore the conceptual framework that lays behind this image, in order to show that it is much more than a rhetorical figure, and that Aristotle’s wording encompasses a whole articulated theory, whose details are set (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  24
    De anima: on the soul. Aristotle & H. Lawson-Tancred - 1987 - Penguin Books.
    Book synopsis: For the Pre-Socratic philosophers the soul was the source of movement and sensation, while for Plato it was the seat of being, metaphysically distinct from the body that it was forced temporarily to inhabit. Plato's student Aristotle was determined to test the truth of both these beliefs against the emerging sciences of logic and biology. His examination of the huge variety of living organisms - the enormous range of their behaviour, their powers and their perceptual sophistication - convinced (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  48.  33
    Aristotle’s Intellects: Now and Then.Jonathan Buttaci - 2013 - Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 87:127-143.
    One of the most highly debated passages in Aristotle is his doctrine of the nous poiētikos of de Anima III.5. The interpretations of its precise nature and operation that were given by ancient and medieval commentators abound also today. With few exceptions, however, present-day interpretations disagree with the ancients and others on the logic of the passage. In particular, while most ancient and medieval commentators agree that there are three intellects or intellectual powers on scene in the passage, most contemporary (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49.  42
    The Powers of Aristotle’s Soul by Thomas Kjeller Johansen.Mary Katrina Krizan - 2014 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 52 (1):162-163.
    In The Powers of Aristotle’s Soul, Thomas Kjeller Johansen offers a fresh treatment of Aristotle’s De Anima, showing that Aristotle can successfully explain the cause of life and activities of living things by appealing to a minimal number of definitionally independent capacities, in much the way that a faculty psychologist would. Johansen situates Aristotle’s account of the soul within the framework of his natural philosophy, arguing that the definitional independence of the soul’s capacities does not conflict with the internal unity (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. Aristotle on the Affective Powers of Colours and Pictures.Elena Cagnoli Fiecconi - 2020 - In Katerina Ierodiakonou (ed.), Colour Psychology in the Graeco-Roman World. pp. 43-80.
    Aristotle’s works on natural science show that he was aware of the affective powers of colour. At De an. 421a13, for example, he writes that hard-eyed animals can only discriminate between frightening and non-frightening colours. In the Nicomachean Ethics, furthermore, colours are the source of pleasures and delight. These pleasures, unlike the pleasures of touch and taste, neither corrupt us nor make us wiser. Aristotle’s views on the affective powers of colours raise a question about the limits he seems to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 1000